University of Pittsburgh



Title: Parasites of the mind. How cultural representations can subvert human interestsAuthorsMaarten Boudry (corresponding author)Ghent University - Department of Philosophy & Moral SciencesSt.-Pietersnieuwstraat 49 - room 2049000 Ghent - Belgium+ 32 473 92 38 75maartenboudry@Steije HofhuisUtrecht University - Department of History and Art HistoryDrift 63512 BS Utrecht, The Netherlandss.t.hofhuis@uu.nlTable of contents TOC \o "1-3" \h \z \u 1Introduction PAGEREF _Toc486506515 \h 42Cultural Evolution PAGEREF _Toc486506516 \h 52.1Human Authorship PAGEREF _Toc486506517 \h 52.2Units of culture PAGEREF _Toc486506518 \h 62.3Millikan’s Challenge PAGEREF _Toc486506519 \h 73Failed Answers to Millikan’s Challenge PAGEREF _Toc486506520 \h 81.Panmemetics PAGEREF _Toc486506521 \h 82.Biologically Maladaptive Culture PAGEREF _Toc486506522 \h 114Doxastic parasites PAGEREF _Toc486506523 \h 134.1Explaining the Appeal of Misbelief PAGEREF _Toc486506524 \h 134.2Case Study: European Witch Persecutions PAGEREF _Toc486506525 \h 155Discussion PAGEREF _Toc486506526 \h 176References PAGEREF _Toc486506527 \h 19Title: Parasites of the mind. How cultural representations can subvert human interestsAbstractAre there any such things as mind viruses? By analogy with biological parasites, such cultural items are supposed to subvert or harm the interests of their host. Most popularly, this notion has been associated with Richard Dawkins’ concept of the “selfish meme”. To unpack this claim, we first clear some conceptual ground around the notions of cultural adaptation and units of culture. We then formulate Millikan’s challenge: how can cultural items (‘memes’ or whatever you want to call them) develop novel purposes of their own, cross-cutting or subverting human purposes? If this central challenge is not met, talk of cultural ‘parasites’ or ‘selfish memes’ will be vacuous or superfluous. First, we discuss why other attempts to answer Millikan’s challenge have failed. In particular, we put to rest the claims of panmemetics, a somewhat sinister worldview according to which human culture is nothing more than a swarm of selfish agents, plotting and scheming behind the scenes. Next, we reject a more reasonable, but still overly permissive approach to mind parasites, which equates them with biologically maladaptive culture. Finally, we present our own answer to Millikan’s challenge: certain systems of misbelief can be fruitfully treated as selfish agents developing novel purposes of their own. In fact, we venture that this is the only way to properly understand them. Systems of misbelief are designed to spread in a viral-like manner, without any regard to the interests of their human hosts, and with possibly harmful consequences. As a proof of concept, we discuss witchcraft beliefs in early modern Europe. In this particular case, treating cultural representations as “parasites” – i.e. adopting the meme’s eye view – promises to shed new light on a mystery that historians and social scientists have been wrestling with for decades. Keywords: mind parasites; cultural adaptation; misbeliefs; meme’s eye view; witch persecutions; maladaptive cultureIntroductionFew ideas are so well applicable to itself, as even its critics might admit, as the notion of a meme. Introduced by Richard Dawkins as a unit of cultural information, a rival replicator to the gene, memes have captured the public imagination, and colonized brains far and wide. But is it a valuable idea, which deserves to be spread? Or is it a vacuous and worthless gambit for churning out pseudo-explanations of culture, a misleading metaphor that has muddled the minds of many enthusiasts and has even fostered a syndrome called “Darwinian paranoia” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Godfrey-Smith</Author><Year>2009</Year><RecNum>765</RecNum><DisplayText>(Godfrey-Smith, 2009)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>765</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1270031717">765</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">819</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Godfrey-Smith, Peter</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Darwinian populations and natural selection</title></titles><pages>VIII, 207</pages><dates><year>2009</year></dates><pub-location>Oxford</pub-location><publisher>Oxford university press</publisher><isbn>9780199552047</isbn><accession-num>001325766</accession-num><call-num>L27.24F512&#xD;G97.430</call-num></record></Cite></EndNote>(Godfrey-Smith, 2009)? In short, is the meme meme itself an annoying mind parasite?Meme enthusiasts have made some ambitious claims on behalf of memes. The science of memetics, as it came to be known, promised to offer a new and unifying theory of culture, superseding traditional conceptions about human agency, intentionality and free will ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Blackmore</Author><Year>2000</Year><RecNum>897</RecNum><DisplayText>(Aunger, 2002; Blackmore, 2000; Lynch, 2008)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>897</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1278342288">897</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">887</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Blackmore, S. J.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The meme machine</title></titles><dates><year>2000</year></dates><pub-location>Oxford</pub-location><publisher>Oxford University Press</publisher></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Aunger</Author><Year>2002</Year><RecNum>2513</RecNum><record><rec-number>2513</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1462582928">2513</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Aunger, Robert</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The electric meme: A new theory of how we think</title></titles><dates><year>2002</year></dates><publisher>Cambridge Univ Press</publisher><isbn>0743201507</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Lynch</Author><Year>2008</Year><RecNum>2512</RecNum><record><rec-number>2512</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1462582905">2512</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Lynch, Aaron</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Thought contagion: How belief spreads through society</title></titles><dates><year>2008</year></dates><publisher>Basic Books</publisher><isbn>0786725648</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Aunger, 2002; Blackmore, 2000; Lynch, 2008). In one slogan, the startling thesis of memetics is: we think we are in control of our thoughts, but they are in control of us. Such overblown pretensions, to put it mildly, have not enhanced the fitness of the meme meme in the academic world, and have made it easy for critics to make short shrift of the whole endeavor. In addition, two implausible notions came to be associated with memes: the idea that culture is composed of discrete units, and that they spread by means of straightforward replication. In this paper, we argue that these contentious points have unfortunately obscured the kernel insight of meme meme. There is no need for a new science of memetics, in the sense of a unifying and overarching theory of culture, which would relate to culture as genetics relates to the living world. Nevertheless, we do need the meme’s eye view ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Dennett</Author><Year>2006</Year><RecNum>481</RecNum><DisplayText>(Dennett, 1995, 2006)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>481</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="0">481</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">562</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dennett, Daniel C.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Breaking the spell: Religion as a natural phenomenon</title></titles><dates><year>2006</year></dates><pub-location>New York, N.Y.</pub-location><publisher>Viking (Penguin)</publisher></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Dennett</Author><Year>1995</Year><RecNum>1854</RecNum><record><rec-number>1854</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1380803252">1854</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dennett, Daniel C.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Darwin&apos;s dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life</title></titles><dates><year>1995</year></dates><pub-location>New York</pub-location><publisher>Simon &amp; Schuster</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Dennett, 1995, 2006), in particular to understand the phenomenon of mind parasites, “selfish” forms of culture that are designed to further their own propagation, even at the expense of their hosts. Adopting the meme’s eye view neither makes you “mind-blind” PEVuZE5vdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5TcGVyYmVyPC9BdXRob3I+PFllYXI+MjAwMDwvWWVhcj48

UmVjTnVtPjkwMjwvUmVjTnVtPjxEaXNwbGF5VGV4dD4oQXRyYW4sIDIwMDI7IEJveWVyLCAxOTk0

OyBTcGVyYmVyLCAyMDAwKTwvRGlzcGxheVRleHQ+PHJlY29yZD48cmVjLW51bWJlcj45MDI8L3Jl

Yy1udW1iZXI+PGZvcmVpZ24ta2V5cz48a2V5IGFwcD0iRU4iIGRiLWlkPSJlczl0dHZzZDFwMnhh

dGV0NWV0cHZleG4wMnc5OXI1czBldGQiIHRpbWVzdGFtcD0iMTI3OTYxMDgzNSI+OTAyPC9rZXk+

PGtleSBhcHA9IkVOV2ViIiBkYi1pZD0iUjdCWWF3cnRtQ1lBQUFLbWZLQSI+ODkyPC9rZXk+PC9m

b3JlaWduLWtleXM+PHJlZi10eXBlIG5hbWU9IkJvb2sgU2VjdGlvbiI+NTwvcmVmLXR5cGU+PGNv

bnRyaWJ1dG9ycz48YXV0aG9ycz48YXV0aG9yPlNwZXJiZXIsIERhbjwvYXV0aG9yPjwvYXV0aG9y

cz48c2Vjb25kYXJ5LWF1dGhvcnM+PGF1dGhvcj5BdW5nZXIsIFJvYmVydDwvYXV0aG9yPjwvc2Vj

b25kYXJ5LWF1dGhvcnM+PC9jb250cmlidXRvcnM+PHRpdGxlcz48dGl0bGU+QW4gb2JqZWN0aW9u

IHRvIHRoZSBtZW1ldGljIGFwcHJvYWNoIHRvIGN1bHR1cmU8L3RpdGxlPjxzZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0

bGU+RGFyd2luaXppbmcgY3VsdHVyZTogVGhlIHN0YXR1cyBvZiBtZW1ldGljcyBhcyBhIHNjaWVu

Y2U8L3NlY29uZGFyeS10aXRsZT48L3RpdGxlcz48cGVyaW9kaWNhbD48ZnVsbC10aXRsZT5EYXJ3

aW5pemluZyBjdWx0dXJlOiB0aGUgc3RhdHVzIG9mIG1lbWV0aWNzIGFzIGEgc2NpZW5jZTwvZnVs

bC10aXRsZT48L3BlcmlvZGljYWw+PHBhZ2VzPjE2My0xNzM8L3BhZ2VzPjxkYXRlcz48eWVhcj4y

MDAwPC95ZWFyPjwvZGF0ZXM+PHB1Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj5PeGZvcmQ8L3B1Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj48cHVi

bGlzaGVyPk94Zm9yZCBVbml2ZXJzaXR5IFByZXNzPC9wdWJsaXNoZXI+PC9yZWNvcmQ+PC9DaXRl

PjxDaXRlPjxBdXRob3I+QXRyYW48L0F1dGhvcj48WWVhcj4yMDAyPC9ZZWFyPjxSZWNOdW0+MTYw

OTwvUmVjTnVtPjxyZWNvcmQ+PHJlYy1udW1iZXI+MTYwOTwvcmVjLW51bWJlcj48Zm9yZWlnbi1r

ZXlzPjxrZXkgYXBwPSJFTiIgZGItaWQ9ImVzOXR0dnNkMXAyeGF0ZXQ1ZXRwdmV4bjAydzk5cjVz

MGV0ZCIgdGltZXN0YW1wPSIxMzgwODAzMjMzIj4xNjA5PC9rZXk+PC9mb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PHJl

Zi10eXBlIG5hbWU9IkJvb2siPjY8L3JlZi10eXBlPjxjb250cmlidXRvcnM+PGF1dGhvcnM+PGF1

dGhvcj5BdHJhbiwgU2NvdHQ8L2F1dGhvcj48L2F1dGhvcnM+PC9jb250cmlidXRvcnM+PHRpdGxl

cz48dGl0bGU+SW4gZ29kcyB3ZSB0cnVzdCA6IHRoZSBldm9sdXRpb25hcnkgbGFuZHNjYXBlIG9m

IHJlbGlnaW9uPC90aXRsZT48c2Vjb25kYXJ5LXRpdGxlPkV2b2x1dGlvbiBhbmQgY29nbml0aW9u

PC9zZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+PHBlcmlvZGljYWw+PGZ1bGwtdGl0bGU+RXZvbHV0

aW9uIGFuZCBjb2duaXRpb248L2Z1bGwtdGl0bGU+PC9wZXJpb2RpY2FsPjxwYWdlcz54dmksIDM0

OCBzLjwvcGFnZXM+PGtleXdvcmRzPjxrZXl3b3JkPkV2b2x1dGlvbiAoYmlvbG9naSkgcmVsaWdp

w7ZzYSBhc3Bla3Rlcjwva2V5d29yZD48a2V5d29yZD5Tb2Npb2Jpb2xvZ2kgcmVsaWdpw7ZzYSBh

c3Bla3Rlcjwva2V5d29yZD48a2V5d29yZD5Qc3ljaG9sb2d5LCBSZWxpZ2lvdXMuPC9rZXl3b3Jk

PjxrZXl3b3JkPkdlbmV0aWMgcHN5Y2hvbG9neS48L2tleXdvcmQ+PGtleXdvcmQ+RXZvbHV0aW9u

IChCaW9sb2d5KSDCoSBSZWxpZ2lvdXMgYXNwZWN0czwva2V5d29yZD48L2tleXdvcmRzPjxkYXRl

cz48eWVhcj4yMDAyPC95ZWFyPjwvZGF0ZXM+PHB1Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj5OZXcgWW9yazwvcHViLWxv

Y2F0aW9uPjxwdWJsaXNoZXI+T3hmb3JkIFVuaXZlcnNpdHkgUHJlc3M8L3B1Ymxpc2hlcj48aXNi

bj4wMTk1MTc4MDMzIChoZnQuKSYjeEQ7MDE5NTE0OTMwMDwvaXNibj48YWNjZXNzaW9uLW51bT4w

MDEzODIyODA8L2FjY2Vzc2lvbi1udW0+PGNhbGwtbnVtPkwxMy5SQTEyLjQwJiN4RDtMMjcuMTBB

ODAwPC9jYWxsLW51bT48L3JlY29yZD48L0NpdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5Cb3llcjwvQXV0aG9y

PjxZZWFyPjE5OTQ8L1llYXI+PFJlY051bT40NTY8L1JlY051bT48cmVjb3JkPjxyZWMtbnVtYmVy

PjQ1NjwvcmVjLW51bWJlcj48Zm9yZWlnbi1rZXlzPjxrZXkgYXBwPSJFTiIgZGItaWQ9ImVzOXR0

dnNkMXAyeGF0ZXQ1ZXRwdmV4bjAydzk5cjVzMGV0ZCIgdGltZXN0YW1wPSIwIj40NTY8L2tleT48

a2V5IGFwcD0iRU5XZWIiIGRiLWlkPSJSN0JZYXdydG1DWUFBQUttZktBIj41Mzk8L2tleT48L2Zv

cmVpZ24ta2V5cz48cmVmLXR5cGUgbmFtZT0iQm9vayI+NjwvcmVmLXR5cGU+PGNvbnRyaWJ1dG9y

cz48YXV0aG9ycz48YXV0aG9yPkJveWVyLCBQYXNjYWw8L2F1dGhvcj48L2F1dGhvcnM+PC9jb250

cmlidXRvcnM+PHRpdGxlcz48dGl0bGU+VGhlIG5hdHVyYWxuZXNzIG9mIHJlbGlnaW91cyBpZGVh

cyA6IEEgY29nbml0aXZlIHRoZW9yeSBvZiByZWxpZ2lvbjwvdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+PHBhZ2Vz

PlhWLCAzMjQ8L3BhZ2VzPjxkYXRlcz48eWVhcj4xOTk0PC95ZWFyPjwvZGF0ZXM+PHB1Yi1sb2Nh

dGlvbj5CZXJrZWxleSAoQ2FsaWYuKTwvcHViLWxvY2F0aW9uPjxwdWJsaXNoZXI+VW5pdmVyc2l0

eSBvZiBDYWxpZm9ybmlhIFByZXNzPC9wdWJsaXNoZXI+PGlzYm4+MDUyMDA3NTU5NTwvaXNibj48

YWNjZXNzaW9uLW51bT4wMDA0MTk3NzU8L2FjY2Vzc2lvbi1udW0+PGNhbGwtbnVtPkwyNy4yOEU3

MDI8L2NhbGwtbnVtPjwvcmVjb3JkPjwvQ2l0ZT48L0VuZE5vdGU+

ADDIN EN.CITE PEVuZE5vdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5TcGVyYmVyPC9BdXRob3I+PFllYXI+MjAwMDwvWWVhcj48

UmVjTnVtPjkwMjwvUmVjTnVtPjxEaXNwbGF5VGV4dD4oQXRyYW4sIDIwMDI7IEJveWVyLCAxOTk0

OyBTcGVyYmVyLCAyMDAwKTwvRGlzcGxheVRleHQ+PHJlY29yZD48cmVjLW51bWJlcj45MDI8L3Jl

Yy1udW1iZXI+PGZvcmVpZ24ta2V5cz48a2V5IGFwcD0iRU4iIGRiLWlkPSJlczl0dHZzZDFwMnhh

dGV0NWV0cHZleG4wMnc5OXI1czBldGQiIHRpbWVzdGFtcD0iMTI3OTYxMDgzNSI+OTAyPC9rZXk+

PGtleSBhcHA9IkVOV2ViIiBkYi1pZD0iUjdCWWF3cnRtQ1lBQUFLbWZLQSI+ODkyPC9rZXk+PC9m

b3JlaWduLWtleXM+PHJlZi10eXBlIG5hbWU9IkJvb2sgU2VjdGlvbiI+NTwvcmVmLXR5cGU+PGNv

bnRyaWJ1dG9ycz48YXV0aG9ycz48YXV0aG9yPlNwZXJiZXIsIERhbjwvYXV0aG9yPjwvYXV0aG9y

cz48c2Vjb25kYXJ5LWF1dGhvcnM+PGF1dGhvcj5BdW5nZXIsIFJvYmVydDwvYXV0aG9yPjwvc2Vj

b25kYXJ5LWF1dGhvcnM+PC9jb250cmlidXRvcnM+PHRpdGxlcz48dGl0bGU+QW4gb2JqZWN0aW9u

IHRvIHRoZSBtZW1ldGljIGFwcHJvYWNoIHRvIGN1bHR1cmU8L3RpdGxlPjxzZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0

bGU+RGFyd2luaXppbmcgY3VsdHVyZTogVGhlIHN0YXR1cyBvZiBtZW1ldGljcyBhcyBhIHNjaWVu

Y2U8L3NlY29uZGFyeS10aXRsZT48L3RpdGxlcz48cGVyaW9kaWNhbD48ZnVsbC10aXRsZT5EYXJ3

aW5pemluZyBjdWx0dXJlOiB0aGUgc3RhdHVzIG9mIG1lbWV0aWNzIGFzIGEgc2NpZW5jZTwvZnVs

bC10aXRsZT48L3BlcmlvZGljYWw+PHBhZ2VzPjE2My0xNzM8L3BhZ2VzPjxkYXRlcz48eWVhcj4y

MDAwPC95ZWFyPjwvZGF0ZXM+PHB1Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj5PeGZvcmQ8L3B1Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj48cHVi

bGlzaGVyPk94Zm9yZCBVbml2ZXJzaXR5IFByZXNzPC9wdWJsaXNoZXI+PC9yZWNvcmQ+PC9DaXRl

PjxDaXRlPjxBdXRob3I+QXRyYW48L0F1dGhvcj48WWVhcj4yMDAyPC9ZZWFyPjxSZWNOdW0+MTYw

OTwvUmVjTnVtPjxyZWNvcmQ+PHJlYy1udW1iZXI+MTYwOTwvcmVjLW51bWJlcj48Zm9yZWlnbi1r

ZXlzPjxrZXkgYXBwPSJFTiIgZGItaWQ9ImVzOXR0dnNkMXAyeGF0ZXQ1ZXRwdmV4bjAydzk5cjVz

MGV0ZCIgdGltZXN0YW1wPSIxMzgwODAzMjMzIj4xNjA5PC9rZXk+PC9mb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PHJl

Zi10eXBlIG5hbWU9IkJvb2siPjY8L3JlZi10eXBlPjxjb250cmlidXRvcnM+PGF1dGhvcnM+PGF1

dGhvcj5BdHJhbiwgU2NvdHQ8L2F1dGhvcj48L2F1dGhvcnM+PC9jb250cmlidXRvcnM+PHRpdGxl

cz48dGl0bGU+SW4gZ29kcyB3ZSB0cnVzdCA6IHRoZSBldm9sdXRpb25hcnkgbGFuZHNjYXBlIG9m

IHJlbGlnaW9uPC90aXRsZT48c2Vjb25kYXJ5LXRpdGxlPkV2b2x1dGlvbiBhbmQgY29nbml0aW9u

PC9zZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+PHBlcmlvZGljYWw+PGZ1bGwtdGl0bGU+RXZvbHV0

aW9uIGFuZCBjb2duaXRpb248L2Z1bGwtdGl0bGU+PC9wZXJpb2RpY2FsPjxwYWdlcz54dmksIDM0

OCBzLjwvcGFnZXM+PGtleXdvcmRzPjxrZXl3b3JkPkV2b2x1dGlvbiAoYmlvbG9naSkgcmVsaWdp

w7ZzYSBhc3Bla3Rlcjwva2V5d29yZD48a2V5d29yZD5Tb2Npb2Jpb2xvZ2kgcmVsaWdpw7ZzYSBh

c3Bla3Rlcjwva2V5d29yZD48a2V5d29yZD5Qc3ljaG9sb2d5LCBSZWxpZ2lvdXMuPC9rZXl3b3Jk

PjxrZXl3b3JkPkdlbmV0aWMgcHN5Y2hvbG9neS48L2tleXdvcmQ+PGtleXdvcmQ+RXZvbHV0aW9u

IChCaW9sb2d5KSDCoSBSZWxpZ2lvdXMgYXNwZWN0czwva2V5d29yZD48L2tleXdvcmRzPjxkYXRl

cz48eWVhcj4yMDAyPC95ZWFyPjwvZGF0ZXM+PHB1Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj5OZXcgWW9yazwvcHViLWxv

Y2F0aW9uPjxwdWJsaXNoZXI+T3hmb3JkIFVuaXZlcnNpdHkgUHJlc3M8L3B1Ymxpc2hlcj48aXNi

bj4wMTk1MTc4MDMzIChoZnQuKSYjeEQ7MDE5NTE0OTMwMDwvaXNibj48YWNjZXNzaW9uLW51bT4w

MDEzODIyODA8L2FjY2Vzc2lvbi1udW0+PGNhbGwtbnVtPkwxMy5SQTEyLjQwJiN4RDtMMjcuMTBB

ODAwPC9jYWxsLW51bT48L3JlY29yZD48L0NpdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5Cb3llcjwvQXV0aG9y

PjxZZWFyPjE5OTQ8L1llYXI+PFJlY051bT40NTY8L1JlY051bT48cmVjb3JkPjxyZWMtbnVtYmVy

PjQ1NjwvcmVjLW51bWJlcj48Zm9yZWlnbi1rZXlzPjxrZXkgYXBwPSJFTiIgZGItaWQ9ImVzOXR0

dnNkMXAyeGF0ZXQ1ZXRwdmV4bjAydzk5cjVzMGV0ZCIgdGltZXN0YW1wPSIwIj40NTY8L2tleT48

a2V5IGFwcD0iRU5XZWIiIGRiLWlkPSJSN0JZYXdydG1DWUFBQUttZktBIj41Mzk8L2tleT48L2Zv

cmVpZ24ta2V5cz48cmVmLXR5cGUgbmFtZT0iQm9vayI+NjwvcmVmLXR5cGU+PGNvbnRyaWJ1dG9y

cz48YXV0aG9ycz48YXV0aG9yPkJveWVyLCBQYXNjYWw8L2F1dGhvcj48L2F1dGhvcnM+PC9jb250

cmlidXRvcnM+PHRpdGxlcz48dGl0bGU+VGhlIG5hdHVyYWxuZXNzIG9mIHJlbGlnaW91cyBpZGVh

cyA6IEEgY29nbml0aXZlIHRoZW9yeSBvZiByZWxpZ2lvbjwvdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+PHBhZ2Vz

PlhWLCAzMjQ8L3BhZ2VzPjxkYXRlcz48eWVhcj4xOTk0PC95ZWFyPjwvZGF0ZXM+PHB1Yi1sb2Nh

dGlvbj5CZXJrZWxleSAoQ2FsaWYuKTwvcHViLWxvY2F0aW9uPjxwdWJsaXNoZXI+VW5pdmVyc2l0

eSBvZiBDYWxpZm9ybmlhIFByZXNzPC9wdWJsaXNoZXI+PGlzYm4+MDUyMDA3NTU5NTwvaXNibj48

YWNjZXNzaW9uLW51bT4wMDA0MTk3NzU8L2FjY2Vzc2lvbi1udW0+PGNhbGwtbnVtPkwyNy4yOEU3

MDI8L2NhbGwtbnVtPjwvcmVjb3JkPjwvQ2l0ZT48L0VuZE5vdGU+

ADDIN EN.CITE.DATA (Atran, 2002; Boyer, 1994; Sperber, 2000), nor is it wedded to the thesis of simple replication or particularism. On the contrary, it draws our attention to patterns that are often missed in traditional approaches to culture, even in sophisticated theories of cultural evolution ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Henrich</Author><Year>2015</Year><RecNum>2494</RecNum><DisplayText>(Henrich, 2015; Norenzayan et al., 2014)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2494</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1460665969">2494</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Henrich, Joseph</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The secret of our success: How culture is driving human evolution, domesticating our species, and making us smarter</title></titles><dates><year>2015</year></dates><publisher>Princeton University Press</publisher><isbn>1400873290</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Norenzayan</Author><Year>2014</Year><RecNum>2532</RecNum><record><rec-number>2532</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1463606618">2532</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Norenzayan, Ara</author><author>Shariff, Azim F</author><author>Gervais, Will M</author><author>Willard, Aiyana K</author><author>McNamara, Rita A</author><author>Slingerland, Edward</author><author>Henrich, Joseph</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The cultural evolution of prosocial religions</title><secondary-title>Behavioral and Brain Sciences</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>Behavioral and Brain Sciences</full-title><abbr-1>Behav. Brain Sci.</abbr-1><abbr-2>Behav Brain Sci</abbr-2><abbr-3>Behavioral &amp; Brain Sciences</abbr-3></periodical><pages>86</pages><volume>1</volume><dates><year>2014</year></dates></record></Cite></EndNote>(Henrich, 2015; Norenzayan et al., 2014). Most scholars of cultural evolution have ignored the meme’s eye view, and those who have taken it seriously have often been too careless or permissive in applying it. Because the metaphor of selfish memes is so vivid and captivating, it is easy to get carried away. With a bit of creativity, one can see memes plotting and scheming everywhere. To clear the ground, we dismiss the claims of panmemetics, and clarify the role of human agency in replicator talk, drawing instructive analogies with artificial selection in the living world. Next, we clear up some confusion regarding the concept of maladaptive/viral/rogue culture. It is important, or so we argue, to dissociate what is ‘biologically maladaptive’ (i.e. harmful to biological fitness) from what is ‘deleterious’ (i.e. harmful to individual agents). Along the way, we take on specific challenges raised by some of the more thoughtful critics of memetics (Millikan, Pinker, Lewens, Sperber). Most centrally, we deal with Millikan’s challenge: how can cultural representations introduce novel purposes in the world, cross-cutting our own? And how would this relate to assumptions about human agency and intentionality? In the end, we argue that the selfish meme metaphor gains most traction when we are dealing with genuine mind viruses, parasitical forms of culture that undermine the interests of their hosts. After discussing two overly permissive answers to Millikan’s challenge (panmemetics and biologically maladaptive culture) we then present our own, more stringent approach. In particular, we argue that systems of misbelief (doxastic parasites) can evolve to subvert the interests of their hosts, To understand how systems of misbeliefs evolve, we have to treat them as parasites with their own purposes and strategies. In other words, we should adopt the meme’s eye view. We illustrate these points with the example of European witch-hunts, which remains an unresolved theoretical puzzle to this day. Before we start, we would like to point out that we are not particularly hung up on the controversial term “meme”, which some would argue carries with it too much unwanted ballast, and can therefore be a source of distraction (see our terminological discussion in REF _Ref486417835 \r \h 2.2 and our concluding remarks). We will use it mainly for the sake of expository convenience, because it is a short and elegant term, and also because Richard Dawkins was indeed one of the first to draw our attention to the possibility of selfish or parasitical culture. In principle, however, we could spell out our whole argument solely in terms of “cultural parasites” (even though that would make the presentation more cumbersome). Cultural EvolutionHuman AuthorshipNobody disputes that culture evolves, in the sense that it changes over time and forms something resembling lineages. But does that mean that Darwinian explanations, in terms of variation and selection, can be fruitfully applied to the cultural domain? Many scholars have argued that, even though cultural systems obviously display functional complexity, the origin of all that design work is hardly a mystery: it’s just us. Biological adaptations are the result of blind evolution, but cultural adaptations are the products of intelligent design. Cultural design emerges, as Pinker ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite ExcludeAuth="1"><Author>Pinker</Author><Year>1997</Year><RecNum>1077</RecNum><Pages>209</Pages><DisplayText>(1997, p. 209)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1077</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1289215178">1077</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">1006</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Pinker, Steven</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>How the mind works</title></titles><pages>xii, 660 p.</pages><keywords><keyword>Cognitive neuroscience.</keyword><keyword>Neuropsychology.</keyword><keyword>Natural selection.</keyword><keyword>Human evolution.</keyword><keyword>Psychology.</keyword></keywords><dates><year>1997</year></dates><pub-location>New York</pub-location><publisher>Norton</publisher><isbn>0393045358</isbn><accession-num>1178888</accession-num><call-num>Jefferson or Adams Building Reading Rooms QP360.5; .P56 1997</call-num></record></Cite></EndNote>(1997, p. 209) wrote, when someone “knuckles down, racks his brain, musters his ingenuity, and composes or writes or paints or invents something”. However, researchers in the burgeoning field of cultural evolution have convincingly argued that plenty of adaptive design in cultural systems is “unauthored”, in the sense that it cannot be credited to the foresighted work of specific intelligent designers PEVuZE5vdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5IZW5yaWNoPC9BdXRob3I+PFllYXI+MjAxNTwvWWVhcj48

UmVjTnVtPjI0OTQ8L1JlY051bT48RGlzcGxheVRleHQ+KEJveWQgJmFtcDsgUmljaGVyc29uLCAy

MDA1OyBIZW5yaWNoLCAyMDE1OyBNZXNvdWRpLCBXaGl0ZW4sICZhbXA7IExhbGFuZCwgMjAwNjsg

UmljaGVyc29uICZhbXA7IEJveWQsIDIwMDU7IFdpbHNvbiwgMjAwMyk8L0Rpc3BsYXlUZXh0Pjxy

ZWNvcmQ+PHJlYy1udW1iZXI+MjQ5NDwvcmVjLW51bWJlcj48Zm9yZWlnbi1rZXlzPjxrZXkgYXBw

PSJFTiIgZGItaWQ9ImVzOXR0dnNkMXAyeGF0ZXQ1ZXRwdmV4bjAydzk5cjVzMGV0ZCIgdGltZXN0

YW1wPSIxNDYwNjY1OTY5Ij4yNDk0PC9rZXk+PC9mb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PHJlZi10eXBlIG5hbWU9

IkJvb2siPjY8L3JlZi10eXBlPjxjb250cmlidXRvcnM+PGF1dGhvcnM+PGF1dGhvcj5IZW5yaWNo

LCBKb3NlcGg8L2F1dGhvcj48L2F1dGhvcnM+PC9jb250cmlidXRvcnM+PHRpdGxlcz48dGl0bGU+

VGhlIHNlY3JldCBvZiBvdXIgc3VjY2VzczogSG93IGN1bHR1cmUgaXMgZHJpdmluZyBodW1hbiBl

dm9sdXRpb24sIGRvbWVzdGljYXRpbmcgb3VyIHNwZWNpZXMsIGFuZCBtYWtpbmcgdXMgc21hcnRl

cjwvdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+PGRhdGVzPjx5ZWFyPjIwMTU8L3llYXI+PC9kYXRlcz48cHVibGlz

aGVyPlByaW5jZXRvbiBVbml2ZXJzaXR5IFByZXNzPC9wdWJsaXNoZXI+PGlzYm4+MTQwMDg3MzI5

MDwvaXNibj48L3JlY29yZD48L0NpdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5NZXNvdWRpPC9BdXRob3I+PFll

YXI+MjAwNjwvWWVhcj48UmVjTnVtPjI1MTg8L1JlY051bT48cmVjb3JkPjxyZWMtbnVtYmVyPjI1

MTg8L3JlYy1udW1iZXI+PGZvcmVpZ24ta2V5cz48a2V5IGFwcD0iRU4iIGRiLWlkPSJlczl0dHZz

ZDFwMnhhdGV0NWV0cHZleG4wMnc5OXI1czBldGQiIHRpbWVzdGFtcD0iMTQ2MzAwNDgwNSI+MjUx

ODwva2V5PjwvZm9yZWlnbi1rZXlzPjxyZWYtdHlwZSBuYW1lPSJKb3VybmFsIEFydGljbGUiPjE3

PC9yZWYtdHlwZT48Y29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjxhdXRob3JzPjxhdXRob3I+TWVzb3VkaSwgQWxleDwv

YXV0aG9yPjxhdXRob3I+V2hpdGVuLCBBbmRyZXc8L2F1dGhvcj48YXV0aG9yPkxhbGFuZCwgS2V2

aW4gTjwvYXV0aG9yPjwvYXV0aG9ycz48L2NvbnRyaWJ1dG9ycz48dGl0bGVzPjx0aXRsZT5Ub3dh

cmRzIGEgdW5pZmllZCBzY2llbmNlIG9mIGN1bHR1cmFsIGV2b2x1dGlvbjwvdGl0bGU+PHNlY29u

ZGFyeS10aXRsZT5CZWhhdmlvcmFsIGFuZCBCcmFpbiBTY2llbmNlczwvc2Vjb25kYXJ5LXRpdGxl

PjwvdGl0bGVzPjxwZXJpb2RpY2FsPjxmdWxsLXRpdGxlPkJlaGF2aW9yYWwgYW5kIEJyYWluIFNj

aWVuY2VzPC9mdWxsLXRpdGxlPjxhYmJyLTE+QmVoYXYuIEJyYWluIFNjaS48L2FiYnItMT48YWJi

ci0yPkJlaGF2IEJyYWluIFNjaTwvYWJici0yPjxhYmJyLTM+QmVoYXZpb3JhbCAmYW1wOyBCcmFp

biBTY2llbmNlczwvYWJici0zPjwvcGVyaW9kaWNhbD48cGFnZXM+MzI5LTM0NzwvcGFnZXM+PHZv

bHVtZT4yOTwvdm9sdW1lPjxudW1iZXI+MDQ8L251bWJlcj48ZGF0ZXM+PHllYXI+MjAwNjwveWVh

cj48L2RhdGVzPjxpc2JuPjE0NjktMTgyNTwvaXNibj48L3JlY29yZD48L0NpdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1

dGhvcj5SaWNoZXJzb248L0F1dGhvcj48WWVhcj4yMDA1PC9ZZWFyPjxSZWNOdW0+NzMwPC9SZWNO

dW0+PHJlY29yZD48cmVjLW51bWJlcj43MzA8L3JlYy1udW1iZXI+PGZvcmVpZ24ta2V5cz48a2V5

IGFwcD0iRU4iIGRiLWlkPSJlczl0dHZzZDFwMnhhdGV0NWV0cHZleG4wMnc5OXI1czBldGQiIHRp

bWVzdGFtcD0iMTI2ODc1NzM3OSI+NzMwPC9rZXk+PGtleSBhcHA9IkVOV2ViIiBkYi1pZD0iUjdC

WWF3cnRtQ1lBQUFLbWZLQSI+Nzk5PC9rZXk+PC9mb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PHJlZi10eXBlIG5hbWU9

IkJvb2siPjY8L3JlZi10eXBlPjxjb250cmlidXRvcnM+PGF1dGhvcnM+PGF1dGhvcj5SaWNoZXJz

b24sIFBldGVyIEouPC9hdXRob3I+PGF1dGhvcj5Cb3lkLCBSb2JlcnQ8L2F1dGhvcj48L2F1dGhv

cnM+PC9jb250cmlidXRvcnM+PHRpdGxlcz48dGl0bGU+Tm90IGJ5IGdlbmVzIGFsb25lOiBIb3cg

Y3VsdHVyZSB0cmFuc2Zvcm1lZCBodW1hbiBldm9sdXRpb248L3RpdGxlPjwvdGl0bGVzPjxwYWdl

cz5JWCwgMzMyPC9wYWdlcz48ZGF0ZXM+PHllYXI+MjAwNTwveWVhcj48L2RhdGVzPjxwdWItbG9j

YXRpb24+Q2hpY2FnbyAoSWxsLik8L3B1Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj48cHVibGlzaGVyPlVuaXZlcnNpdHkg

b2YgQ2hpY2FnbyBwcmVzczwvcHVibGlzaGVyPjxpc2JuPjAyMjY3MTI4NDI8L2lzYm4+PGFjY2Vz

c2lvbi1udW0+MDAwODU5NTAzPC9hY2Nlc3Npb24tbnVtPjxjYWxsLW51bT5QUzA0LkFSQ0hJRUYu

MkdBMDg2JiN4RDtMNjdCLkQzMTQ8L2NhbGwtbnVtPjwvcmVjb3JkPjwvQ2l0ZT48Q2l0ZT48QXV0

aG9yPkJveWQ8L0F1dGhvcj48WWVhcj4yMDA1PC9ZZWFyPjxSZWNOdW0+MTY5NzwvUmVjTnVtPjxy

ZWNvcmQ+PHJlYy1udW1iZXI+MTY5NzwvcmVjLW51bWJlcj48Zm9yZWlnbi1rZXlzPjxrZXkgYXBw

PSJFTiIgZGItaWQ9ImVzOXR0dnNkMXAyeGF0ZXQ1ZXRwdmV4bjAydzk5cjVzMGV0ZCIgdGltZXN0

YW1wPSIxMzgwODAzMjQwIj4xNjk3PC9rZXk+PC9mb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PHJlZi10eXBlIG5hbWU9

IkJvb2siPjY8L3JlZi10eXBlPjxjb250cmlidXRvcnM+PGF1dGhvcnM+PGF1dGhvcj5Cb3lkLCBS

b2JlcnQ8L2F1dGhvcj48YXV0aG9yPlJpY2hlcnNvbiwgUGV0ZXIgSi48L2F1dGhvcj48L2F1dGhv

cnM+PC9jb250cmlidXRvcnM+PHRpdGxlcz48dGl0bGU+VGhlIG9yaWdpbiBhbmQgZXZvbHV0aW9u

IG9mIGN1bHR1cmVzPC90aXRsZT48L3RpdGxlcz48cGFnZXM+VklJSSwgNDU2IGlsbC48L3BhZ2Vz

PjxkYXRlcz48eWVhcj4yMDA1PC95ZWFyPjwvZGF0ZXM+PHB1Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj5PeGZvcmQ8L3B1

Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj48cHVibGlzaGVyPk94Zm9yZCB1bml2ZXJzaXR5IHByZXNzPC9wdWJsaXNoZXI+

PGlzYm4+MDE5NTE2NTI0MSYjeEQ7MDE5NTE4MTQ1WDwvaXNibj48YWNjZXNzaW9uLW51bT4wMDA5

MDU2NzA8L2FjY2Vzc2lvbi1udW0+PGNhbGwtbnVtPkw2N0IuTTA2NDwvY2FsbC1udW0+PC9yZWNv

cmQ+PC9DaXRlPjxDaXRlPjxBdXRob3I+V2lsc29uPC9BdXRob3I+PFllYXI+MjAwMzwvWWVhcj48

UmVjTnVtPjIwOTU8L1JlY051bT48cmVjb3JkPjxyZWMtbnVtYmVyPjIwOTU8L3JlYy1udW1iZXI+

PGZvcmVpZ24ta2V5cz48a2V5IGFwcD0iRU4iIGRiLWlkPSJlczl0dHZzZDFwMnhhdGV0NWV0cHZl

eG4wMnc5OXI1czBldGQiIHRpbWVzdGFtcD0iMTM5MTkwNjQxNSI+MjA5NTwva2V5PjwvZm9yZWln

bi1rZXlzPjxyZWYtdHlwZSBuYW1lPSJCb29rIj42PC9yZWYtdHlwZT48Y29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjxh

dXRob3JzPjxhdXRob3I+V2lsc29uLCBEYXZpZCBTbG9hbjwvYXV0aG9yPjwvYXV0aG9ycz48L2Nv

bnRyaWJ1dG9ycz48dGl0bGVzPjx0aXRsZT5EYXJ3aW4mYXBvcztzIGNhdGhlZHJhbDogRXZvbHV0

aW9uLCByZWxpZ2lvbiwgYW5kIHRoZSBuYXR1cmUgb2Ygc29jaWV0eTwvdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+

PGRhdGVzPjx5ZWFyPjIwMDM8L3llYXI+PC9kYXRlcz48cHVibGlzaGVyPlVuaXZlcnNpdHkgb2Yg

Q2hpY2FnbyBQcmVzczwvcHVibGlzaGVyPjxpc2JuPjAyMjY5MDEzNTE8L2lzYm4+PC9yZWNvcmQ+

PC9DaXRlPjwvRW5kTm90ZT5=

ADDIN EN.CITE PEVuZE5vdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5IZW5yaWNoPC9BdXRob3I+PFllYXI+MjAxNTwvWWVhcj48

UmVjTnVtPjI0OTQ8L1JlY051bT48RGlzcGxheVRleHQ+KEJveWQgJmFtcDsgUmljaGVyc29uLCAy

MDA1OyBIZW5yaWNoLCAyMDE1OyBNZXNvdWRpLCBXaGl0ZW4sICZhbXA7IExhbGFuZCwgMjAwNjsg

UmljaGVyc29uICZhbXA7IEJveWQsIDIwMDU7IFdpbHNvbiwgMjAwMyk8L0Rpc3BsYXlUZXh0Pjxy

ZWNvcmQ+PHJlYy1udW1iZXI+MjQ5NDwvcmVjLW51bWJlcj48Zm9yZWlnbi1rZXlzPjxrZXkgYXBw

PSJFTiIgZGItaWQ9ImVzOXR0dnNkMXAyeGF0ZXQ1ZXRwdmV4bjAydzk5cjVzMGV0ZCIgdGltZXN0

YW1wPSIxNDYwNjY1OTY5Ij4yNDk0PC9rZXk+PC9mb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PHJlZi10eXBlIG5hbWU9

IkJvb2siPjY8L3JlZi10eXBlPjxjb250cmlidXRvcnM+PGF1dGhvcnM+PGF1dGhvcj5IZW5yaWNo

LCBKb3NlcGg8L2F1dGhvcj48L2F1dGhvcnM+PC9jb250cmlidXRvcnM+PHRpdGxlcz48dGl0bGU+

VGhlIHNlY3JldCBvZiBvdXIgc3VjY2VzczogSG93IGN1bHR1cmUgaXMgZHJpdmluZyBodW1hbiBl

dm9sdXRpb24sIGRvbWVzdGljYXRpbmcgb3VyIHNwZWNpZXMsIGFuZCBtYWtpbmcgdXMgc21hcnRl

cjwvdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+PGRhdGVzPjx5ZWFyPjIwMTU8L3llYXI+PC9kYXRlcz48cHVibGlz

aGVyPlByaW5jZXRvbiBVbml2ZXJzaXR5IFByZXNzPC9wdWJsaXNoZXI+PGlzYm4+MTQwMDg3MzI5

MDwvaXNibj48L3JlY29yZD48L0NpdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5NZXNvdWRpPC9BdXRob3I+PFll

YXI+MjAwNjwvWWVhcj48UmVjTnVtPjI1MTg8L1JlY051bT48cmVjb3JkPjxyZWMtbnVtYmVyPjI1

MTg8L3JlYy1udW1iZXI+PGZvcmVpZ24ta2V5cz48a2V5IGFwcD0iRU4iIGRiLWlkPSJlczl0dHZz

ZDFwMnhhdGV0NWV0cHZleG4wMnc5OXI1czBldGQiIHRpbWVzdGFtcD0iMTQ2MzAwNDgwNSI+MjUx

ODwva2V5PjwvZm9yZWlnbi1rZXlzPjxyZWYtdHlwZSBuYW1lPSJKb3VybmFsIEFydGljbGUiPjE3

PC9yZWYtdHlwZT48Y29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjxhdXRob3JzPjxhdXRob3I+TWVzb3VkaSwgQWxleDwv

YXV0aG9yPjxhdXRob3I+V2hpdGVuLCBBbmRyZXc8L2F1dGhvcj48YXV0aG9yPkxhbGFuZCwgS2V2

aW4gTjwvYXV0aG9yPjwvYXV0aG9ycz48L2NvbnRyaWJ1dG9ycz48dGl0bGVzPjx0aXRsZT5Ub3dh

cmRzIGEgdW5pZmllZCBzY2llbmNlIG9mIGN1bHR1cmFsIGV2b2x1dGlvbjwvdGl0bGU+PHNlY29u

ZGFyeS10aXRsZT5CZWhhdmlvcmFsIGFuZCBCcmFpbiBTY2llbmNlczwvc2Vjb25kYXJ5LXRpdGxl

PjwvdGl0bGVzPjxwZXJpb2RpY2FsPjxmdWxsLXRpdGxlPkJlaGF2aW9yYWwgYW5kIEJyYWluIFNj

aWVuY2VzPC9mdWxsLXRpdGxlPjxhYmJyLTE+QmVoYXYuIEJyYWluIFNjaS48L2FiYnItMT48YWJi

ci0yPkJlaGF2IEJyYWluIFNjaTwvYWJici0yPjxhYmJyLTM+QmVoYXZpb3JhbCAmYW1wOyBCcmFp

biBTY2llbmNlczwvYWJici0zPjwvcGVyaW9kaWNhbD48cGFnZXM+MzI5LTM0NzwvcGFnZXM+PHZv

bHVtZT4yOTwvdm9sdW1lPjxudW1iZXI+MDQ8L251bWJlcj48ZGF0ZXM+PHllYXI+MjAwNjwveWVh

cj48L2RhdGVzPjxpc2JuPjE0NjktMTgyNTwvaXNibj48L3JlY29yZD48L0NpdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1

dGhvcj5SaWNoZXJzb248L0F1dGhvcj48WWVhcj4yMDA1PC9ZZWFyPjxSZWNOdW0+NzMwPC9SZWNO

dW0+PHJlY29yZD48cmVjLW51bWJlcj43MzA8L3JlYy1udW1iZXI+PGZvcmVpZ24ta2V5cz48a2V5

IGFwcD0iRU4iIGRiLWlkPSJlczl0dHZzZDFwMnhhdGV0NWV0cHZleG4wMnc5OXI1czBldGQiIHRp

bWVzdGFtcD0iMTI2ODc1NzM3OSI+NzMwPC9rZXk+PGtleSBhcHA9IkVOV2ViIiBkYi1pZD0iUjdC

WWF3cnRtQ1lBQUFLbWZLQSI+Nzk5PC9rZXk+PC9mb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PHJlZi10eXBlIG5hbWU9

IkJvb2siPjY8L3JlZi10eXBlPjxjb250cmlidXRvcnM+PGF1dGhvcnM+PGF1dGhvcj5SaWNoZXJz

b24sIFBldGVyIEouPC9hdXRob3I+PGF1dGhvcj5Cb3lkLCBSb2JlcnQ8L2F1dGhvcj48L2F1dGhv

cnM+PC9jb250cmlidXRvcnM+PHRpdGxlcz48dGl0bGU+Tm90IGJ5IGdlbmVzIGFsb25lOiBIb3cg

Y3VsdHVyZSB0cmFuc2Zvcm1lZCBodW1hbiBldm9sdXRpb248L3RpdGxlPjwvdGl0bGVzPjxwYWdl

cz5JWCwgMzMyPC9wYWdlcz48ZGF0ZXM+PHllYXI+MjAwNTwveWVhcj48L2RhdGVzPjxwdWItbG9j

YXRpb24+Q2hpY2FnbyAoSWxsLik8L3B1Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj48cHVibGlzaGVyPlVuaXZlcnNpdHkg

b2YgQ2hpY2FnbyBwcmVzczwvcHVibGlzaGVyPjxpc2JuPjAyMjY3MTI4NDI8L2lzYm4+PGFjY2Vz

c2lvbi1udW0+MDAwODU5NTAzPC9hY2Nlc3Npb24tbnVtPjxjYWxsLW51bT5QUzA0LkFSQ0hJRUYu

MkdBMDg2JiN4RDtMNjdCLkQzMTQ8L2NhbGwtbnVtPjwvcmVjb3JkPjwvQ2l0ZT48Q2l0ZT48QXV0

aG9yPkJveWQ8L0F1dGhvcj48WWVhcj4yMDA1PC9ZZWFyPjxSZWNOdW0+MTY5NzwvUmVjTnVtPjxy

ZWNvcmQ+PHJlYy1udW1iZXI+MTY5NzwvcmVjLW51bWJlcj48Zm9yZWlnbi1rZXlzPjxrZXkgYXBw

PSJFTiIgZGItaWQ9ImVzOXR0dnNkMXAyeGF0ZXQ1ZXRwdmV4bjAydzk5cjVzMGV0ZCIgdGltZXN0

YW1wPSIxMzgwODAzMjQwIj4xNjk3PC9rZXk+PC9mb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PHJlZi10eXBlIG5hbWU9

IkJvb2siPjY8L3JlZi10eXBlPjxjb250cmlidXRvcnM+PGF1dGhvcnM+PGF1dGhvcj5Cb3lkLCBS

b2JlcnQ8L2F1dGhvcj48YXV0aG9yPlJpY2hlcnNvbiwgUGV0ZXIgSi48L2F1dGhvcj48L2F1dGhv

cnM+PC9jb250cmlidXRvcnM+PHRpdGxlcz48dGl0bGU+VGhlIG9yaWdpbiBhbmQgZXZvbHV0aW9u

IG9mIGN1bHR1cmVzPC90aXRsZT48L3RpdGxlcz48cGFnZXM+VklJSSwgNDU2IGlsbC48L3BhZ2Vz

PjxkYXRlcz48eWVhcj4yMDA1PC95ZWFyPjwvZGF0ZXM+PHB1Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj5PeGZvcmQ8L3B1

Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj48cHVibGlzaGVyPk94Zm9yZCB1bml2ZXJzaXR5IHByZXNzPC9wdWJsaXNoZXI+

PGlzYm4+MDE5NTE2NTI0MSYjeEQ7MDE5NTE4MTQ1WDwvaXNibj48YWNjZXNzaW9uLW51bT4wMDA5

MDU2NzA8L2FjY2Vzc2lvbi1udW0+PGNhbGwtbnVtPkw2N0IuTTA2NDwvY2FsbC1udW0+PC9yZWNv

cmQ+PC9DaXRlPjxDaXRlPjxBdXRob3I+V2lsc29uPC9BdXRob3I+PFllYXI+MjAwMzwvWWVhcj48

UmVjTnVtPjIwOTU8L1JlY051bT48cmVjb3JkPjxyZWMtbnVtYmVyPjIwOTU8L3JlYy1udW1iZXI+

PGZvcmVpZ24ta2V5cz48a2V5IGFwcD0iRU4iIGRiLWlkPSJlczl0dHZzZDFwMnhhdGV0NWV0cHZl

eG4wMnc5OXI1czBldGQiIHRpbWVzdGFtcD0iMTM5MTkwNjQxNSI+MjA5NTwva2V5PjwvZm9yZWln

bi1rZXlzPjxyZWYtdHlwZSBuYW1lPSJCb29rIj42PC9yZWYtdHlwZT48Y29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjxh

dXRob3JzPjxhdXRob3I+V2lsc29uLCBEYXZpZCBTbG9hbjwvYXV0aG9yPjwvYXV0aG9ycz48L2Nv

bnRyaWJ1dG9ycz48dGl0bGVzPjx0aXRsZT5EYXJ3aW4mYXBvcztzIGNhdGhlZHJhbDogRXZvbHV0

aW9uLCByZWxpZ2lvbiwgYW5kIHRoZSBuYXR1cmUgb2Ygc29jaWV0eTwvdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+

PGRhdGVzPjx5ZWFyPjIwMDM8L3llYXI+PC9kYXRlcz48cHVibGlzaGVyPlVuaXZlcnNpdHkgb2Yg

Q2hpY2FnbyBQcmVzczwvcHVibGlzaGVyPjxpc2JuPjAyMjY5MDEzNTE8L2lzYm4+PC9yZWNvcmQ+

PC9DaXRlPjwvRW5kTm90ZT5=

ADDIN EN.CITE.DATA (Boyd & Richerson, 2005; Henrich, 2015; Mesoudi, Whiten, & Laland, 2006; Richerson & Boyd, 2005; Wilson, 2003). It is now widely accepted, at least by scholars of cultural evolution, that much adaptive cultural design was not purposefully crafted by a single author, or even a few innovators and pioneers, but slowly accumulated over time, through a relatively blind process of trial and error. No single person, or even a small group of innovators, can take credit for the design work that goes into igloos, canoes, folklore tales, folk medicine, marriage institutions, procedures for detoxifying food, or complex religious rituals. Much of the design credit, as was argued most forcefully by Henrich ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite ExcludeAuth="1"><Author>Henrich</Author><Year>2015</Year><RecNum>2494</RecNum><DisplayText>(2015)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2494</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1460665969">2494</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Henrich, Joseph</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The secret of our success: How culture is driving human evolution, domesticating our species, and making us smarter</title></titles><dates><year>2015</year></dates><publisher>Princeton University Press</publisher><isbn>1400873290</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(2015), should be assigned to blind cultural evolution. Even after such cultural design has evolved, its rationale remains largely to opaque to human beings. People have little understanding of why they hunt or cook food in a particular way. When asked, they tend to give spurious post hoc explanations, or they draw a blank, saying in effect “this is the way we do things”. In some cases, they are not even aware of the existence of cultural design ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Henrich</Author><Year>2015</Year><RecNum>2494</RecNum><DisplayText>(Henrich, 2015)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2494</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1460665969">2494</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Henrich, Joseph</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The secret of our success: How culture is driving human evolution, domesticating our species, and making us smarter</title></titles><dates><year>2015</year></dates><publisher>Princeton University Press</publisher><isbn>1400873290</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Henrich, 2015).All this is not to say, of course, that human intelligence has no share in adaptive cultural design. But just because intelligent creatures are somehow involved in the process, as the producers and transmitters and consumers of culture, does not mean that they deserve credit for all the design work. Human beings may have local and parochial intentions in transmitting bits of culture, without understanding the aggregated effects of their actions over time. They may copy the most efficient spears and igloos, or imitate the recipes and habits of a successful individual, without having any clue as to the reasons for their success. They may not even be aware that they are transmitting cultural information at all. To assume that evolutionary explanations are moot wherever intentional agents are on the scene, as Pagel ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite ExcludeAuth="1"><Author>Pagel</Author><Year>2006</Year><RecNum>2525</RecNum><Pages>360</Pages><DisplayText>(2006, p. 360)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2525</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1463095765">2525</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Pagel, Mark</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Darwinian cultural evolution rivals genetic evolution</title><secondary-title>Behavioral and Brain Sciences</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>Behavioral and Brain Sciences</full-title><abbr-1>Behav. Brain Sci.</abbr-1><abbr-2>Behav Brain Sci</abbr-2><abbr-3>Behavioral &amp; Brain Sciences</abbr-3></periodical><pages>360-360</pages><volume>29</volume><number>04</number><dates><year>2006</year></dates><isbn>1469-1825</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(2006, p. 360) writes, is to “conflate intentionality with omniscience”.In the living world, all the heavy lifting in design space is done by random variation and selection, or at least by some other blind and unguided processes. At least until very recently, none is the result of intelligent design. In the cultural domain, by contrast, intelligent design does contribute to the emergence of functional complexity, but only to varying degrees. There is a continuum from deliberate, foresighted and conscious design, to mindless, unconscious and blind selection ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Dennett</Author><Year>2006</Year><RecNum>2519</RecNum><DisplayText>(Dennett &amp; McKay, 2006)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2519</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1463006034">2519</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dennett, Daniel C.</author><author>McKay, Ryan</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>A continuum of mindfulness</title><secondary-title>Behavioral and Brain Sciences</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>Behavioral and Brain Sciences</full-title><abbr-1>Behav. Brain Sci.</abbr-1><abbr-2>Behav Brain Sci</abbr-2><abbr-3>Behavioral &amp; Brain Sciences</abbr-3></periodical><pages>353-354</pages><volume>29</volume><number>04</number><dates><year>2006</year></dates><isbn>1469-1825</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Dennett & McKay, 2006). In many cases, of course, the origins of cultural design are lost in the mist of time, leaving us with little more than scant circumstantial evidence. Some cultural inventions were probably created in one fell swoop by geniuses, some arose in relatively discrete creative outbursts by a few pioneers, still others accumulated in small, incremental steps, with little or no understanding on the part of the agents involved. Sometimes the development of cultural design over time is monitored and steered in a particular direction, but sometimes it happens in a relatively unguided and haphazard way. Units of cultureRicherson and Boyd define culture as “information capable of affecting individuals’ behavior that they acquire from other members of their species through teaching, imitation, and other forms of social transmission.” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Richerson</Author><Year>2005</Year><RecNum>730</RecNum><Pages>5</Pages><DisplayText>(Richerson &amp; Boyd, 2005, p. 5)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>730</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1268757379">730</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">799</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Richerson, Peter J.</author><author>Boyd, Robert</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution</title></titles><pages>IX, 332</pages><dates><year>2005</year></dates><pub-location>Chicago (Ill.)</pub-location><publisher>University of Chicago press</publisher><isbn>0226712842</isbn><accession-num>000859503</accession-num><call-num>PS04.ARCHIEF.2GA086&#xD;L67B.D314</call-num></record></Cite></EndNote>(Richerson & Boyd, 2005, p. 5) An important question for cultural theorists is the following: can cultural information be broken down into discrete and identifiable units, similar to ‘genes’? Here we favor a pragmatic approach. If some piece of information exhibits appreciable functional coherence, and is spreading through a population in the way described by Richerson and Boyd, with different instantiations forming lineages of descent, then that piece of information can be baptized as a “meme” (or another convenient term). ‘Memes’ then are just functional units of cultural information that persist through time: beliefs, practices, rituals, words, recipes, tunes, mannerisms, pictures. Many cultural theorists resist this nomenclature, preferring instead to talk about representations or cultural variants, or the more specific terms from the above list ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Sperber</Author><Year>2000</Year><RecNum>902</RecNum><DisplayText>(Richerson &amp; Boyd, 2005; Sperber, 2000)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>902</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1279610835">902</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">892</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book Section">5</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Sperber, Dan</author></authors><secondary-authors><author>Aunger, Robert</author></secondary-authors></contributors><titles><title>An objection to the memetic approach to culture</title><secondary-title>Darwinizing culture: The status of memetics as a science</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>Darwinizing culture: the status of memetics as a science</full-title></periodical><pages>163-173</pages><dates><year>2000</year></dates><pub-location>Oxford</pub-location><publisher>Oxford University Press</publisher></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Richerson</Author><Year>2005</Year><RecNum>730</RecNum><record><rec-number>730</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1268757379">730</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">799</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Richerson, Peter J.</author><author>Boyd, Robert</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution</title></titles><pages>IX, 332</pages><dates><year>2005</year></dates><pub-location>Chicago (Ill.)</pub-location><publisher>University of Chicago press</publisher><isbn>0226712842</isbn><accession-num>000859503</accession-num><call-num>PS04.ARCHIEF.2GA086&#xD;L67B.D314</call-num></record></Cite></EndNote>(Richerson & Boyd, 2005; Sperber, 2000). In their view, the term “meme” suggests that culture is composed of discrete units analogous to genes, which are copied by simple imitation. At bottom, however, this is a terminological discussion. Cultural evolutionists could decide to adopt Dawkins’ terminology, without taking on board the notion of replication by simple copying ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Durham</Author><Year>1991</Year><RecNum>2541</RecNum><DisplayText>(Durham, 1991)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2541</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1464818988">2541</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Durham, William H</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Coevolution: Genes, culture, and human diversity</title></titles><dates><year>1991</year></dates><publisher>Stanford University Press</publisher><isbn>0804721564</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Durham, 1991). The concept of a meme, as Mesoudi et al. have argued, tolerates ambiguity and fuzzy boundaries, and does not require strict particularism. It is not a problem that we have no method for individuating one meme from another. Many of the putative objections against the concept of a “meme” would apply with equal force to the evolutionary notion of a “gene”, which is far less crisp and clear-cut than many critics imagine. In spite of these obstacles to defining genes, “both empirical and theoretical traditions within population biology have thrived … by using simple, discrete gene concepts.” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Mesoudi</Author><Year>2006</Year><RecNum>2518</RecNum><Pages>343</Pages><DisplayText>(Mesoudi et al., 2006, p. 343)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2518</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1463004805">2518</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Mesoudi, Alex</author><author>Whiten, Andrew</author><author>Laland, Kevin N</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Towards a unified science of cultural evolution</title><secondary-title>Behavioral and Brain Sciences</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>Behavioral and Brain Sciences</full-title><abbr-1>Behav. Brain Sci.</abbr-1><abbr-2>Behav Brain Sci</abbr-2><abbr-3>Behavioral &amp; Brain Sciences</abbr-3></periodical><pages>329-347</pages><volume>29</volume><number>04</number><dates><year>2006</year></dates><isbn>1469-1825</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Mesoudi et al., 2006, p. 343) The same point applies to units of culture. As Richerson and Boyd write, “The selfish meme effect is quite robust. Nothing in the argument depends on cultural variants being discrete, genelike particles. It works exactly the same if “memes” were continuously varying […]” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Richerson</Author><Year>2005</Year><RecNum>730</RecNum><Pages>154</Pages><DisplayText>(Richerson &amp; Boyd, 2005, p. 154)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>730</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1268757379">730</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">799</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Richerson, Peter J.</author><author>Boyd, Robert</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution</title></titles><pages>IX, 332</pages><dates><year>2005</year></dates><pub-location>Chicago (Ill.)</pub-location><publisher>University of Chicago press</publisher><isbn>0226712842</isbn><accession-num>000859503</accession-num><call-num>PS04.ARCHIEF.2GA086&#xD;L67B.D314</call-num></record></Cite></EndNote>(Richerson & Boyd, 2005, p. 154)For similar reasons, it is important to sidestep fruitless debates over the ontological status or physical substrate of a meme ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Lynch</Author><Year>2008</Year><RecNum>2512</RecNum><DisplayText>(Aunger, 2002, 2000; Lynch, 2008)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2512</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1462582905">2512</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Lynch, Aaron</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Thought contagion: How belief spreads through society</title></titles><dates><year>2008</year></dates><publisher>Basic Books</publisher><isbn>0786725648</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Aunger</Author><Year>2000</Year><RecNum>2491</RecNum><record><rec-number>2491</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1460138587">2491</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Edited Book">28</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Aunger, Robert</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Darwinizing Culture: The Status of Memetics as a Science</title></titles><dates><year>2000</year></dates><publisher>OUP Oxford</publisher><isbn>9780192632449</isbn><urls><related-urls><url> app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1462582928">2513</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Aunger, Robert</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The electric meme: A new theory of how we think</title></titles><dates><year>2002</year></dates><publisher>Cambridge Univ Press</publisher><isbn>0743201507</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Aunger, 2002, 2000; Lynch, 2008). The controversy over whether memes should be identified with particular states of the brain, or with observable artefacts or behavior, is a distraction ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Plotkin</Author><Year>2002</Year><RecNum>2528</RecNum><DisplayText>(Plotkin, 2002)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2528</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1463163706">2528</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Plotkin, H.C.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The Imagined World Made Real: Towards a Natural Science of Culture</title></titles><dates><year>2002</year></dates><publisher>Rutgers University Press</publisher><isbn>9780813532684</isbn><urls><related-urls><url>;(Plotkin, 2002). Memes are most usefully thought of as pieces of information, just as genes should not be identified with DNA molecules, but with the information carried by these molecules ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Williams</Author><Year>1992</Year><RecNum>2520</RecNum><DisplayText>(Durham, 1991; Haig, 2007; Williams, 1992)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2520</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1463008051">2520</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Williams, George C</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Natural selection</title></titles><dates><year>1992</year></dates><publisher>Oxford University Press</publisher><isbn>0195361571</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Durham</Author><Year>1991</Year><RecNum>2541</RecNum><record><rec-number>2541</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1464818988">2541</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Durham, William H</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Coevolution: Genes, culture, and human diversity</title></titles><dates><year>1991</year></dates><publisher>Stanford University Press</publisher><isbn>0804721564</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Haig</Author><Year>2007</Year><RecNum>2570</RecNum><record><rec-number>2570</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1470843133">2570</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book Section">5</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Haig, David</author></authors><secondary-authors><author>Ridley, Mark</author></secondary-authors></contributors><titles><title>The gene meme</title><secondary-title>Richard Dawkins: How a Scientist Changed the Way We Think </secondary-title></titles><pages>50-65</pages><dates><year>2007</year></dates></record></Cite></EndNote>(Durham, 1991; Haig, 2007; Williams, 1992). If one cultural item is causally responsible for the emergence of another, and both are sufficiently similar to be treated as instantiating the same information, and many of these items form lineages in a human population, then it doesn’t matter whether we give them a generic title like “meme” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Dawkins</Author><Year>1976</Year><RecNum>763</RecNum><DisplayText>(Dawkins, 1976)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>763</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1270028295">763</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">817</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dawkins, Richard</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The selfish gene</title></titles><pages>XI, 224 ill.</pages><keywords><keyword>Genetics.</keyword><keyword>Evolution (Biology)</keyword><keyword>Sociobiology.</keyword></keywords><dates><year>1976</year></dates><pub-location>Oxford</pub-location><publisher>Oxford University Press</publisher><isbn>0195200004&#xD;019857519X</isbn><accession-num>000048283</accession-num><call-num>PS04.ARCHIEF.5SB.043&#xD;W71L.003-164&#xD;W78.GEN232&#xD;L27.FH24H043</call-num></record></Cite></EndNote>(Dawkins, 1976), “culturgen” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Lumsden</Author><Year>1981</Year><RecNum>2521</RecNum><DisplayText>(Lumsden &amp; Wilson, 1981)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2521</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1463089149">2521</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Lumsden, Charles J</author><author>Wilson, Edward O</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Genes, mind, and ideology</title><secondary-title>The Sciences</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>The Sciences</full-title></periodical><pages>6-8</pages><volume>21</volume><number>9</number><dates><year>1981</year></dates><isbn>2326-1951</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Lumsden & Wilson, 1981) or “cultural variant” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Richerson</Author><Year>2005</Year><RecNum>730</RecNum><DisplayText>(Richerson &amp; Boyd, 2005)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>730</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1268757379">730</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">799</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Richerson, Peter J.</author><author>Boyd, Robert</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution</title></titles><pages>IX, 332</pages><dates><year>2005</year></dates><pub-location>Chicago (Ill.)</pub-location><publisher>University of Chicago press</publisher><isbn>0226712842</isbn><accession-num>000859503</accession-num><call-num>PS04.ARCHIEF.2GA086&#xD;L67B.D314</call-num></record></Cite></EndNote>(Richerson & Boyd, 2005), or whether we use more traditional labels such as ideas, habits, beliefs, or artefacts. In any event, the problem of particularism is not solved by abandoning the term “meme” and substituting a different concept. When Dan Sperber, one of the foremost critic of memetics ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Sperber</Author><Year>2000</Year><RecNum>902</RecNum><DisplayText>(Sperber, 2000)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>902</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1279610835">902</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">892</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book Section">5</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Sperber, Dan</author></authors><secondary-authors><author>Aunger, Robert</author></secondary-authors></contributors><titles><title>An objection to the memetic approach to culture</title><secondary-title>Darwinizing culture: The status of memetics as a science</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>Darwinizing culture: the status of memetics as a science</full-title></periodical><pages>163-173</pages><dates><year>2000</year></dates><pub-location>Oxford</pub-location><publisher>Oxford University Press</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Sperber, 2000), speaks of his preferred concept of “shared representation”, he has to add essentially the same disclaimer: “what we mean is that these individuals have mental representations similar enough to be considered versions of one another.” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Sperber</Author><Year>1996</Year><RecNum>678</RecNum><Pages>82</Pages><DisplayText>(Sperber, 1996, p. 82)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>678</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1265734647">678</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">754</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Sperber, Dan</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Explaining culture: A naturalistic approach</title></titles><dates><year>1996</year></dates><pub-location>Cambridge, Mass.</pub-location><publisher>Blackwell</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Sperber, 1996, p. 82). Indeed. The concept of a “meme” requires nothing more than Sperber’s proviso.The truly novel (and controversial) aspect of memes, as introduced by Richard Dawkins in 1976, is not the idea of particularism, nor even the putative commitment to simple replication through imitation ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Sperber</Author><Year>2000</Year><RecNum>902</RecNum><DisplayText>(Sperber, 2000)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>902</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1279610835">902</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">892</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book Section">5</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Sperber, Dan</author></authors><secondary-authors><author>Aunger, Robert</author></secondary-authors></contributors><titles><title>An objection to the memetic approach to culture</title><secondary-title>Darwinizing culture: The status of memetics as a science</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>Darwinizing culture: the status of memetics as a science</full-title></periodical><pages>163-173</pages><dates><year>2000</year></dates><pub-location>Oxford</pub-location><publisher>Oxford University Press</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Sperber, 2000), but rather the idea that memes can be treated as somehow selfish, as parasites of the mind. The real bone of contention is not one about terminology, but about the meme’s point of view: the idea that items of cultural information – whatever you want to call them – can evolve in such a way that they end up subverting the interests of their hosts. Dennett does not tire of raising this fundamental question whenever we are dealing with adaptive design through selective processes: cui bono? Who or what is the ultimate beneficiary of all this selecting? PEVuZE5vdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5EZW5uZXR0PC9BdXRob3I+PFllYXI+MTk5NTwvWWVhcj48

UmVjTnVtPjE4NTQ8L1JlY051bT48RGlzcGxheVRleHQ+KERlbm5ldHQsIDE5OTAsIDE5OTUsIDIw

MDEpPC9EaXNwbGF5VGV4dD48cmVjb3JkPjxyZWMtbnVtYmVyPjE4NTQ8L3JlYy1udW1iZXI+PGZv

cmVpZ24ta2V5cz48a2V5IGFwcD0iRU4iIGRiLWlkPSJlczl0dHZzZDFwMnhhdGV0NWV0cHZleG4w

Mnc5OXI1czBldGQiIHRpbWVzdGFtcD0iMTM4MDgwMzI1MiI+MTg1NDwva2V5PjwvZm9yZWlnbi1r

ZXlzPjxyZWYtdHlwZSBuYW1lPSJCb29rIj42PC9yZWYtdHlwZT48Y29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjxhdXRo

b3JzPjxhdXRob3I+RGVubmV0dCwgRGFuaWVsIEMuPC9hdXRob3I+PC9hdXRob3JzPjwvY29udHJp

YnV0b3JzPjx0aXRsZXM+PHRpdGxlPkRhcndpbiZhcG9zO3MgZGFuZ2Vyb3VzIGlkZWE6IGV2b2x1

dGlvbiBhbmQgdGhlIG1lYW5pbmdzIG9mIGxpZmU8L3RpdGxlPjwvdGl0bGVzPjxkYXRlcz48eWVh

cj4xOTk1PC95ZWFyPjwvZGF0ZXM+PHB1Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj5OZXcgWW9yazwvcHViLWxvY2F0aW9u

PjxwdWJsaXNoZXI+U2ltb24gJmFtcDsgU2NodXN0ZXI8L3B1Ymxpc2hlcj48L3JlY29yZD48L0Np

dGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5EZW5uZXR0PC9BdXRob3I+PFllYXI+MTk5MDwvWWVhcj48UmVjTnVt

PjE0OTA8L1JlY051bT48cmVjb3JkPjxyZWMtbnVtYmVyPjE0OTA8L3JlYy1udW1iZXI+PGZvcmVp

Z24ta2V5cz48a2V5IGFwcD0iRU4iIGRiLWlkPSJlczl0dHZzZDFwMnhhdGV0NWV0cHZleG4wMnc5

OXI1czBldGQiIHRpbWVzdGFtcD0iMTM3MTAyNDQ4NCI+MTQ5MDwva2V5PjxrZXkgYXBwPSJFTldl

YiIgZGItaWQ9IlI3Qllhd3J0bUNZQUFBS21mS0EiPjEzMzQ8L2tleT48L2ZvcmVpZ24ta2V5cz48

cmVmLXR5cGUgbmFtZT0iSm91cm5hbCBBcnRpY2xlIj4xNzwvcmVmLXR5cGU+PGNvbnRyaWJ1dG9y

cz48YXV0aG9ycz48YXV0aG9yPkRlbm5ldHQsIERhbmllbCBDLjwvYXV0aG9yPjwvYXV0aG9ycz48

L2NvbnRyaWJ1dG9ycz48dGl0bGVzPjx0aXRsZT5NZW1lcyBhbmQgdGhlIGV4cGxvaXRhdGlvbiBv

ZiBpbWFnaW5hdGlvbjwvdGl0bGU+PHNlY29uZGFyeS10aXRsZT5UaGUgSm91cm5hbCBvZiBBZXN0

aGV0aWNzIGFuZCBBcnQgQ3JpdGljaXNtPC9zZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+PHBlcmlv

ZGljYWw+PGZ1bGwtdGl0bGU+VGhlIEpvdXJuYWwgb2YgQWVzdGhldGljcyBhbmQgQXJ0IENyaXRp

Y2lzbTwvZnVsbC10aXRsZT48YWJici0xPkogQWVzLiBBcnQuIENyaXQuPC9hYmJyLTE+PC9wZXJp

b2RpY2FsPjxwYWdlcz4xMjctMTM1PC9wYWdlcz48dm9sdW1lPjQ4PC92b2x1bWU+PG51bWJlcj4y

PC9udW1iZXI+PGRhdGVzPjx5ZWFyPjE5OTA8L3llYXI+PC9kYXRlcz48aXNibj4wMDIxLTg1Mjk8

L2lzYm4+PC9yZWNvcmQ+PC9DaXRlPjxDaXRlPjxBdXRob3I+RGVubmV0dDwvQXV0aG9yPjxZZWFy

PjIwMDE8L1llYXI+PFJlY051bT4yNTA1PC9SZWNOdW0+PHJlY29yZD48cmVjLW51bWJlcj4yNTA1

PC9yZWMtbnVtYmVyPjxmb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PGtleSBhcHA9IkVOIiBkYi1pZD0iZXM5dHR2c2Qx

cDJ4YXRldDVldHB2ZXhuMDJ3OTlyNXMwZXRkIiB0aW1lc3RhbXA9IjE0NjIxMjk0MzAiPjI1MDU8

L2tleT48L2ZvcmVpZ24ta2V5cz48cmVmLXR5cGUgbmFtZT0iSm91cm5hbCBBcnRpY2xlIj4xNzwv

cmVmLXR5cGU+PGNvbnRyaWJ1dG9ycz48YXV0aG9ycz48YXV0aG9yPkRlbm5ldHQsIERhbmllbCBD

LjwvYXV0aG9yPjwvYXV0aG9ycz48L2NvbnRyaWJ1dG9ycz48dGl0bGVzPjx0aXRsZT5UaGUgZXZv

bHV0aW9uIG9mIGN1bHR1cmU8L3RpdGxlPjxzZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0bGU+VGhlIE1vbmlzdDwvc2Vj

b25kYXJ5LXRpdGxlPjwvdGl0bGVzPjxwZXJpb2RpY2FsPjxmdWxsLXRpdGxlPlRoZSBNb25pc3Q8

L2Z1bGwtdGl0bGU+PGFiYnItMT5Nb25pc3Q8L2FiYnItMT48L3BlcmlvZGljYWw+PHBhZ2VzPjMw

NS0zMjQ8L3BhZ2VzPjx2b2x1bWU+ODQ8L3ZvbHVtZT48bnVtYmVyPjM8L251bWJlcj48ZGF0ZXM+

PHllYXI+MjAwMTwveWVhcj48L2RhdGVzPjwvcmVjb3JkPjwvQ2l0ZT48L0VuZE5vdGU+AG==

ADDIN EN.CITE PEVuZE5vdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5EZW5uZXR0PC9BdXRob3I+PFllYXI+MTk5NTwvWWVhcj48

UmVjTnVtPjE4NTQ8L1JlY051bT48RGlzcGxheVRleHQ+KERlbm5ldHQsIDE5OTAsIDE5OTUsIDIw

MDEpPC9EaXNwbGF5VGV4dD48cmVjb3JkPjxyZWMtbnVtYmVyPjE4NTQ8L3JlYy1udW1iZXI+PGZv

cmVpZ24ta2V5cz48a2V5IGFwcD0iRU4iIGRiLWlkPSJlczl0dHZzZDFwMnhhdGV0NWV0cHZleG4w

Mnc5OXI1czBldGQiIHRpbWVzdGFtcD0iMTM4MDgwMzI1MiI+MTg1NDwva2V5PjwvZm9yZWlnbi1r

ZXlzPjxyZWYtdHlwZSBuYW1lPSJCb29rIj42PC9yZWYtdHlwZT48Y29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjxhdXRo

b3JzPjxhdXRob3I+RGVubmV0dCwgRGFuaWVsIEMuPC9hdXRob3I+PC9hdXRob3JzPjwvY29udHJp

YnV0b3JzPjx0aXRsZXM+PHRpdGxlPkRhcndpbiZhcG9zO3MgZGFuZ2Vyb3VzIGlkZWE6IGV2b2x1

dGlvbiBhbmQgdGhlIG1lYW5pbmdzIG9mIGxpZmU8L3RpdGxlPjwvdGl0bGVzPjxkYXRlcz48eWVh

cj4xOTk1PC95ZWFyPjwvZGF0ZXM+PHB1Yi1sb2NhdGlvbj5OZXcgWW9yazwvcHViLWxvY2F0aW9u

PjxwdWJsaXNoZXI+U2ltb24gJmFtcDsgU2NodXN0ZXI8L3B1Ymxpc2hlcj48L3JlY29yZD48L0Np

dGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5EZW5uZXR0PC9BdXRob3I+PFllYXI+MTk5MDwvWWVhcj48UmVjTnVt

PjE0OTA8L1JlY051bT48cmVjb3JkPjxyZWMtbnVtYmVyPjE0OTA8L3JlYy1udW1iZXI+PGZvcmVp

Z24ta2V5cz48a2V5IGFwcD0iRU4iIGRiLWlkPSJlczl0dHZzZDFwMnhhdGV0NWV0cHZleG4wMnc5

OXI1czBldGQiIHRpbWVzdGFtcD0iMTM3MTAyNDQ4NCI+MTQ5MDwva2V5PjxrZXkgYXBwPSJFTldl

YiIgZGItaWQ9IlI3Qllhd3J0bUNZQUFBS21mS0EiPjEzMzQ8L2tleT48L2ZvcmVpZ24ta2V5cz48

cmVmLXR5cGUgbmFtZT0iSm91cm5hbCBBcnRpY2xlIj4xNzwvcmVmLXR5cGU+PGNvbnRyaWJ1dG9y

cz48YXV0aG9ycz48YXV0aG9yPkRlbm5ldHQsIERhbmllbCBDLjwvYXV0aG9yPjwvYXV0aG9ycz48

L2NvbnRyaWJ1dG9ycz48dGl0bGVzPjx0aXRsZT5NZW1lcyBhbmQgdGhlIGV4cGxvaXRhdGlvbiBv

ZiBpbWFnaW5hdGlvbjwvdGl0bGU+PHNlY29uZGFyeS10aXRsZT5UaGUgSm91cm5hbCBvZiBBZXN0

aGV0aWNzIGFuZCBBcnQgQ3JpdGljaXNtPC9zZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+PHBlcmlv

ZGljYWw+PGZ1bGwtdGl0bGU+VGhlIEpvdXJuYWwgb2YgQWVzdGhldGljcyBhbmQgQXJ0IENyaXRp

Y2lzbTwvZnVsbC10aXRsZT48YWJici0xPkogQWVzLiBBcnQuIENyaXQuPC9hYmJyLTE+PC9wZXJp

b2RpY2FsPjxwYWdlcz4xMjctMTM1PC9wYWdlcz48dm9sdW1lPjQ4PC92b2x1bWU+PG51bWJlcj4y

PC9udW1iZXI+PGRhdGVzPjx5ZWFyPjE5OTA8L3llYXI+PC9kYXRlcz48aXNibj4wMDIxLTg1Mjk8

L2lzYm4+PC9yZWNvcmQ+PC9DaXRlPjxDaXRlPjxBdXRob3I+RGVubmV0dDwvQXV0aG9yPjxZZWFy

PjIwMDE8L1llYXI+PFJlY051bT4yNTA1PC9SZWNOdW0+PHJlY29yZD48cmVjLW51bWJlcj4yNTA1

PC9yZWMtbnVtYmVyPjxmb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PGtleSBhcHA9IkVOIiBkYi1pZD0iZXM5dHR2c2Qx

cDJ4YXRldDVldHB2ZXhuMDJ3OTlyNXMwZXRkIiB0aW1lc3RhbXA9IjE0NjIxMjk0MzAiPjI1MDU8

L2tleT48L2ZvcmVpZ24ta2V5cz48cmVmLXR5cGUgbmFtZT0iSm91cm5hbCBBcnRpY2xlIj4xNzwv

cmVmLXR5cGU+PGNvbnRyaWJ1dG9ycz48YXV0aG9ycz48YXV0aG9yPkRlbm5ldHQsIERhbmllbCBD

LjwvYXV0aG9yPjwvYXV0aG9ycz48L2NvbnRyaWJ1dG9ycz48dGl0bGVzPjx0aXRsZT5UaGUgZXZv

bHV0aW9uIG9mIGN1bHR1cmU8L3RpdGxlPjxzZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0bGU+VGhlIE1vbmlzdDwvc2Vj

b25kYXJ5LXRpdGxlPjwvdGl0bGVzPjxwZXJpb2RpY2FsPjxmdWxsLXRpdGxlPlRoZSBNb25pc3Q8

L2Z1bGwtdGl0bGU+PGFiYnItMT5Nb25pc3Q8L2FiYnItMT48L3BlcmlvZGljYWw+PHBhZ2VzPjMw

NS0zMjQ8L3BhZ2VzPjx2b2x1bWU+ODQ8L3ZvbHVtZT48bnVtYmVyPjM8L251bWJlcj48ZGF0ZXM+

PHllYXI+MjAwMTwveWVhcj48L2RhdGVzPjwvcmVjb3JkPjwvQ2l0ZT48L0VuZE5vdGU+AG==

ADDIN EN.CITE.DATA (Dennett, 1990, 1995, 2001)In evolutionary biology, genes are often assigned the protagonist role in explanations of adaptive design ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Dawkins</Author><Year>1982</Year><RecNum>1569</RecNum><DisplayText>(Dawkins, 1982; Sterelny &amp; Kitcher, 1988; Williams, 1992)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1569</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1375726623">1569</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dawkins, Richard</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The Extended Phenotype: The Long Reach of the Gene</title></titles><dates><year>1982</year></dates><publisher>Oxford University Press, Incorporated</publisher><isbn>9780192860880</isbn><urls><related-urls><url> app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1463092220">2524</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Sterelny, Kim</author><author>Kitcher, Philip</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The return of the gene</title><secondary-title>The Journal of Philosophy</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>The Journal of Philosophy</full-title><abbr-1>J Phil.</abbr-1></periodical><pages>339-361</pages><volume>85</volume><number>7</number><dates><year>1988</year></dates><isbn>0022-362X</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Williams</Author><Year>1992</Year><RecNum>2520</RecNum><record><rec-number>2520</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1463008051">2520</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Williams, George C</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Natural selection</title></titles><dates><year>1992</year></dates><publisher>Oxford University Press</publisher><isbn>0195361571</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Dawkins, 1982; Sterelny & Kitcher, 1988; Williams, 1992). By treating genes as if they were selfish agents furthering their own propagation, we can shed light on many puzzling phenomena in the living world. This is not to say that everything in evolution revolves around genes ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Jablonka</Author><Year>2005</Year><RecNum>1056</RecNum><DisplayText>(Jablonka &amp; Lamb, 2005)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1056</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1289214335">1056</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">996</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Jablonka, E.</author><author>Lamb, M. J.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Evolution in four dimensions: Genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life</title></titles><dates><year>2005</year></dates><pub-location>Cambridge</pub-location><publisher>MIT Press</publisher><isbn>0262101076</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Jablonka & Lamb, 2005), or that the perspective of the organism is never useful. Organism-centered explanation of adaptive design work to the extent that their interests align with those of their hereditary material, as indeed they often do. As Dennett writes: “The theory becomes interesting only when we look at the exceptions, the circumstances under which there is a pulling apart of the two perspectives” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Dennett</Author><Year>1990</Year><RecNum>1490</RecNum><Pages>130</Pages><DisplayText>(Dennett, 1990, p. 130)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1490</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1371024484">1490</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">1334</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dennett, Daniel C.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Memes and the exploitation of imagination</title><secondary-title>The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism</full-title><abbr-1>J Aes. Art. Crit.</abbr-1></periodical><pages>127-135</pages><volume>48</volume><number>2</number><dates><year>1990</year></dates><isbn>0021-8529</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Dennett, 1990, p. 130). In biology, there are plenty of conditions in which the perspective of the organism and the gene are pulled apart, such as kin selection, eusociality, retroviruses, parasite/host interactions, mitochondrial DNA, sex-linked genes, and transmissible cancer. Millikan’s ChallengeBut where do we see this divergence of interests in the case of cultural evolution? You can baptize any piece of culture as a “meme”, but that does not mean it is usefully described as having selfish purposes of its own. Haig writes that memes can have purposes “to the extent that they have properties that have promoted their propagation from mind to mind.” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Haig</Author><Year>2006</Year><RecNum>2571</RecNum><Pages>14</Pages><DisplayText>(Haig, 2006, p. 14)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2571</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1470844146">2571</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book Section">5</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Haig, David</author></authors><secondary-authors><author>Jones, M.</author><author>Fabian, A.C.</author></secondary-authors></contributors><titles><title>Intrapersonal conflict</title><secondary-title>Conflict</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>Conflict</full-title></periodical><pages>8-22</pages><dates><year>2006</year></dates><pub-location>Cambridge</pub-location><publisher>Cambridge University Press</publisher><isbn>0521839602</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Haig, 2006, p. 14) But are these novel purposes, which potentially diverge from human ones? In what sense can pieces of cultural information develop purposes that thwart the interests of their hosts? Perhaps the most lucid formulation of what we take to be the central challenge for the meme’s eye view was offered by Ruth Millikan: Part of what they have been selected for is their ability to be reproduced accurately through the medium of human minds. But this does not subvert their essentially human purposes. ... The memes have merely fed these interests a much richer diet than if each person had to invent all of his own amusements, or invent all of the entertainments he uses to invoke the gratitude and appreciation of others. … Side effects and mishaps resulting from use of these [basic cognitive ] mechanisms will surely occur, but there is no reason to suppose that they systematically produce memes with purposes of a different kind from those either of the genes or of the psyche. ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Millikan</Author><Year>2004</Year><RecNum>1457</RecNum><Pages>18-19</Pages><DisplayText>(Millikan, 2004, pp. 18-19)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1457</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1367862176">1457</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">1304</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Millikan, Ruth Garrett</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Varieties of meaning: the 2002 Jean Nicod lectures</title></titles><dates><year>2004</year></dates><publisher>The MIT Press</publisher><isbn>0262134446</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Millikan, 2004, pp. 18-19)It is not enough just to define “memetic purposes” into existence, if these are merely derivative of human purposes. For the idea of selfish memes to gain traction, we need to see a divergence of interests between human and memetic purposes. Note that Millikan concedes that there can be cultural design without a designer, which was the point that troubled Pinker. She also does not object to the nomenclature of memes. Her point is that, even if cultural representations are adapted by cultural evolution to thrive in a population of humans brains, they are still essentially serving human purposes. In order to be reproductively successful, memes have to adapt themselves to the environment of human desires, interests and tastes. The hosts may be oblivious to this selection process, but the resulting memes will still benefit them. Folksongs, recipes, artefacts, jokes and rituals are products of blind cultural evolution without ever subverting our human interests. If they can be said to go “viral”, that is only because they appeal to universal human tastes and preferences. Evolution is smarter than we are, as Orgel’s second rule reminds us: it knows better how to tickle our fancy and satisfy our cravings than any lone human genius. If this line of reasoning is correct, it seems that memes will always serve some human interest, and it becomes vacuous to track the “fitness” of the memes themselves, as Lewens ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite ExcludeAuth="1"><Author>Lewens</Author><Year>2015</Year><RecNum>2568</RecNum><Pages>31</Pages><DisplayText>(2015, p. 31)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2568</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1470836318">2568</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Lewens, Tim</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Cultural Evolution: Conceptual Challenges</title></titles><dates><year>2015</year></dates><publisher>OUP Oxford</publisher><isbn>0191655805</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(2015, p. 31) wrote. In order for the selfish meme metaphor to gain traction, however, we must find situations in which memes give rise to purposes of their own that cannot be anchored in the intentions of human beings. Preferably, we want cases where they actively thwart human interests, so that no other intentional explanations on the level of human agency are on offer.Millikan’s challenge can be strengthened by a point that was made by Durham ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite ExcludeAuth="1"><Author>Durham</Author><Year>1991</Year><RecNum>2541</RecNum><Pages>198</Pages><DisplayText>(1991, p. 198)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2541</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1464818988">2541</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Durham, William H</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Coevolution: Genes, culture, and human diversity</title></titles><dates><year>1991</year></dates><publisher>Stanford University Press</publisher><isbn>0804721564</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(1991, p. 198). We are not just looking for memes that harm their hosts, because this may happen simply as a result of a divergence of human interests. It may be in the interest of one agent (or group of agents) to impose some cultural representations on others, even though this is harmful to the latter. For example, people can be coerced into participating in a religious ritual, or adopting a marriage custom, or using a particular piece of technology, even though they dislike or disapprove of these respective memes, and even though are aware of their harmful effects. Such memes, strictly speaking, subvert the interests of their hosts, but they are still serving someone else’s interests. Durham calls this “selection by imposition”, as opposed to the more regular “selection by choice”, whereby individuals evaluate and select the memes they prefer. In both cases, according to Durham, we seem to have cultural evolution through human decision making: “either way, culture changes under human direction” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Durham</Author><Year>1991</Year><RecNum>2541</RecNum><Pages>198</Pages><DisplayText>(Durham, 1991, p. 198)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2541</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1464818988">2541</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Durham, William H</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Coevolution: Genes, culture, and human diversity</title></titles><dates><year>1991</year></dates><publisher>Stanford University Press</publisher><isbn>0804721564</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Durham, 1991, p. 198). This serves to reinforce Millikan’s point: human preferences direct cultural evolution. So how can memes have selfish interests of their own, which are not derivative of human preference?Failed Answers to Millikan’s ChallengePanmemetics Before we discuss what we take to be genuine selfish memes, we have to deal with an influential and more permissive approach to meme talk, and show why it runs afoul of Millikan’s challenge. In this radical and encompassing view, which we call panmemetics, all of human culture is treated as consisting of selfish memes. Eventually, this approach leads to the subversive and startling conclusion that we are not in control of our thoughts, but the memes are in control of us. Our brains are just breeding grounds for selfish parasites manipulating us into fostering their own proliferation. In The Meme Machine, Susan Blackmore writes:To start to think memetically we have to make a giant flip in our minds just as biologists had to do when taking on the idea of the selfish gene. Instead of thinking of our ideas as our own creations, and as working for us, we have to think of them as autonomous selfish memes, working only to get themselves copied. … This is a scary idea indeed. ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Blackmore</Author><Year>2000</Year><RecNum>897</RecNum><Pages>7-8</Pages><DisplayText>(Blackmore, 2000, pp. 7-8)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>897</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1278342288">897</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">887</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Blackmore, S. J.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The meme machine</title></titles><dates><year>2000</year></dates><pub-location>Oxford</pub-location><publisher>Oxford University Press</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Blackmore, 2000, pp. 7-8)Another major proponents of memetics, Robert Aunger, similarly writes: Who’s talking when I speak: the memes or me? Are my very thoughts something I was able to decide on, or are they just parasites attempting to get out of me and thus infect others? ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Aunger</Author><Year>2002</Year><RecNum>2513</RecNum><Suffix>loc. 281</Suffix><DisplayText>(Aunger, 2002loc. 281)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2513</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1462582928">2513</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Aunger, Robert</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The electric meme: A new theory of how we think</title></titles><dates><year>2002</year></dates><publisher>Cambridge Univ Press</publisher><isbn>0743201507</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Aunger, 2002loc. 281)Elsewhere, Aunger writes about the prospect of “people turned into zombies, with only the illusion of control over their own behavior” and provocatively asks: “Do we have thoughts, or do they have us?” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Aunger</Author><Year>2002</Year><RecNum>2513</RecNum><Suffix>loc. 120</Suffix><DisplayText>(Aunger, 2002loc. 120)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2513</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1462582928">2513</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Aunger, Robert</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The electric meme: A new theory of how we think</title></titles><dates><year>2002</year></dates><publisher>Cambridge Univ Press</publisher><isbn>0743201507</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Aunger, 2002loc. 120). So what remains of human autonomy in this sinister worldview? Some proponents of panmemetics have offered a shimmer of hope for humanity, by exhorting us to revolt against our selfish replicators. In The Robot’s Rebellion, Keith Stanovich writes: “We indeed are the runaway robot of science fiction stories-the robot who subordinates its creator’s interests to its own interests.” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Stanovich</Author><Year>2005</Year><RecNum>1475</RecNum><Pages>xii</Pages><DisplayText>(Stanovich, 2005, p. xii)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1475</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1369303456">1475</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">1320</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Stanovich, Keith E.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The Robot&apos;s Rebellion: Finding Meaning in the Age of Darwin</title></titles><dates><year>2005</year></dates><publisher>University of Chicago Press</publisher><isbn>9780226771250</isbn><urls><related-urls><url>;(Stanovich, 2005, p. xii). For memeticists like Susan Blackmore, however, this is “all a cop-out”. In her meme-infested worldview, there is no room for a self, for deliberate choice, for free will, so “there is no one to rebel” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Blackmore</Author><Year>2000</Year><RecNum>897</RecNum><Pages>246</Pages><DisplayText>(Blackmore, 2000, p. 246)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>897</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1278342288">897</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">887</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Blackmore, S. J.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The meme machine</title></titles><dates><year>2000</year></dates><pub-location>Oxford</pub-location><publisher>Oxford University Press</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Blackmore, 2000, p. 246). “I” am just an illusion created by “my” memes.If anything merits the label “Darwinian paranoia” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Godfrey-Smith</Author><Year>2009</Year><RecNum>765</RecNum><Pages>142-145</Pages><DisplayText>(Godfrey-Smith, 2009, pp. 142-145)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>765</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1270031717">765</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">819</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Godfrey-Smith, Peter</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Darwinian populations and natural selection</title></titles><pages>VIII, 207</pages><dates><year>2009</year></dates><pub-location>Oxford</pub-location><publisher>Oxford university press</publisher><isbn>9780199552047</isbn><accession-num>001325766</accession-num><call-num>L27.24F512&#xD;G97.430</call-num></record></Cite></EndNote>(Godfrey-Smith, 2009, pp. 142-145), this might be it. Let’s pursue the call for rebellion against selfish replicators for a second. Rebelling against that other replicator, our old friend the gene, is pretty straightforward for intelligent human beings: make sure to stay celibate or always use contraceptives, never visit sperm banks (or donate eggs), and don’t support your extended family. By adhering to these simple rules, you will sure to doom the fate of your poor genes. By contrast, the notion of a “rebellion against our memes” ends up in a conceptual quagmire. What else is this rebellion, if not itself a “meme”, with which you might be infected upon opening Stanovich’s book? Even your critical thinking skills, which you rely upon to examine the notion of selfish memes – or to evaluate the cogency of a rebellion against them – can be treated as one of those very memes that you should be rebelling against. Stanovich recognizes this fact: “Scientific and rational thinking are themselves memeplexes – co-adapted sets of interlocking memes” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Stanovich</Author><Year>2005</Year><RecNum>1475</RecNum><Pages>180</Pages><DisplayText>(Stanovich, 2005, p. 180)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1475</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1369303456">1475</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">1320</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Stanovich, Keith E.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The Robot&apos;s Rebellion: Finding Meaning in the Age of Darwin</title></titles><dates><year>2005</year></dates><publisher>University of Chicago Press</publisher><isbn>9780226771250</isbn><urls><related-urls><url>;(Stanovich, 2005, p. 180). He calls this the “co-adapted meme paradox” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Stanovich</Author><Year>2005</Year><RecNum>1475</RecNum><Pages>180</Pages><DisplayText>(Stanovich, 2005, p. 180)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1475</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1369303456">1475</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">1320</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Stanovich, Keith E.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The Robot&apos;s Rebellion: Finding Meaning in the Age of Darwin</title></titles><dates><year>2005</year></dates><publisher>University of Chicago Press</publisher><isbn>9780226771250</isbn><urls><related-urls><url>;(Stanovich, 2005, p. 180), which testifies to the “devilish recursiveness” of memetics, but in fact, it is merely an artifact of a metaphor stretched beyond the breaking point. If selfish memes explain everything, they explain nothing. Almost any cultural phenomenon can be restaged as a little drama where the memes are pulling the strings. For example, a mundane observation such as “this apple cake recipe is popular” can be translated as “the recipe-meme has succeeded in replicating itself by devising clever adaptations to appeal to human taste buds”. Or take the discovery of the Higgs boson: one could argue that the Higgs meme “infected” hosts all around the world following the experiments at CERN, which caused a sudden spike in its cultural fitness. From an epidemiological point of view, nothing is more contagious than the naked truth. If there is an 9.0 earthquake tomorrow in the Philippines, the attendant belief “there has been a huge earthquake in the Philippines” will infect millions of brains worldwide in a matter of hours. No biological virus can spread with such breathtaking speed. As Douglas Adams wrote: “Nothing travels faster than the speed of light with the possible exception of bad news, which obeys its own special laws.” But can anything be learned from adopting the meme’s eye view here? Is it enlightening to say that the earthquake meme is exploiting the brains of its hosts to make more copies of itself? Either this is just a fanciful and unenlightening re-description of what we knew all along, or it is a crude form of reductionism, which ignores the fact alluded to above: there is a continuum in culture between relatively mindless processes and intelligent design. Methodical selection & biotechnologyIt is instructive to compare this with the selfish gene. Because blind evolution has done almost all the heavy lifting in nature, and because DNA is the universal code for all life on the planet, the gene’s eye view is much more unifying and universally applicable in the living world than the meme’s eye view could ever be in the cultural world. But even the gene’s eye view runs up against certain limits. Methodical artificial selection and modern biotechnology, provide interesting exceptions. Poodles, bintje potatoes and Belgian Blue cows are forms of biological design, accumulated through small, incremental improvements, but unlike in the case of natural selection, their lineages have been stewarded and directed by intelligent breeders. Poodles, of course, are vehicles for genetic information no less than undomesticated wolves. Their DNA gets replicated and reshuffled through meiosis every generation, just as with wolves. Can we call the poodle genes “selfish” in the interesting, metaphorical sense? In effect, from the gene’s point of view, the difference is not consequential. In the wild, wolf genes have to deal with a host of selective pressures, whereas poodle genes mostly have to deal with one overwhelming selective factor, namely the breeder’s fancy. While the breeder provides food, comfort and protection, thus slackening many of the other selective pressures, he carefully decides which poodles are allowed to mate and reproduce. Note that this is not an exception to, but merely a special case of, natural selection ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Dennett</Author><Year>2001</Year><RecNum>2505</RecNum><DisplayText>(Dennett, 2001)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2505</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1462129430">2505</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dennett, Daniel C.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The evolution of culture</title><secondary-title>The Monist</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>The Monist</full-title><abbr-1>Monist</abbr-1></periodical><pages>305-324</pages><volume>84</volume><number>3</number><dates><year>2001</year></dates></record></Cite></EndNote>(Dennett, 2001). One can still recast what is happening from the poodle genes’ point of view. For example, one could say that poodle genes have invaded a new niche (the bourgeois urban household), developing novel strategies for adapting to the novel selection pressures (the breeder’s fancy). Poodle genes for fluffy fur manipulate the breeder into providing care and protection, much like the brain of a cuckoo chick’s host parents are being manipulated by the parasitic bird’s bright red gape and loud begging call. In cases of purely methodical selection, however, no-one bothers to offer such a gene-centered description. Not because it is strictly false, but because it is unenlightening and contrived. Intentional explanations for poodle design are anchored in the breeders themselves, who are steering the evolution of their stock in a pre-established direction. Modern biotechnology puts further strain on the gene’s eye view. While traditional breeders are still mimicking evolution, in effect partly replacing Mother Nature’s role, bio-engineers are directly intervening in the genome to create a desired phenotype. For example, they insert a gene in cotton to allow it to make its own insecticide (Bt-cotton), or they equip the tomato genome with an anti-freeze gene. Replicator machinery is still churning along in Bt-cotton cells, but the perspective of the selfish gene falls apart. In short, where human intentions reign and provide direction, talk of plotting replicators becomes strained, unenlightening or even preposterous. Once we realize this point, the dramatic claims of panmemetics can be put to rest. Finally, panmemetics is further compounded by the fact that it dissolves the distinction between good and bad forms of culture. By treating all of culture as consisting of selfish memes, furthering their own interests, we can no longer distinguish between genuine mind parasites and memes that are valuable, true or beautiful. If all memes are mind parasites of sorts, then the theory becomes vacuous ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Lewens</Author><Year>2015</Year><RecNum>2568</RecNum><Suffix>chapter 2.5</Suffix><DisplayText>(Lewens, 2015chapter 2.5)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2568</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1470836318">2568</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Lewens, Tim</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Cultural Evolution: Conceptual Challenges</title></titles><dates><year>2015</year></dates><publisher>OUP Oxford</publisher><isbn>0191655805</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Lewens, 2015chapter 2.5). If such a normative distinction appears at all in the panmemetic literature, it often seems arbitrary and bereft of theoretical significance. For example, Aunger starts his book with an interesting vignette about how witchcraft beliefs spread like viruses (see further). But it is unclear how Aunger’s panmemetic perspective helps explaining why witchcraft beliefs are virulent. If all memes are mind parasites of sorts, then what is the difference between witchcraft memes and, say, heliocentrism memes? The thesis that some memes are mind parasites needs to amount to more than saying that “these are some memes we don’t like” or “these are some memes that have spread far and wide”. In the absence of a substantive theoretical distinction, parlance of mind parasites reduces to mere rhetoric. We may find that antisemitism is a pernicious meme, but if this claim amounts to nothing more than rephrasing our distaste of anti-Semitism, it will not be edifying. To solve this problem, we will have to show that, in a substantial and non-question begging way, mind parasites are detrimental to the interests of the host themselves. Biologically Maladaptive CultureIn panmemetics, all of human culture is analyzed in terms of memes furthering their selfish interests, with human agency taking the back seat. But this approach does not answer Millikan’s challenge: in many cases panmemetics does not provide a demonstration of novel memetic purposes, but just a fanciful rephrasing of phenomena we already understood perfectly well in terms of human desires and preferences. We need a robust account of how memes introduce novel purposes in the world, and show when and where these purposes might diverge from human ones. One natural approach do to so is inspired by the analogy with biological viruses. Dennett has proposed a classification of memes analogous to biological symbionts: some are mutualists (enhancing the fitness of the host), others are commensals (neutral to the host) and still others are parasites (fitness-reducing). Biological symbionts can be placed along this continuum, and so, Dennett claims, can memes. Dennett’s classification is useful, but it brings to light an important ambiguity. In the case of biological viruses, the reference point of our classification is the fitness of the host. Properly speaking, we are classifying the different ways in which the selfish genes of host and symbiont may be related: are they antagonistic, neutral, of cooperative? But in the case of memes, their environment provides an additional and more important source of intentionality: human interests and purposes. Remember Millikan’s challenge, which was to show how memes can give rise to irreducibly novel purposes, over and above human ones. If some memes can be thought of as harmful “parasites”, as per Dennett’s classification, whose interests are they supposed to hurt exactly? Are they parasitizing on us, or on our genes? It is important to clear up this ambiguity. Take the idea of celibacy. Delius ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite ExcludeAuth="1"><Author>Delius</Author><Year>1991</Year><RecNum>2517</RecNum><DisplayText>(1991)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2517</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1462736567">2517</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book Section">5</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Delius, Juan D.</author></authors><secondary-authors><author>Dawkins, M. S.</author><author>Halliday, T. R.</author><author>Dawkins, R.</author></secondary-authors></contributors><titles><title>The nature of culture</title><secondary-title>The Tinbergen Legacy</secondary-title></titles><pages>75-99</pages><dates><year>1991</year></dates><pub-location>Dordrecht</pub-location><publisher>Springer Netherlands</publisher><isbn>978-0-585-35156-8</isbn><label>Delius1991</label><urls><related-urls><url>;(1991) argues that “[c]elibacy is an obvious parasite meme that causes a reduction of host reproduction.” Dennett, too, writes that celibacy is “the most obvious meme example” of a parasite ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Dennett</Author><Year>1995</Year><RecNum>1854</RecNum><Pages>367</Pages><DisplayText>(Dennett, 1995, p. 367)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1854</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1380803252">1854</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dennett, Daniel C.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Darwin&apos;s dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life</title></titles><dates><year>1995</year></dates><pub-location>New York</pub-location><publisher>Simon &amp; Schuster</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Dennett, 1995, p. 367). Indeed, we can treat the meme for celibacy as a “parasite” of sorts, but only when we adopt the vantage point of our genes and their desire for immortality. Any cultural invention or practice that stands in the way of biological reproduction is disastrous for human genes. On the face of it, however, the meme for celibacy need not subvert human purposes, and may precisely be the outcome of a carefully weighted deliberation. Even though a celibate lifestyle is often part of an evolved cultural tradition, like the celibacy rule for Catholic priests, a well-informed decision to remain childless may spring up outside of such a tradition, and would not be any less fatal for the genes. This is well demonstrated in Richerson and Boyd’s chapter on maladaptive culture in Not by genes alone. Richerson and Boyd give a fascinating account of the demographic transition, the phenomenon of rapidly dropping birth rates observed in many contemporary societies. Foremost among the causes of the demographic transition, they argue, are “maladaptive” forms of culture such as universal education and materialism, which spread in a population as a result of the runaway effects of prestige-biased transmission. They too, confusingly, use the term “selfish cultural variants” to describe the causes of the demographic transition ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite ExcludeAuth="1"><Author>Richerson</Author><Year>2005</Year><RecNum>730</RecNum><Pages>153</Pages><DisplayText>(2005, p. 153)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>730</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1268757379">730</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">799</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Richerson, Peter J.</author><author>Boyd, Robert</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution</title></titles><pages>IX, 332</pages><dates><year>2005</year></dates><pub-location>Chicago (Ill.)</pub-location><publisher>University of Chicago press</publisher><isbn>0226712842</isbn><accession-num>000859503</accession-num><call-num>PS04.ARCHIEF.2GA086&#xD;L67B.D314</call-num></record></Cite></EndNote>(2005, p. 153). But it is strange to describe people who lead voluntarily childless but fulfilling lives, as having succumbed to a selfish meme. Such a definition would not have any bearing on our personal valuation of memes. What is maladaptive from the point of view of my genes may further my personal goals in life. Richerson and Boyd seem to be aware of this tension, as witnessed by their quip, “If you want to improve your kids’ genetic fitness, for goodness sake don’t help them with their homework!” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Richerson</Author><Year>2005</Year><RecNum>730</RecNum><Pages>178</Pages><DisplayText>(Richerson &amp; Boyd, 2005, p. 178)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>730</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1268757379">730</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">799</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Richerson, Peter J.</author><author>Boyd, Robert</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution</title></titles><pages>IX, 332</pages><dates><year>2005</year></dates><pub-location>Chicago (Ill.)</pub-location><publisher>University of Chicago press</publisher><isbn>0226712842</isbn><accession-num>000859503</accession-num><call-num>PS04.ARCHIEF.2GA086&#xD;L67B.D314</call-num></record></Cite></EndNote>(Richerson & Boyd, 2005, p. 178). Obviously, Richerson and Boyd would not dream of heeding that advice in their personal lives, nor would any other sensible parent except for the crudest pop-sociobiologist. Helping our children with their homework is exactly what we want, even after reflecting on the likely fitness-reducing effects. Though our preferences are themselves shaped by cultural evolution, as both Dennett and Richerson and Boyd point out ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Dennett</Author><Year>1995</Year><RecNum>1854</RecNum><Pages>329-330</Pages><DisplayText>(Dennett, 1995, pp. 329-330)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1854</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1380803252">1854</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dennett, Daniel C.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Darwin&apos;s dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life</title></titles><dates><year>1995</year></dates><pub-location>New York</pub-location><publisher>Simon &amp; Schuster</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Dennett, 1995, pp. 329-330), it does not seem useful to describe the memes for education as “selfish”, given that they are actively fostered and promoted by their conscious vectors. Remember Millikan’s challenge: the memes for celibacy or contraceptives or universal education thwart our selfish genes, but they have not introduced any novel purpose in the world. The purposes of contraceptives are our purposes – they are explicitly represented by human producers and consumers. For example, condoms provide shortcuts to the carrot which Mother Nature dangles in front of our noses, all the while deflecting from the goals she had in mind. Though it is true that a condom is itself a piece of cultural technology, pruned and perfected by the efforts of many minds, its purpose of preventing insemination is not a freely-floating memetic one, but has always been firmly anchored in the minds of conscious agents. My own reflective goals (e.g. having sex without spawning offspring) may be perfectly maladaptive in their own right, whether or not I use evolved cultural technology to achieve them. Child adoption, contraceptives, celibacy and exclusive homosexuality are all equally “parasitic” from the gene’s point of view, but in the words of Steven Pinker, himself voluntarily childless, “if my genes don't like it, they can go jump in the lake” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Pinker</Author><Year>1997</Year><RecNum>1077</RecNum><Pages>52</Pages><DisplayText>(Pinker, 1997, p. 52)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1077</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1289215178">1077</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">1006</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Pinker, Steven</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>How the mind works</title></titles><pages>xii, 660 p.</pages><keywords><keyword>Cognitive neuroscience.</keyword><keyword>Neuropsychology.</keyword><keyword>Natural selection.</keyword><keyword>Human evolution.</keyword><keyword>Psychology.</keyword></keywords><dates><year>1997</year></dates><pub-location>New York</pub-location><publisher>Norton</publisher><isbn>0393045358</isbn><accession-num>1178888</accession-num><call-num>Jefferson or Adams Building Reading Rooms QP360.5; .P56 1997</call-num></record></Cite></EndNote>(Pinker, 1997, p. 52). In this paper, we are looking for a divergence of interests between me and my memes, not between my memes and my genes. The difference between the two normative standards may be illustrated with one of Richerson and Boyd’s own examples: the pro-natalist ideologies of the Hutterites and Amish. These closed-knit and insular communities have succeeded in stemming the tide of what Richerson and Boyd call “maladaptive” modern culture, and have so far resisted the demographic transition observed everywhere around them. In Richerson & Boyd’s framework, Hutterite ideology inoculates its hosts against the mind parasites of modernity – such as consumerism and materialism and the idea of women’s rights – to which the rest of us have succumbed. But perhaps it is the other way around: perhaps the Hutterite belief system is the mind parasite itself, rather than the firewall against it. After all, Hutterite memes may well benefit the genetic interests of their hosts, but they do not necessarily make for fulfilling and happy lives (see further).If we are to retain Dennett’s classification between mutualists, commensals and parasites, therefore, we think it is better to define those categories with respect to human interests, not to genetic interests. There may be contexts where it is useful to contrast the interests of genes and memes, but we should not lose track of the intermediate (and more important) perspective of human agency. Memes that are “parasitic” from the perspective of my genes may simply be the outcome of deliberate human choices. Talk of “selfish memes” and “rogue culture” can be misleading here, as if humans are the hapless victims of the ideas of modernity. These are not novel memetic purposes, but distinctively human ones. Finally, now that we have laid to rest the inflated claims of panmemetics, sidestepped the question of biological maladaptiveness, and disentangled genetic from personal interests, it is time to present what we consider Exhibit A of the meme’s eye view. Doxastic parasitesExplaining the Appeal of Misbelief“Like computer viruses, successful mind viruses will tend to be hard for their victims to detect. If you are the victim of one, the chances are that you won't know it, and may even vigorously deny it.” Richard Dawkins, Viruses of the Mind ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite ExcludeAuth="1"><Author>Dawkins</Author><Year>1993</Year><RecNum>969</RecNum><Pages>20</Pages><DisplayText>(1993, p. 20)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>969</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1284038070">969</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">941</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book Section">5</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dawkins, Richard</author></authors><secondary-authors><author>Dahlbom, B.</author></secondary-authors></contributors><titles><title>Viruses of the mind</title><secondary-title>Dennett and his critics: Demystifying mind</secondary-title></titles><pages>13-27</pages><dates><year>1993</year></dates><pub-location>Oxford</pub-location><publisher>Blackwell</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(1993, p. 20)There is a sense in which doxastic memes (i.e. beliefs) are much more “infectious” than other types of culture. This is because they command assent. Being exposed to the right sort of evidence for belief X suffices for you to be become a carrier of X, like in the earthquake example above. It is a conceptual truth about beliefs that we do not choose our own ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Adler</Author><Year>2002</Year><RecNum>2215</RecNum><DisplayText>(Adler, 2002)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2215</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1427741572">2215</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Adler, Jonathan</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Belief&apos;s own ethics</title></titles><dates><year>2002</year></dates><pub-location>London</pub-location><publisher>MIT Press</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Adler, 2002). Rather, they impose themselves upon us, in the manner of uninvited dinner guests, refusing to leave even as we try to get rid of them. We can freely choose not spread a rumor, or sing a song, or tell a lame joke. With a modicum of self-control, we can even choose not to use an annoying buzzword, hum a catchy tune, or copy a mannerism. But we cannot freely chose not to believe something, if we have been exposed to appropriate evidence ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Adler</Author><Year>2002</Year><RecNum>2215</RecNum><DisplayText>(Adler, 2002)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2215</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1427741572">2215</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Adler, Jonathan</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Belief&apos;s own ethics</title></titles><dates><year>2002</year></dates><pub-location>London</pub-location><publisher>MIT Press</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Adler, 2002). In the case of blatant and palpable truths, exposed right in front of our noses, the infection rate is nearly perfect.What about beliefs that fail to correspond with reality, i.e. misbeliefs? Most such beliefs are quickly weeded out when we stumble upon evidence that disproves them, or fail to find any evidence that confirms them. Others misbeliefs, however, may be unlikely to encounter any destabilizing evidence. They may be difficult to falsify or too obscure to be open to epistemic scrutiny, there may be taboos or practical limitations preventing investigation, or they may be coupled with other beliefs that prevent their falsification ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Talmont-Kaminski</Author><Year>2013</Year><RecNum>1411</RecNum><DisplayText>(Dennett, 2006; Talmont-Kaminski, 2013)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1411</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1364202418">1411</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">1263</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Talmont-Kaminski, K.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Religion As Magical Ideology: How the Supernatural Reflects Rationality</title></titles><dates><year>2013</year></dates><publisher>Isd</publisher><isbn>9781844656448</isbn><urls><related-urls><url> app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="0">481</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">562</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dennett, Daniel C.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Breaking the spell: Religion as a natural phenomenon</title></titles><dates><year>2006</year></dates><pub-location>New York, N.Y.</pub-location><publisher>Viking (Penguin)</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Dennett, 2006; Talmont-Kaminski, 2013). David Haig has suggested that the most likely candidates for the role of selfish meme are to be found in complexes of beliefs: “The place to look for sophisticated adaptation and selfishness will be in coherent ideologies, large ‘asexual’ meme complexes that are transmitted as a unit with high fidelity of transmission” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Haig</Author><Year>2007</Year><RecNum>2570</RecNum><Pages>63</Pages><DisplayText>(Haig, 2007, p. 63)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2570</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1470843133">2570</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book Section">5</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Haig, David</author></authors><secondary-authors><author>Ridley, Mark</author></secondary-authors></contributors><titles><title>The gene meme</title><secondary-title>Richard Dawkins: How a Scientist Changed the Way We Think </secondary-title></titles><pages>50-65</pages><dates><year>2007</year></dates></record></Cite></EndNote>(Haig, 2007, p. 63). Sterelny, on the other hand, is more skeptical of the usefulness of the meme’s eye view for explaining the virulence of certain misbeliefs, even though he is sympathetic to other applications of memetics (in particular to physical artifacts). The main reason for his skepticism is that, for him, an explanation of the popularity of misbeliefs should fall directly out of a description of the workings of the human mind, without any need for the meme’s eye view:The crucial problem is one of human psychology: explaining why we find occult-force explanations credible. Once we find out why humans find credible explanations of their environment in terms of occult forces, what else is there to explain? ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Sterelny</Author><Year>2006</Year><RecNum>1436</RecNum><Pages>159</Pages><DisplayText>(Sterelny, 2006, p. 159)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1436</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1364770011">1436</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">1285</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Sterelny, Kim</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Memes revisited</title><secondary-title>The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science</full-title></periodical><pages>145-165</pages><volume>57</volume><number>1</number><dates><year>2006</year></dates><isbn>0007-0882</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Sterelny, 2006, p. 159) […] the socially-mediated flow of false belief does not turn on the nature of the beliefs themselves but on the details of human psychology. Once we understand the psychology of religious belief, there is no phenomenon that a meme theory and only a meme theory can explain. ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Sterelny</Author><Year>2006</Year><RecNum>1436</RecNum><Pages>162</Pages><DisplayText>(Sterelny, 2006, p. 162)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1436</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1364770011">1436</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">1285</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Sterelny, Kim</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Memes revisited</title><secondary-title>The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science</full-title></periodical><pages>145-165</pages><volume>57</volume><number>1</number><dates><year>2006</year></dates><isbn>0007-0882</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Sterelny, 2006, p. 162)Sterelny is right that what makes for an attractive misbelief depends, among other things, on particular and contingent properties of the human mind. But we will now argue that certain systems of misbeliefs may exploit our cognitive foibles in ingenious and unpredictable ways, which cannot be simply read off of human psychology. By way of analogy, consider that adaptations in the living world also depend (obviously) on the details of the selective pressure in the environment. For instance, eyes will only evolve in a transparent medium, or they would be completely useless. However, from this observation it does not follow that merely studying environments will furnish a deep appreciation of the adaptive design of the camera eye. Just as stable features of a physical environment may lead to robust adaptive design in a living organism, the stable features of human psychology may give rise to robust adaptive solutions. Moreover, as we will see in our case study about witch persecutions (see further), systems of misbelief adapt not just to the make-up of the human mind, but also to local historical and cultural conditions. This makes Sterelny’s reduction of the question of the pervasiveness of certain misbelief to “details of human psychology” even more problematic.In earlier publications, we have documented the many ways in which systems of misbeliefs are remarkably resilient in the face of counterevidence, and display features that ensure spurious confirmations PEVuZE5vdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5Cb3Vkcnk8L0F1dGhvcj48WWVhcj4yMDExPC9ZZWFyPjxS

ZWNOdW0+NzI5PC9SZWNOdW0+PERpc3BsYXlUZXh0PihCb3VkcnksIEJsYW5ja2UsICZhbXA7IFBp

Z2xpdWNjaSwgMjAxNTsgQm91ZHJ5ICZhbXA7IEJyYWVja21hbiwgMjAxMSwgMjAxMik8L0Rpc3Bs

YXlUZXh0PjxyZWNvcmQ+PHJlYy1udW1iZXI+NzI5PC9yZWMtbnVtYmVyPjxmb3JlaWduLWtleXM+

PGtleSBhcHA9IkVOIiBkYi1pZD0iZXM5dHR2c2QxcDJ4YXRldDVldHB2ZXhuMDJ3OTlyNXMwZXRk

IiB0aW1lc3RhbXA9IjEyNjg2NzA0OTUiPjcyOTwva2V5PjxrZXkgYXBwPSJFTldlYiIgZGItaWQ9

IlI3Qllhd3J0bUNZQUFBS21mS0EiPjc5ODwva2V5PjwvZm9yZWlnbi1rZXlzPjxyZWYtdHlwZSBu

YW1lPSJKb3VybmFsIEFydGljbGUiPjE3PC9yZWYtdHlwZT48Y29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjxhdXRob3Jz

PjxhdXRob3I+Qm91ZHJ5LCBNYWFydGVuPC9hdXRob3I+PGF1dGhvcj5CcmFlY2ttYW4sIEpvaGFu

PC9hdXRob3I+PC9hdXRob3JzPjwvY29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjx0aXRsZXM+PHRpdGxlPkltbXVuaXpp

bmcgc3RyYXRlZ2llcyAmYW1wOyBlcGlzdGVtaWMgZGVmZW5zZSBtZWNoYW5pc21zPC90aXRsZT48

c2Vjb25kYXJ5LXRpdGxlPlBoaWxvc29waGlhPC9zZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+PHBl

cmlvZGljYWw+PGZ1bGwtdGl0bGU+UGhpbG9zb3BoaWE8L2Z1bGwtdGl0bGU+PC9wZXJpb2RpY2Fs

PjxwYWdlcz4xNDUtMTYxPC9wYWdlcz48dm9sdW1lPjM5PC92b2x1bWU+PG51bWJlcj4xPC9udW1i

ZXI+PGRhdGVzPjx5ZWFyPjIwMTE8L3llYXI+PC9kYXRlcz48ZWxlY3Ryb25pYy1yZXNvdXJjZS1u

dW0+MTAuMTAwNy9zMTE0MDYtMDEwLTkyNTQtOTwvZWxlY3Ryb25pYy1yZXNvdXJjZS1udW0+PC9y

ZWNvcmQ+PC9DaXRlPjxDaXRlPjxBdXRob3I+Qm91ZHJ5PC9BdXRob3I+PFllYXI+MjAxMjwvWWVh

cj48UmVjTnVtPjg0NDwvUmVjTnVtPjxyZWNvcmQ+PHJlYy1udW1iZXI+ODQ0PC9yZWMtbnVtYmVy

Pjxmb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PGtleSBhcHA9IkVOIiBkYi1pZD0iZXM5dHR2c2QxcDJ4YXRldDVldHB2

ZXhuMDJ3OTlyNXMwZXRkIiB0aW1lc3RhbXA9IjEyNzM3NDQ3OTIiPjg0NDwva2V5PjxrZXkgYXBw

PSJFTldlYiIgZGItaWQ9IlI3Qllhd3J0bUNZQUFBS21mS0EiPjg0NTwva2V5PjwvZm9yZWlnbi1r

ZXlzPjxyZWYtdHlwZSBuYW1lPSJKb3VybmFsIEFydGljbGUiPjE3PC9yZWYtdHlwZT48Y29udHJp

YnV0b3JzPjxhdXRob3JzPjxhdXRob3I+Qm91ZHJ5LCBNYWFydGVuPC9hdXRob3I+PGF1dGhvcj5C

cmFlY2ttYW4sIEpvaGFuPC9hdXRob3I+PC9hdXRob3JzPjwvY29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjx0aXRsZXM+

PHRpdGxlPkhvdyBDb252ZW5pZW50ISBUaGUgRXBpc3RlbWljIFJhdGlvbmFsZSBvZiBTZWxmLXZh

bGlkYXRpbmcgQmVsaWVmIFN5c3RlbXM8L3RpdGxlPjxzZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0bGU+UGhpbG9zb3Bo

aWNhbCBQc3ljaG9sb2d5PC9zZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+PHBlcmlvZGljYWw+PGZ1

bGwtdGl0bGU+UGhpbG9zb3BoaWNhbCBQc3ljaG9sb2d5PC9mdWxsLXRpdGxlPjxhYmJyLTE+UGhp

bC4gUHN5Y2g8L2FiYnItMT48L3BlcmlvZGljYWw+PHBhZ2VzPjM0MS0zNjQ8L3BhZ2VzPjx2b2x1

bWU+MjU8L3ZvbHVtZT48bnVtYmVyPjM8L251bWJlcj48ZGF0ZXM+PHllYXI+MjAxMjwveWVhcj48

L2RhdGVzPjxlbGVjdHJvbmljLXJlc291cmNlLW51bT4xMC4xMDgwLzA5NTE1MDg5LjIwMTEuNTc5

NDIwPC9lbGVjdHJvbmljLXJlc291cmNlLW51bT48L3JlY29yZD48L0NpdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhv

cj5Cb3Vkcnk8L0F1dGhvcj48WWVhcj4yMDE1PC9ZZWFyPjxSZWNOdW0+MjE1MTwvUmVjTnVtPjxy

ZWNvcmQ+PHJlYy1udW1iZXI+MjE1MTwvcmVjLW51bWJlcj48Zm9yZWlnbi1rZXlzPjxrZXkgYXBw

PSJFTiIgZGItaWQ9ImVzOXR0dnNkMXAyeGF0ZXQ1ZXRwdmV4bjAydzk5cjVzMGV0ZCIgdGltZXN0

YW1wPSIxNDAzNDMyNjg4Ij4yMTUxPC9rZXk+PC9mb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PHJlZi10eXBlIG5hbWU9

IkpvdXJuYWwgQXJ0aWNsZSI+MTc8L3JlZi10eXBlPjxjb250cmlidXRvcnM+PGF1dGhvcnM+PGF1

dGhvcj5Cb3VkcnksIE1hYXJ0ZW48L2F1dGhvcj48YXV0aG9yPkJsYW5ja2UsIFMuPC9hdXRob3I+

PGF1dGhvcj5QaWdsaXVjY2ksIE0uPC9hdXRob3I+PC9hdXRob3JzPjwvY29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjx0

aXRsZXM+PHRpdGxlPldoYXQgTWFrZXMgV2VpcmQgQmVsaWVmcyBUaHJpdmU/IFRoZSBFcGlkZW1p

b2xvZ3kgb2YgUHNldWRvc2NpZW5jZTwvdGl0bGU+PHNlY29uZGFyeS10aXRsZT5QaGlsb3NvcGhp

Y2FsIFBzeWNob2xvZ3k8L3NlY29uZGFyeS10aXRsZT48L3RpdGxlcz48cGVyaW9kaWNhbD48ZnVs

bC10aXRsZT5QaGlsb3NvcGhpY2FsIFBzeWNob2xvZ3k8L2Z1bGwtdGl0bGU+PGFiYnItMT5QaGls

LiBQc3ljaDwvYWJici0xPjwvcGVyaW9kaWNhbD48cGFnZXM+MTE3Ny0xMTk4PC9wYWdlcz48dm9s

dW1lPjI4PC92b2x1bWU+PG51bWJlcj44PC9udW1iZXI+PGRhdGVzPjx5ZWFyPjIwMTU8L3llYXI+

PC9kYXRlcz48L3JlY29yZD48L0NpdGU+PC9FbmROb3RlPgB=

ADDIN EN.CITE PEVuZE5vdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhvcj5Cb3Vkcnk8L0F1dGhvcj48WWVhcj4yMDExPC9ZZWFyPjxS

ZWNOdW0+NzI5PC9SZWNOdW0+PERpc3BsYXlUZXh0PihCb3VkcnksIEJsYW5ja2UsICZhbXA7IFBp

Z2xpdWNjaSwgMjAxNTsgQm91ZHJ5ICZhbXA7IEJyYWVja21hbiwgMjAxMSwgMjAxMik8L0Rpc3Bs

YXlUZXh0PjxyZWNvcmQ+PHJlYy1udW1iZXI+NzI5PC9yZWMtbnVtYmVyPjxmb3JlaWduLWtleXM+

PGtleSBhcHA9IkVOIiBkYi1pZD0iZXM5dHR2c2QxcDJ4YXRldDVldHB2ZXhuMDJ3OTlyNXMwZXRk

IiB0aW1lc3RhbXA9IjEyNjg2NzA0OTUiPjcyOTwva2V5PjxrZXkgYXBwPSJFTldlYiIgZGItaWQ9

IlI3Qllhd3J0bUNZQUFBS21mS0EiPjc5ODwva2V5PjwvZm9yZWlnbi1rZXlzPjxyZWYtdHlwZSBu

YW1lPSJKb3VybmFsIEFydGljbGUiPjE3PC9yZWYtdHlwZT48Y29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjxhdXRob3Jz

PjxhdXRob3I+Qm91ZHJ5LCBNYWFydGVuPC9hdXRob3I+PGF1dGhvcj5CcmFlY2ttYW4sIEpvaGFu

PC9hdXRob3I+PC9hdXRob3JzPjwvY29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjx0aXRsZXM+PHRpdGxlPkltbXVuaXpp

bmcgc3RyYXRlZ2llcyAmYW1wOyBlcGlzdGVtaWMgZGVmZW5zZSBtZWNoYW5pc21zPC90aXRsZT48

c2Vjb25kYXJ5LXRpdGxlPlBoaWxvc29waGlhPC9zZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+PHBl

cmlvZGljYWw+PGZ1bGwtdGl0bGU+UGhpbG9zb3BoaWE8L2Z1bGwtdGl0bGU+PC9wZXJpb2RpY2Fs

PjxwYWdlcz4xNDUtMTYxPC9wYWdlcz48dm9sdW1lPjM5PC92b2x1bWU+PG51bWJlcj4xPC9udW1i

ZXI+PGRhdGVzPjx5ZWFyPjIwMTE8L3llYXI+PC9kYXRlcz48ZWxlY3Ryb25pYy1yZXNvdXJjZS1u

dW0+MTAuMTAwNy9zMTE0MDYtMDEwLTkyNTQtOTwvZWxlY3Ryb25pYy1yZXNvdXJjZS1udW0+PC9y

ZWNvcmQ+PC9DaXRlPjxDaXRlPjxBdXRob3I+Qm91ZHJ5PC9BdXRob3I+PFllYXI+MjAxMjwvWWVh

cj48UmVjTnVtPjg0NDwvUmVjTnVtPjxyZWNvcmQ+PHJlYy1udW1iZXI+ODQ0PC9yZWMtbnVtYmVy

Pjxmb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PGtleSBhcHA9IkVOIiBkYi1pZD0iZXM5dHR2c2QxcDJ4YXRldDVldHB2

ZXhuMDJ3OTlyNXMwZXRkIiB0aW1lc3RhbXA9IjEyNzM3NDQ3OTIiPjg0NDwva2V5PjxrZXkgYXBw

PSJFTldlYiIgZGItaWQ9IlI3Qllhd3J0bUNZQUFBS21mS0EiPjg0NTwva2V5PjwvZm9yZWlnbi1r

ZXlzPjxyZWYtdHlwZSBuYW1lPSJKb3VybmFsIEFydGljbGUiPjE3PC9yZWYtdHlwZT48Y29udHJp

YnV0b3JzPjxhdXRob3JzPjxhdXRob3I+Qm91ZHJ5LCBNYWFydGVuPC9hdXRob3I+PGF1dGhvcj5C

cmFlY2ttYW4sIEpvaGFuPC9hdXRob3I+PC9hdXRob3JzPjwvY29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjx0aXRsZXM+

PHRpdGxlPkhvdyBDb252ZW5pZW50ISBUaGUgRXBpc3RlbWljIFJhdGlvbmFsZSBvZiBTZWxmLXZh

bGlkYXRpbmcgQmVsaWVmIFN5c3RlbXM8L3RpdGxlPjxzZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0bGU+UGhpbG9zb3Bo

aWNhbCBQc3ljaG9sb2d5PC9zZWNvbmRhcnktdGl0bGU+PC90aXRsZXM+PHBlcmlvZGljYWw+PGZ1

bGwtdGl0bGU+UGhpbG9zb3BoaWNhbCBQc3ljaG9sb2d5PC9mdWxsLXRpdGxlPjxhYmJyLTE+UGhp

bC4gUHN5Y2g8L2FiYnItMT48L3BlcmlvZGljYWw+PHBhZ2VzPjM0MS0zNjQ8L3BhZ2VzPjx2b2x1

bWU+MjU8L3ZvbHVtZT48bnVtYmVyPjM8L251bWJlcj48ZGF0ZXM+PHllYXI+MjAxMjwveWVhcj48

L2RhdGVzPjxlbGVjdHJvbmljLXJlc291cmNlLW51bT4xMC4xMDgwLzA5NTE1MDg5LjIwMTEuNTc5

NDIwPC9lbGVjdHJvbmljLXJlc291cmNlLW51bT48L3JlY29yZD48L0NpdGU+PENpdGU+PEF1dGhv

cj5Cb3Vkcnk8L0F1dGhvcj48WWVhcj4yMDE1PC9ZZWFyPjxSZWNOdW0+MjE1MTwvUmVjTnVtPjxy

ZWNvcmQ+PHJlYy1udW1iZXI+MjE1MTwvcmVjLW51bWJlcj48Zm9yZWlnbi1rZXlzPjxrZXkgYXBw

PSJFTiIgZGItaWQ9ImVzOXR0dnNkMXAyeGF0ZXQ1ZXRwdmV4bjAydzk5cjVzMGV0ZCIgdGltZXN0

YW1wPSIxNDAzNDMyNjg4Ij4yMTUxPC9rZXk+PC9mb3JlaWduLWtleXM+PHJlZi10eXBlIG5hbWU9

IkpvdXJuYWwgQXJ0aWNsZSI+MTc8L3JlZi10eXBlPjxjb250cmlidXRvcnM+PGF1dGhvcnM+PGF1

dGhvcj5Cb3VkcnksIE1hYXJ0ZW48L2F1dGhvcj48YXV0aG9yPkJsYW5ja2UsIFMuPC9hdXRob3I+

PGF1dGhvcj5QaWdsaXVjY2ksIE0uPC9hdXRob3I+PC9hdXRob3JzPjwvY29udHJpYnV0b3JzPjx0

aXRsZXM+PHRpdGxlPldoYXQgTWFrZXMgV2VpcmQgQmVsaWVmcyBUaHJpdmU/IFRoZSBFcGlkZW1p

b2xvZ3kgb2YgUHNldWRvc2NpZW5jZTwvdGl0bGU+PHNlY29uZGFyeS10aXRsZT5QaGlsb3NvcGhp

Y2FsIFBzeWNob2xvZ3k8L3NlY29uZGFyeS10aXRsZT48L3RpdGxlcz48cGVyaW9kaWNhbD48ZnVs

bC10aXRsZT5QaGlsb3NvcGhpY2FsIFBzeWNob2xvZ3k8L2Z1bGwtdGl0bGU+PGFiYnItMT5QaGls

LiBQc3ljaDwvYWJici0xPjwvcGVyaW9kaWNhbD48cGFnZXM+MTE3Ny0xMTk4PC9wYWdlcz48dm9s

dW1lPjI4PC92b2x1bWU+PG51bWJlcj44PC9udW1iZXI+PGRhdGVzPjx5ZWFyPjIwMTU8L3llYXI+

PC9kYXRlcz48L3JlY29yZD48L0NpdGU+PC9FbmROb3RlPgB=

ADDIN EN.CITE.DATA (Boudry, Blancke, & Pigliucci, 2015; Boudry & Braeckman, 2011, 2012). Systems of misbelief seem to exhibit cultural design. They are equipped with immunizing strategies and defense mechanisms, which protect them from critical scrutiny and refutation, and they have features that make them self-perpetuating. Importantly, this design need not be authored. It is more plausible that such design emerges after several successive modifications and combinations, as believers stumble upon sticky gambits and useful immunizations, and the most resilient and persistent beliefs tend to propagate in a population. By unwittingly selecting the misbeliefs that are resilient, infectious, impervious to refutation, and conducive to further dissemination, believers are setting a novel evolutionary dynamic in motion, beyond their conscious control. Over time, misbeliefs will be honed by cultural evolution to better exploit both our cognitive make-up and the local cultural context. The misbeliefs that survive this selection tournament and become part of culture ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Sperber</Author><Year>1990</Year><RecNum>464</RecNum><DisplayText>(Sperber, 1990)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>464</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="0">464</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">547</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book Section">5</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Sperber, Dan</author></authors><secondary-authors><author>Gaskell, George</author><author>Fraser, Colin</author></secondary-authors></contributors><titles><title>The epidemiology of beliefs</title><secondary-title>The social psychological study of widespread beliefs</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>The social psychological study of widespread beliefs</full-title></periodical><pages>25-44</pages><dates><year>1990</year></dates><pub-location>Oxford</pub-location><publisher>Clarendon Press</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Sperber, 1990), are the ones that tend to be more intuitive and appealing, more resilient in the face of destabilizing evidence, better adapted to rapid dissemination, more conducive to spurious evidence, less open to epistemic scrutiny ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Sperber</Author><Year>2009</Year><RecNum>2498</RecNum><DisplayText>(Dennett, 2006; Sperber, 2009)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2498</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1461424340">2498</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Sperber, Dan</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Culturally transmitted misbeliefs</title><secondary-title>Behavioral and Brain Sciences</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>Behavioral and Brain Sciences</full-title><abbr-1>Behav. Brain Sci.</abbr-1><abbr-2>Behav Brain Sci</abbr-2><abbr-3>Behavioral &amp; Brain Sciences</abbr-3></periodical><pages>534-535</pages><volume>32</volume><number>6</number><dates><year>2009</year></dates><isbn>0140-525X</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Dennett</Author><Year>2006</Year><RecNum>481</RecNum><record><rec-number>481</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="0">481</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">562</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dennett, Daniel C.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Breaking the spell: Religion as a natural phenomenon</title></titles><dates><year>2006</year></dates><pub-location>New York, N.Y.</pub-location><publisher>Viking (Penguin)</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Dennett, 2006; Sperber, 2009), and more likely to motivate credibility-enhancing displays that infect others ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Henrich</Author><Year>2009</Year><RecNum>2187</RecNum><DisplayText>(Henrich, 2009)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2187</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1419271585">2187</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Henrich, Joseph</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The evolution of costly displays, cooperation and religion: Credibility enhancing displays and their implications for cultural evolution</title><secondary-title>Evolution and Human Behavior</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>Evolution and human behavior</full-title></periodical><pages>244-260</pages><volume>30</volume><number>4</number><dates><year>2009</year></dates><isbn>1090-5138</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Henrich, 2009). In other words – and here we adopt the meme’s eye view already – they become better at deceiving us. The philosopher Stephen Law compared irrational belief systems with “intellectual black holes” in which “unwary passersby can find themselves … drawn in” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Law</Author><Year>2011</Year><RecNum>1257</RecNum><Pages>10</Pages><DisplayText>(Law, 2011, p. 10)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1257</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1310677226">1257</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">1125</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Law, Stephen</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Believing bullshit: How not to get sucked into an intellectual black hole</title></titles><dates><year>2011</year></dates><pub-location>New York</pub-location><publisher>Prometheus</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Law, 2011, p. 10). In the evolutionary dynamic of misbeliefs, human interests do not figure at all, except in the limiting case that, say, any misbelief which immediately motivates suicidal behavior would quickly be selected out of the meme pool. And even then, the very act of suicide may help to broadcast the meme to new receptive hosts. But short of discrete and unwitnessed suicide, there is a still lot of space for deleterious effects. In effect, it would take a conspiracy of benevolent and wise deceivers through the generations to ensure that misbeliefs never take a nasty turn. Naturally, such a benevolent deceiver would not himself accept those misbeliefs, but would carefully select them on behalf of his tribe or community, in their own best interests. He would be like the prophet Bokonon in Kurt Vonnegut’s Cat’s Cradle, confecting systems of bittersweet lies for his flock, without being able to reap their benefits themselves. Absent such implausible benign deceivers, there is only cultural evolution to put trust in. And what has evolution ever done for us? Cui bono? As it happens, examples of such beliefs abound in the anthropological literature, but they are not always given due attention, in part due to the influence of functionalism. In his book Sick Societies, Robert Edgerton ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite ExcludeAuth="1"><Author>Edgerton</Author><Year>1992</Year><RecNum>900</RecNum><DisplayText>(1992)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>900</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1279589239">900</key><key app="ENWeb" db-id="R7BYawrtmCYAAAKmfKA">890</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Edgerton, Robert B.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Sick societies: Challenging the myth of primitive harmony</title></titles><pages>278 p.</pages><keywords><keyword>Cultural relativism.</keyword><keyword>Ethnocentrism.</keyword><keyword>Social perception.</keyword><keyword>Developing countries Social conditions.</keyword></keywords><dates><year>1992</year></dates><pub-location>New York &amp; Toronto</pub-location><publisher>Free Press</publisher><isbn>0029089255</isbn><accession-num>614715</accession-num><call-num>Jefferson or Adams Building Reading Rooms GN345.5; .E34 1992&#xD;Jefferson or Adams Building Reading Rooms - STORED OFFSITE GN345.5; .E34 1992</call-num></record></Cite></EndNote>(1992) has collected numerous examples of beliefs and attendant practices that gravely harm the interests of their hosts. Many of those relate to supernatural misbeliefs. In almost every known culture in the world, disease and other calamities are attributed to supernatural ghosts, demons, gods and witches. In some cultures, there is simply no other theoretical resource for explaining misfortune. Oftentimes, this belief in supernatural evil leads to time-consuming, wasteful, or outright dangerous behavior. Case Study: European Witch PersecutionsIn this paper, we have no space to develop a case study of systems of misbelief in detail. One particularly promising test case for the hypothesis of parasitical culture, however, is the phenomenon of witchcraft beliefs in early modern Europe. Belief in evil supernatural creatures abound all over the world, but early modern Europa witnessed the rise of a particularly virulent strain of ideas about witchcraft that motivated the persecution of tens of thousands of innocent victims. Witches, it was widely assumed, were ordinary Christians who had made a covenant with Satan, giving them the power to cast evil spells. A popular idea was that they convened at regular times during witches’ sabbaths, usually by riding a broomstick or a goat, plotting evil plans to ravage communities. ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Levack</Author><Year>2006</Year><RecNum>2605</RecNum><DisplayText>(Goodare, 2016; Levack, 2006)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2605</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308794">2605</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Levack, Brian P</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The witch-hunt in early modern Europe</title></titles><dates><year>2006</year></dates><publisher>Pearson Education</publisher><isbn>0582419018</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Goodare</Author><Year>2016</Year><RecNum>2602</RecNum><record><rec-number>2602</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308347">2602</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Goodare, Julian</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The European Witch-Hunt</title></titles><dates><year>2016</year></dates><publisher>Routledge</publisher><isbn>131719831X</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Goodare, 2016; Levack, 2006)Why did belief in witches, and the tendency to persecute them, spread far and wide, despite the fact that there are no such creatures? If we want to understand the rationale of witchcraft beliefs, we cannot just ask the witch hunters themselves. It is useless to consult them about the function of their belief in witchcraft. Our question would baffle them, because the answer would be obvious from where they are standing: “Because there really are witches out there, of course, and we had better be aware of their evil ways!” And indeed, belief in the magical powers of diabolical forces made perfect sense in the intellectual world of 16th and 17th century Europe ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Clark</Author><Year>1999</Year><RecNum>2597</RecNum><DisplayText>(Clark, 1999)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2597</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477307946">2597</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Clark, Stuart</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Thinking with demons: the idea of witchcraft in early modern Europe</title></titles><dates><year>1999</year></dates><publisher>Oxford University Press on Demand</publisher><isbn>0198208081</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Clark, 1999). Historians and social scientists with theoretical ambitions have been puzzled by the persistence of the European witch hunts. In the past several scholars had tried to devise functional explanations for the witch trials ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Erikson</Author><Year>1966</Year><RecNum>2529</RecNum><DisplayText>(Ben-Yehuda, 1980; Erikson, 1966; Thomas, 2003)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2529</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1463602966">2529</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Erikson, Kai T</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Wayward puritans: A study in the sociology of deviance</title></titles><dates><year>1966</year></dates><publisher>Wiley New York</publisher><isbn>0471244279</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Ben-Yehuda</Author><Year>1980</Year><RecNum>2600</RecNum><record><rec-number>2600</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308217">2600</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Ben-Yehuda, Nachman</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The European witch craze of the 14th to 17th centuries: A sociologist&apos;s perspective</title><secondary-title>American Journal of Sociology</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>American Journal of Sociology</full-title></periodical><pages>1-31</pages><dates><year>1980</year></dates><isbn>0002-9602</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Thomas</Author><Year>2003</Year><RecNum>2607</RecNum><record><rec-number>2607</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308883">2607</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Thomas, Keith</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Religion and the decline of magic: studies in popular beliefs in sixteenth and seventeenth-century England</title></titles><dates><year>2003</year></dates><publisher>Penguin UK</publisher><isbn>0141932406</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Ben-Yehuda, 1980; Erikson, 1966; Thomas, 2003). Perhaps, some argued, witchcraft persecutions foster social cohesion and protect the rules of civil conduct, by punishing anti-social transgressors. If you are afraid of being accused of witchcraft by your neighbors, after all, you might think twice before being rude or nasty towards them. Or perhaps witch hunts were useful ways of channeling aggressive impulses unto individuals at the periphery of the group, rather than allowing all that negative energy to rampage through more vital parts of the social fabric. After all, early modern Europe experienced several highly stressful social transitions. Or perhaps witch hunts provided some solace by offering explanations for misfortune that had befallen the community, and that would otherwise be unbearably mysterious.However, there is no plausible evidence that witch persecutions performed such services on a systematic basis, either to individuals or society at large, as is now generally acknowledged by most historians ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Hehl</Author><Year>1987</Year><RecNum>2604</RecNum><DisplayText>(Goodare, 2016; Hehl, 1987; Scarre &amp; Callow, 2001)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2604</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308429">2604</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Hehl, Ulrich von</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Hexenprozesse und Geschichtswissenschaft</title><secondary-title>Historisches Jahrbuch</secondary-title></titles><periodical><full-title>Historisches Jahrbuch</full-title></periodical><pages>349-375</pages><volume>107</volume><dates><year>1987</year></dates></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Scarre</Author><Year>2001</Year><RecNum>2609</RecNum><record><rec-number>2609</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477310362">2609</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Scarre, Geoffrey</author><author>Callow, John</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>witchcraft and magic in sixteenth-and seventeenth-century Europe</title></titles><dates><year>2001</year></dates><publisher>Palgrave Macmillan</publisher><isbn>1137243341</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Goodare</Author><Year>2016</Year><RecNum>2602</RecNum><record><rec-number>2602</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308347">2602</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Goodare, Julian</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The European Witch-Hunt</title></titles><dates><year>2016</year></dates><publisher>Routledge</publisher><isbn>131719831X</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Goodare, 2016; Hehl, 1987; Scarre & Callow, 2001). On the contrary, witch hunts often eroded group cohesion, increased mutual suspicion and exacerbated existing social tensions, creating fears about possible revenge from as yet undiscovered witches: “during witch-hunts people tended to draw apart rather than pull together” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Stark</Author><Year>2003</Year><RecNum>2530</RecNum><Pages>217</Pages><DisplayText>(Stark, 2003, p. 217)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2530</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1463603204">2530</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Stark, Rodney</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>For the glory of God: How monotheism led to reformations, science, witch-hunts, and the end of slavery</title></titles><dates><year>2003</year></dates><publisher>Princeton University Press</publisher><isbn>1400866804</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Stark, 2003, p. 217). Another approach to the puzzle of witch hunts is to search for an interested party behind the scenes who might have profited from the persecutions. Perhaps it was a means for the ruling classes to dominate the common folk, or a ploy used by men to oppress women ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Muchembled</Author><Year>1987</Year><RecNum>2606</RecNum><DisplayText>(Barstow, 1994; Muchembled, 1987)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2606</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308836">2606</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Journal Article">17</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Muchembled, Robert</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Sorcières, Justice et Société aux 16 et 17 siècles</title></titles><dates><year>1987</year></dates></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Barstow</Author><Year>1994</Year><RecNum>2598</RecNum><record><rec-number>2598</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308087">2598</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Barstow, Anne L</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Witchcraze: A new history of the European witch hunts</title></titles><dates><year>1994</year></dates><publisher>HarperCollins</publisher><isbn>006250049X</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Barstow, 1994; Muchembled, 1987). “Too well designed” wrote the Marxist anthropologist about the witch-hunts system; the whole enterprise functioned so smoothly that there must have been an underlying motive apart from the stated goals of the witch-hunters ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Harris</Author><Year>1989</Year><RecNum>2603</RecNum><Pages>236</Pages><DisplayText>(Harris, 1989, p. 236)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2603</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308401">2603</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Harris, Marvin</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Cows, pigs, wars, &amp; witches: the riddles of culture</title></titles><dates><year>1989</year></dates><publisher>Vintage</publisher><isbn>0679724680</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Harris, 1989, p. 236). Someone somewhere in those communities must have decided, more or less consciously, to hunt down some witches, and must have benefited from the ensuing course of events, or else they would not have occurred in the first place. Further investigation would eventually unveil the hidden culprit. If witch hunts were secretly orchestrated, however, we would expect them to exhibit certain telltale patterns, for example targeting specific classes of individuals. But history shows otherwise ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Scarre</Author><Year>2001</Year><RecNum>2609</RecNum><DisplayText>(Behringer, 2004; Levack, 2006; Scarre &amp; Callow, 2001)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2609</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477310362">2609</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Scarre, Geoffrey</author><author>Callow, John</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>witchcraft and magic in sixteenth-and seventeenth-century Europe</title></titles><dates><year>2001</year></dates><publisher>Palgrave Macmillan</publisher><isbn>1137243341</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Behringer</Author><Year>2004</Year><RecNum>2599</RecNum><record><rec-number>2599</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308153">2599</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Behringer, Wolfgang</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Witches and witch-hunts: a global history</title></titles><dates><year>2004</year></dates><publisher>Polity</publisher><isbn>0745627188</isbn></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Levack</Author><Year>2006</Year><RecNum>2605</RecNum><record><rec-number>2605</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308794">2605</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Levack, Brian P</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The witch-hunt in early modern Europe</title></titles><dates><year>2006</year></dates><publisher>Pearson Education</publisher><isbn>0582419018</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Behringer, 2004; Levack, 2006; Scarre & Callow, 2001). During outbreaks of witch persecution, the chain of accusations could develop in rather haphazard and capricious ways. The division between persecutors and victims that these theories would lead us to expect, was far from obvious; initiative for the persecutions often came from ordinary people and woman, and males as well as people from the ruling classes ended up on the stake too. Large trials looked like genuine panics. They also rarely occurred at the same place twice. As a key witchcraft-expert explains: “Normally people are not interested in burning their neighbors, and governments do not wish to wipe out their tax-payers” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Behringer</Author><Year>2004</Year><RecNum>2599</RecNum><Pages>149</Pages><DisplayText>(Behringer, 2004, p. 149)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2599</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308153">2599</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Behringer, Wolfgang</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Witches and witch-hunts: a global history</title></titles><dates><year>2004</year></dates><publisher>Polity</publisher><isbn>0745627188</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Behringer, 2004, p. 149).The meme’s eye view suggests a different approach, promising to shed new light on a conundrum that historians and social theorists have been wrestling with for decades. Misbeliefs about witchcraft were molded by cultural evolution, not to serve the interest of human actors, but to further their own reproduction and propagation. If you adopt the meme’s eye view, a number of features of witchcraft beliefs and persecutions suddenly start to make sense. For instance, the widespread notion of large sabbaths, attended by witches in the region, implied that witches knew and were able to identify each other. Furthermore, belief in witches’ powers of flight lifted geographical restrictions on the attendance of the Sabbaths. Such beliefs facilitated long and prodigious chains of accusations.Another portentous feature of witch hunts was the belief that it constituted as a “crimen exceptum”, a crime so very serious that the normal restrictions in torture could be disbanded. But people subjected to torture, in their desperation to end their ordeal, will confess to the most preposterous crimes. As one suspected witch confessed an ever longer list of accomplices under torture, officials in neighboring towns were warned of the infiltration of witches in their communities, leading to “spill-over” effects. As more and more people were convicted and burnt as witches, confessing to exactly the sorts of crimes that their torturers were expecting, the belief in witchcraft became more entrenched over time, while the magnitude of the persecutions became larger over the course of the 16th and early 17th centuries ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Monter</Author><Year>2002</Year><RecNum>2608</RecNum><DisplayText>(Levack, 2006; Monter, 2002)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2608</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477309094">2608</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Monter, William</author></authors><tertiary-authors><author>Ankerloo, Bengt, Stuart Clark</author></tertiary-authors></contributors><titles><title>Witch trials in continental Europe 1560-1660</title><secondary-title>Witchcraft and magic in Europe</secondary-title></titles><pages>3-52</pages><volume>Volum 4: The period of the witch trials</volume><dates><year>2002</year></dates></record></Cite><Cite><Author>Levack</Author><Year>2006</Year><RecNum>2605</RecNum><record><rec-number>2605</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308794">2605</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Levack, Brian P</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The witch-hunt in early modern Europe</title></titles><dates><year>2006</year></dates><publisher>Pearson Education</publisher><isbn>0582419018</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Levack, 2006; Monter, 2002). Books and pamphlets about the urgent dangers of diabolical witchcraft were reprinted frequently, and widely read throughout Europe ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Levack</Author><Year>2006</Year><IDText>The witch-hunt in early modern Europe</IDText><DisplayText>(Levack, 2006)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2605</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477308794">2605</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Levack, Brian P</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>The witch-hunt in early modern Europe</title></titles><dates><year>2006</year></dates><publisher>Pearson Education</publisher><isbn>0582419018</isbn></record></Cite></EndNote>(Levack, 2006).From the meme’s eye view, the rationale of beliefs in large witches’ sabbaths was not the reality of such sabbaths, as the witch hunters believed, but the adaptive value such beliefs conferred on the fitness of witchcraft beliefs: they were more conducive to spreading the witch persecutions. Similarly, the adaptive rationale of eliciting confessions under torture was not to discover real witches, but to trigger a chain reaction of accusations, ensuring that the witchcraft beliefs would live for another day. Specific beliefs about witches – their shape-shifting powers – were designed to make the belief system immune from falsification. The use of “spectral evidence” based on dreams and visions, for instance during the infamous Salem witch trials, provided another spurious source of confirmation. And of course, the popular belief that skeptical minds who doubted the existence of witchcraft were themselves in cahoots with the devil, has a glaring adaptive rationale ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Monter</Author><Year>2002</Year><RecNum>2608</RecNum><DisplayText>(Monter, 2002)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>2608</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="55590vfskzezeme9vx1vzttczxafvftfpzwd" timestamp="1477309094">2608</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Monter, William</author></authors><tertiary-authors><author>Ankerloo, Bengt, Stuart Clark</author></tertiary-authors></contributors><titles><title>Witch trials in continental Europe 1560-1660</title><secondary-title>Witchcraft and magic in Europe</secondary-title></titles><pages>3-52</pages><volume>Volum 4: The period of the witch trials</volume><dates><year>2002</year></dates></record></Cite></EndNote>(Monter, 2002). Such memes, as Daniel Dennett writes, “disable the selective forces arrayed against them” ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Dennett</Author><Year>1995</Year><RecNum>1854</RecNum><Pages>349</Pages><DisplayText>(Dennett, 1995, p. 349)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1854</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1380803252">1854</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dennett, Daniel C.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Darwin&apos;s dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life</title></titles><dates><year>1995</year></dates><pub-location>New York</pub-location><publisher>Simon &amp; Schuster</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Dennett, 1995, p. 349).Now we can return to Millikan’s challenge. According to her argument, evolving memes do not create novel purposes in the world, but merely satisfy the interests of their hosts in a more prodigious and efficient way than individual human ingenuity can muster. Cultural design may not be authored by human beings, she admitted, but it would still serve their interests (or the interests of some manipulator imposing representations on others). The example of witchcraft beliefs, however, offers a promising example of how a system of misbeliefs can evolve a functional rationale of its own which subverts the interests of its hosts. Beliefs in witchcraft have a purpose, but it is not represented anywhere in the minds of believers, and neither does it do them many favors. ADDIN EN.CITE <EndNote><Cite><Author>Dennett</Author><Year>1995</Year><RecNum>1854</RecNum><Pages>78`,164–165</Pages><DisplayText>(Dennett, 1995, pp. 78,164–165)</DisplayText><record><rec-number>1854</rec-number><foreign-keys><key app="EN" db-id="es9ttvsd1p2xatet5etpvexn02w99r5s0etd" timestamp="1380803252">1854</key></foreign-keys><ref-type name="Book">6</ref-type><contributors><authors><author>Dennett, Daniel C.</author></authors></contributors><titles><title>Darwin&apos;s dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life</title></titles><dates><year>1995</year></dates><pub-location>New York</pub-location><publisher>Simon &amp; Schuster</publisher></record></Cite></EndNote>(Dennett, 1995, pp. 78,164–165). In order to appreciate this design, we have to adopt the meme’s eye view, since the beliefs themselves are the only suitable repositories of adaptive purpose. We may prefer to talk of “parasites” or “selfish culture” instead, if we dislike the concept of a “meme”. But, we hope to have shown by now, we need something conceptually equivalent to the meme’s eye view in order to understand what is going on. DiscussionThere are several reasons why memes have not been taken seriously, and not all of them are bad reasons. The overblown claims of panmemetics, with their occasional outbreaks of Darwinian paranoia, have not increased the fitness of the meme meme in the academic world. The success of the meme meme in one environment has even undermined its fitness in another. Precisely because memes have become a staple of popular culture, with millions of Google search results, many academic researchers have treated them with suspicion and disdain. On top of that, there has been a problem of linked loci: because of its origins as an explicit analogue of the gene, the meme meme has been associated with atomist approaches to culture, and the notion of simple copying through imitation. Most of this criticism stems from an outdated conception of what a gene is, and a failure to appreciate the value of idealizations. In fact, some theorists who are critical of memes have broken down culture into discrete units of their own, thus idealizing and simplifying real-life cultural evolution in ways similar to the concept of a “meme”. But for the reasons mentioned above, they have resisted Dawkins’ nomenclature. This would be mostly a semantic issue, if not for the fact that the most important element of the meme concept has been buried along with the term. This is the idea of selfish cultural elements, or mind parasites, which spread to benefit no one but themselves. In this paper, we have tried to unpack this claim with some care, taking issue with more permissive uses of the meme’s eye view in the literature, in particular with the grandiose claims of panmemetics. As signposts on this treacherous terrain, we have used challenges to memetics as voiced by its most thoughtful critics (Millikan, Pinker, Lewens, Sperber). In the end, we argued that systems of misbelief may evolve into full-fledged mind parasites, developing novel purposes of their own, and subverting the interests of their vectors (not just of the latter’s genes). By definition, after all, people have no reflective awareness of their own misbeliefs and the latter’s attendant costs and benefits. If you start thinking about what your beliefs are ‘for’, or what benefits they might confer on you, they no longer have any sway over you. Because of this lack of reflective awareness, systems of misbelief may grow unruly and develop an evolutionary dynamic of their own. In the end, they are selected for reasons that remain opaque to their hosts. People will then be furthering the spread of misbeliefs that, unbeknownst to them, are adapted to ensure their own propagation, even at the detriment of their hosts. Doxastic parasites spread not because they serve human interest, but because they are more salient, attractive, better shielded from critical scrutiny and refutation, more conducive to spurious confirmation, and more likely to elicit credibility-enhancing displays that infect other agentso. We think destructive phenomena like the European witch hunts should be Exhibit A of the meme’s eye view, precisely because it is hard to makes sense of on a traditional understanding of cultural evolution. Our analysis shows novel memetic purposes may arise through cultural evolution of misbeliefs, crosscutting the interests of their hosts. Traditional approaches to witch hunts have failed to find substantial functional benefits accruing from burning members of your own community, nor have they identified culprits who might have benefited from such a course of events (except in some cases). Our proposal is to treat the witchcraft beliefs themselves as selfish agents, furthering their own interests. By doing so, certain patterns of cultural evolution suddenly start to make sense in ways that were invisible to traditional approaches. By taking a pragmatic approach to the notion of cultural parasites, and showing in some detail when the meme’s eye view may be fruitful or even indispensable, hopefully we have allayed some suspicions about meme-talk, as well as tempered the enthusiasm of panmemeticists. To throw out Dawkins’ brainchild with the bathwater, as many critics of memes have done, is to deprive oneself of an important conceptual tool to understand culture. Whether you call them selfish memes or cultural parasites or viruses of the mind, they exist and have real-life consequences. And we need to understand them.References ADDIN EN.REFLIST Adler, J. (2002). Belief's own ethics. London: MIT Press.Atran, S. (2002). In gods we trust : the evolutionary landscape of religion. New York: Oxford University Press.Aunger, R. (2002). The electric meme: A new theory of how we think: Cambridge Univ Press.Aunger, R. (Ed.). (2000). Darwinizing Culture: The Status of Memetics as a Science: OUP Oxford.Barstow, A. L. (1994). Witchcraze: A new history of the European witch hunts: HarperCollins.Behringer, W. (2004). Witches and witch-hunts: a global history: Polity.Ben-Yehuda, N. (1980). The European witch craze of the 14th to 17th centuries: A sociologist's perspective. American Journal of Sociology, 1-31. Blackmore, S. J. (2000). The meme machine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Boudry, M., Blancke, S., & Pigliucci, M. (2015). What Makes Weird Beliefs Thrive? The Epidemiology of Pseudoscience. Philosophical Psychology, 28(8), 1177-1198. Boudry, M., & Braeckman, J. (2011). Immunizing strategies & epistemic defense mechanisms. Philosophia, 39(1), 145-161. doi: 10.1007/s11406-010-9254-9Boudry, M., & Braeckman, J. (2012). How Convenient! The Epistemic Rationale of Self-validating Belief Systems. Philosophical Psychology, 25(3), 341-364. doi: 10.1080/09515089.2011.579420Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (2005). The origin and evolution of cultures. Oxford: Oxford university press.Boyer, P. (1994). The naturalness of religious ideas : A cognitive theory of religion. Berkeley (Calif.): University of California Press.Clark, S. (1999). Thinking with demons: the idea of witchcraft in early modern Europe: Oxford University Press on Demand.Darwin, C. (1998 [1859]). The origin of species. Oxford: Oxford university press.Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Dawkins, R. (1982). The Extended Phenotype: The Long Reach of the Gene: Oxford University Press, Incorporated.Dawkins, R. (1993). Viruses of the mind. In B. Dahlbom (Ed.), Dennett and his critics: Demystifying mind (pp. 13-27). Oxford: Blackwell.Delius, J. D. (1991). The nature of culture. In M. S. Dawkins, T. R. Halliday & R. Dawkins (Eds.), The Tinbergen Legacy (pp. 75-99). Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.Dennett, D. C. (1990). Memes and the exploitation of imagination. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 48(2), 127-135. Dennett, D. C. (1995). Darwin's dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life. New York: Simon & Schuster.Dennett, D. C. (2001). The evolution of culture. The Monist, 84(3), 305-324. Dennett, D. C. (2006). Breaking the spell: Religion as a natural phenomenon. New York, N.Y.: Viking (Penguin).Dennett, D. C., & McKay, R. (2006). A continuum of mindfulness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 29(04), 353-354. Durham, W. H. (1991). Coevolution: Genes, culture, and human diversity: Stanford University Press.Edgerton, R. B. (1992). Sick societies: Challenging the myth of primitive harmony. New York & Toronto: Free Press.Erikson, K. T. (1966). Wayward puritans: A study in the sociology of deviance: Wiley New York.Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford: Oxford university press.Goodare, J. (2016). The European Witch-Hunt: Routledge.Haig, D. (2006). Intrapersonal conflict. In M. Jones & A. C. Fabian (Eds.), Conflict (pp. 8-22). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Haig, D. (2007). The gene meme. In M. Ridley (Ed.), Richard Dawkins: How a Scientist Changed the Way We Think (pp. 50-65).Harris, M. (1989). Cows, pigs, wars, & witches: the riddles of culture: Vintage.Hehl, U. v. (1987). Hexenprozesse und Geschichtswissenschaft. Historisches Jahrbuch, 107, 349-375. Henrich, J. (2009). The evolution of costly displays, cooperation and religion: Credibility enhancing displays and their implications for cultural evolution. Evolution and Human Behavior, 30(4), 244-260. Henrich, J. (2015). The secret of our success: How culture is driving human evolution, domesticating our species, and making us smarter: Princeton University Press.Ingold, T. (2007). The trouble with ‘evolutionary biology’. Anthropology Today, 23(2), 13-17. Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. J. (2005). Evolution in four dimensions: Genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life. Cambridge: MIT Press.Law, S. (2011). Believing bullshit: How not to get sucked into an intellectual black hole. New York: Prometheus.Levack, B. P. (2006). The witch-hunt in early modern Europe: Pearson Education.Lewens, T. (2015). Cultural Evolution: Conceptual Challenges: OUP Oxford.Lumsden, C. J., & Wilson, E. O. (1981). Genes, mind, and ideology. The Sciences, 21(9), 6-8. Lynch, A. (2008). Thought contagion: How belief spreads through society: Basic Books.McKay, R., & Whitehouse, H. (2015). Religion and morality. Psychological Bulletin, 141(2), 447-473. doi: 10.1037/a0038455Mesoudi, A., Whiten, A., & Laland, K. N. (2006). Towards a unified science of cultural evolution. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 29(04), 329-347. Millikan, R. G. (2004). Varieties of meaning: the 2002 Jean Nicod lectures: The MIT Press.Monter, W. (2002). Witch trials in continental Europe 1560-1660 (B. Ankerloo, Stuart Clark Ed. Vol. Volum 4: The period of the witch trials).Muchembled, R. (1987). Sorcières, Justice et Société aux 16 et 17 siècles. Norenzayan, A. (2013). Big gods: How religion transformed cooperation and conflict: Princeton University Press.Norenzayan, A., Shariff, A. F., Gervais, W. M., Willard, A. K., McNamara, R. A., Slingerland, E., & Henrich, J. (2014). The cultural evolution of prosocial religions. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1, 86. Pagel, M. (2006). Darwinian cultural evolution rivals genetic evolution. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 29(04), 360-360. Pinker, S. (1997). How the mind works. New York: Norton.Pinker, S. (2012). The false allure of group selection. Edge, Jun, 19, 2012. Plotkin, H. C. (2002). The Imagined World Made Real: Towards a Natural Science of Culture: Rutgers University Press.Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2005). Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution. Chicago (Ill.): University of Chicago press.Scarre, G., & Callow, J. (2001). witchcraft and magic in sixteenth-and seventeenth-century Europe: Palgrave Macmillan.Sperber, D. (1990). The epidemiology of beliefs. In G. Gaskell & C. Fraser (Eds.), The social psychological study of widespread beliefs (pp. 25-44). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Sperber, D. (1996). Explaining culture: A naturalistic approach. Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell.Sperber, D. (2000). An objection to the memetic approach to culture. In R. Aunger (Ed.), Darwinizing culture: The status of memetics as a science (pp. 163-173). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Sperber, D. (2009). Culturally transmitted misbeliefs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32(6), 534-535. Stanovich, K. E. (2005). The Robot's Rebellion: Finding Meaning in the Age of Darwin: University of Chicago Press.Stark, R. (2003). For the glory of God: How monotheism led to reformations, science, witch-hunts, and the end of slavery: Princeton University Press.Sterelny, K. (2006). Memes revisited. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(1), 145-165. Sterelny, K., & Kitcher, P. (1988). The return of the gene. The Journal of Philosophy, 85(7), 339-361. Talmont-Kaminski, K. (2013). Religion As Magical Ideology: How the Supernatural Reflects Rationality: Isd.Thomas, K. (2003). Religion and the decline of magic: studies in popular beliefs in sixteenth and seventeenth-century England: Penguin UK.Williams, G. C. (1992). Natural selection: Oxford University Press.Wilson, D. S. (2003). Darwin's cathedral: Evolution, religion, and the nature of society: University of Chicago Press. ................
................

In order to avoid copyright disputes, this page is only a partial summary.

Google Online Preview   Download