Political Development: A Critical Perspective



Table of Contents

INTRODUCTION 2

1. THE SEARCH FOR CRITERIA 9

THE CRITERION AS PARTICIPATION 9

2 THE CRITERION AS 42

DIFFERENTIATION

3 THE CRITERION AS CAPABILITIES 67

4 THE CRITERION AS CONVERSION 85

5 The Concept of Development 180

Political Development: A Critical Perspective

By Daya Krishna,

Delhi , Oxford University Press, 1979.

LBSNAA 320.011kri.

INTRODUCTION

There can be little doubt that the concept of political develop-

ment has Become the central pivot around which most of the

recent thought in political science tends to organize itself.

This may bespeak a certain development in the field of political

science itself or in that with which the study of political

science is concerned, viz. the realm of politics itself Both

seem to be the case. The imperial responsibilities of the United

States after the Second World War, coupled with its competitive

role on a global scale against a country with a different

political system, led American political scientists almost

inevitably to view their field in comparative perspective. And

once things begin to be viewed in that way, specially from the

vantage point of a superpower with global responsibilities for

client and protégée states, the distinction between the

'developed' we and the 'underdeveloped' they gets built into the

way issues are seen, questions are asked, and theories

formulated. The political scientist almost inevitably identifies

himself with the polity of which he happens to be a member, and

that to some extent

determines the way he sees the phenomena he wants to study

-scientifically, that is, with detachment and objectivity. The

epistemological problems raised by this determination of the

social perception of social scientists in general and poli-

tical scientists in particular have seldom been the subject of

focal attention by these scientists themselves or by philosophers

concerned with the social sciences. To some extent,'anthro-

pologists in their study of so-called primitive, non-literate

cul- tures have been aware of these problems, along with

historians who have studied literate cultures other than their

own. And it is generally amongst practitioners of anthropology

and history that the concept of development as it was applied to

their fields came to be,seriously questioned. The sociologist

and the poli-

2 Political Development

tical scientist, however, generally look on the study of man and

society as embodied in history and anthropology as not being

scientific in the sense that they are not concerned with the

discovery of laws of the phenomena they study, but only with

their description which at best is sought to be, made

intelligible in terms of meanings which they embody or purposes

they

fulfil. The historian and the anthropologist are supposed merely

to provide the data against which the social scientist may test

his theories. And, if they do attempt to formulate laws, they

quickly become oriented to the same type of concerns and

perspectives which the sociologist or the political scientist

enter- tains.

The early search for comparative methodology had some

such purpose in mind. It was to do what lack of experimentation

precluded or appeared to preclude in the social sciences. The

diversity of cultures and civilizations was supposed to provide

that variety of conditions and combinations which the theorist

in the social sciences would re-quire to test his hypotheses. The

Human Relations Area Files attempt to provide such data, and the

early work of Malinowski, Roheim, Margaret Mead, and

Herskovits tries to do something like this for psychoanalytic

and economic theories. The work of Whiting and Child on

child-training and personality development is another good

example of this type of use of cross-cultural material.

However, comparative studies do not remain confined for long

to what may be called the testing of hypotheses, and they begin

to ask whether the same functions are being performed well or

ill in different settings and thus to judge societies com-

paratively and find whether one is better than the other, at

least in those respects in which they are being compared. The

cognitive enterprise thus subtly turns into an evaluative enter-

prise, without explicitly declaring itself to be such. One reason

for the subterfuge n-iay possibly lie in the fear that the

effective- ness of the evaluation may be jeopardized if it were

to be ex- plicitly declared as such. Another, and perhaps more

subtle, reason may lie in the feeling that the cognitive and the

evalua- tive elements are so intermixed in the situation that to

test a hypothesis is inevitably to make an evaluative judgement

also. The two directions of the cognitive interest, however,

are not merely different but also opposed to each other. The

search

Introduction 3

for laws which have universal validity goes counter

to the idea that there are better or worse ways of exemplifying

those laws. It would be strange to hear someone say that the law

of gravitation is better exemplified by one phenomenon than by

another. Such a statement may be true in some educational context

where the task is to make somebody understand what exactly is

meant by the law concerned. But there are no intrinsic

differences in exemplification, and once one has understood what

a law means, one also understands that the example used by the

teacher exemplifies it in no special, pre-eminent sense. Also,

the law, in so far as it is a law, cannot but be exemplified, and

thus in the purely cognitive perspective, the distinctions of

better and worse can only be treated as something illusory or the

result of the intrusion of non-cognitive interests in a field

where they do not belong.

On the other hand, the intrusion of the category of 'function'

with its correlate notion of 'efficient performance' brings the

idea of 'purpose' into the heart of the social sciences-an idea

whose banishment from nature was supposed to have been

responsible for the triumph of the natural sciences. But once we

begin to talk in terms of 'functions' and their more or less

'efficient' fulfilment, we generally assume that everything that

we are comparing is trying to fulfil the same function and that

the notion of efficiency that we employ happens to be the same

everywhere. But once diversity in functions and differences

amongst criteria of efficiency are admitted, the whole purpose

for which the comparative approach was being used fails to make

sense.

It may be urged that the developmental perspective can be

relevantly built into the strictly cognitive enterprise, if

reality is seen as dynamic rather than static in nature. The

opening of the evolutionary perspective in biology has taught us

to do just that. Everything in the world, and the world itself,

may be un- derstood only when seen in the perspective of time and

in the context of the question 'how has it come to be what it is

today?' But this assumes that 'temporal', 'changing', 'dynamic',

'evolu- tionary', 'developmental' all mean the same thing, which

they obviously do not. To change is not necessarily to evolve,

and to evolve is not necessarily to develop. Change, for example,

may be mere fluctuation or even mere movement, a change of posi-

page 4 Political Development

tion with respect to certain other co-ordinates. And evolution

mayjust be a patterning of change in a particular direction, as,

for example, when we talk of the evolution of the solar system.

Also, to talk of reality as dynamic does not solve the problem

posed by the so-called static perspective, as it is usually

thought to do. If there is a law that governs the dynamics of

change or, in less anthropomorphic language, if the change is in

accordance with a law that can be discerned, then the change is

only apparent, since it is already known what the situation is

going to change into or ' in other words, what change is

going to occur. If the trouble with a static system was that the

laws could not but be exemplified by whatever happened to be,

the situation remains the same even when we make our system

dynamic. Only now laws are exemplified not so much by

whatever is but rather by whatever occurs. The shift from things

to processes does not change the situation in any essential

respect.

Neither the functional nor the dynamic perspective, thus,

seems to necessitate a developmental perspective such as came

into favour in the political sciences in the United States in the

sixties. Nor does the comparative method require it in any

significant way. What could then he the possible reasons for its

emergence and almost uncontested doninance for more than two

decades amongst intellectual circles in that country? @ The

reasons given are of many kinds. But the two most often found in

literature concerned with this subject relate to the desire to

escape the parochial limitations of the earlier state of

political science in the United States which was, by and large,

confined to the American political experience alone, and, to the

failure of U.S. economic aid in fostering economic development

in countries of Asia, Africa, and Latin America. The latter

reason is, perhaps, more important as it continues to be

repeated in almost every work on political development, while

the former has almost dropped out of sight.

However, it is not easy to determine the exact role of the

failure of economic development in countries of Asia, Afdca, and

Latin America in the elaboration of the concept of political

development by political scientists in the United States. One

wonders to what extent it was a part of or, for that matter,

implication or even a cause of political, interventionism, which

introduction 5 ,

nay be considered to be some sort of political aid on

the analogy of economic aid., In any case, if political

development is a precondition of economic development, it

needs to be arti- culated and studied in its own right. But if

it is treated only in the context of economic development,

then wherever there is economic development we would be

justified in assuming that political development has also

occurred.

It is not always made clear in discussions whether political

development is treated as both a necessary and a sufficient con-

dition of economic development or merely as a necessary condi-

tion. As the lament is that economic development is not oc-

curring for political reasons, it may be taken that it is un-

doubtedly considered a necessary condition and perhaps both a

sufficient and a necessary condition of economic development.

The phenomenon of economic development is, however, it- self

varied and diverse in character. It not only continuously

fluctuates even in the so-called developed economics but even

has sharp and prolonged periods of depression in many of them.

Also, the relative economic growth rates of different countries

vary over different perio 'ds of time, as do the growth rates of

the countries themselves. But if changes in the political

sphere were to be theoretically required as necessary

preconditions for change in the econon-iic sphere, we would

have to assume cor- relate precedent changes in the political

sphere without which the changes in the economic sphere would

become unintelli- gible. It would be, so to say, the

fluctuation or decline in political growth rate which would be

shown in the fluctuation or decline in, the economic growth

rate. This would, however, bring into question the autonomy of

the economic realm and the immanent causality which may be

said to obtain therein. This interpretation might appear to

some readers to be a gross misunderstanding of the relations

between the political and the economic realms as argued by the

writers on poli- tical development. It may be argued that what

was actually suggested is that there are certain political

prerequisites to economic development without which no

economic develop- ment can take place. But this is precisely

what is meant by calling political development a necessary

condition and nothing is gained by calling it a prerequisite,

for both mean the same thing and raise the same problem.

2

6 Political Development

If, on the other hand, both the political and economic realms

are treated as relatively autonomous and independent of each

other with the possiblity that either may grow and develop

independently of the other, then the question of independent

criteria for the growth of both may be raised and investigated.

But, then, the failure of the so-called underdeveloped countries

of Asia, Africa, and Latin America to make good economically,

even if true, could not be taken as a sign of their political under-

development. Nor, for that matter, could the economic develop-

ment of the so-called developed countries of North America

and Western Europe be taken as a sign of their political devel-

opment. The two could vary independently and thus would

have to be judged and established independently also.

The search for independent criteria for political development

has taken place, though not in a clear-cut way. Hardly anyone

has faced the question what it would mean for a polity to be

developed even if its economy were stagnating or declining. On

the other hand, the, problem of a developing economy with an

underdeveloped polity has been discussed to a certain extent,

especially in the context of totalitarian societies. To consider or

not to consider the Soviet Union as a developed polity has been

the perennial dilemma of Western writers on political develop-

ment. Those who are inclined to treat the achievement of

democracy as a criterion of political developjnent tend to deny

the Soviet Union the claim of being a developed polity. On the

other hand, those who think in terms of power or in terms of

industrialization tend to treat it as highly developed.

The situation becomes even more complicated because of the

persistent tendency to bring in notions of modernization and

social development which themselves are neither clearly defined

nor demarcated from what is usually regarded as economic or

political development. One is not quite clear whether 'modern-

ization' is the same as 'social development' and 'social develop-

ment' the same as 'economic and political development', as-

suniing the two to be diff@rent. It is surprising that sociologists

who continuously talk of 'modernization' and 'social develop-

ment' do not make their distinctiveness from economic and

political development fairly clear. Perhaps they too feel that if a

society is achieving economic development then it must also be

achieving social development. But, if so, we would have the

introduction 7

same problems as we had earlier with political development.

To cap all this, the notion of 'social evolution' has been

brought in to buttress the concept,of development in all these

fields, as if it could not be sustained by itself. It is interesting in

this respect to note that the notion of evolution has not been

much applied to the domain of economics where the idea of

development is perhaps most securely entrenched. In fact, one

hardly hears of 'economic evolution' though 'social evolution'

is a fairly common term these days and 'political evolution'

is slowly coining into its own. It is tacitly assumed that, 'to he

evolved' is 'to be developed' and 'to be developed' is 'to be

better' and 'what is better' is one's own society. Along with this

is the belief that there is something in evolution which neces-

sitates it to be so. But if it were really so, then, first, there would

not be much virtue in being what one is and, secondly, there

would be no point in lamenting that others have not made good.

What the idea of evolution perhaps does for its proponents is to

ensure that there will be no sliding back for those who have

arrived. But even this could not ensure that they themselves

would be the bearers of the next evolutionary thrust, unless

they chose to believe that evolution had stopped with them. In

fact, if past experience is to be believed, the greater likelihood

is that it would be some other group which would break into

the next phase of evolution, if any. But, as evolution is supposed

to be both inevitable and involuntary, there does not seem

much point in lamenting or lauding it either way.

The questions with respect to political development, thus,

have on the one hand to be separated from the larger questions

of development in general and, on the other hand, to be dis,

tinguished from development in other domains. We propose to

do this by examining in detail the proposed explications of the

concept of political development and the criteria suggested for

assessing and measuring it in diverse ways. Along with this, we

also propose to discuss the larger question regarding what

exactly is meant by the concept of development and what are

the conditions of its relevant applicability to a domain.

1. THE SEARCH FOR CRITERIA

THE CRITERION AS PARTICIPATION

If one is to discuss political development and compare different

politics to find which are developed and which are not, then

obviously one has to find some criterion or set of criteria in

terms of which one can make the comparison. Many have been

the criteria offered, and as the concept itself has been elaborated

primarily in the United States, it would be natural to expect

most of these criteria to be idealized versions of what prevails

or is supposed to prevail in the political system of that country.

The criteria, in order to serve the purpose for which they are

intended, must be measurable directly or indirectly. Also, they

should, to a large extent, be quantitatively variable, as other-

wise a characteristic would either be present or absent and

thus show a country to be either completely undeveloped or

completely'developed politically. Quantitative variability, on

the other hand, would make it a matter of 'more or less', that

is, a matter of relative degree. Also, if the criteria are multiple

in character. they would have to be given relative weightage

with respect to each other so that some generalized judgement

might be reached in cases where they diverge from one another.

The criteria, it should be remembered, are for purposes of

determining the degree of political development that a parti-

cular society may be said to have achieved, especially when

compared with other societies or even with past stages of its

own history. Further, if the concept of political development

is to be treated as even relatively autonomous, then the criteria

for it should at least to some extent be different from those that

are supposed to measure, say, economic or social or cultural

The Criterion as Participation 9

development. This would raise the question of the relationship

between these different realms and whether development in any

of them presupposes at least some development in the others

also. If, however, the concept of 'autonomous realms' itself he

questioned, then we would either have one set of criteria for

measuring all development or development in one sector would

be taken as indicating development in other domains as it is

treated as determining them. The attempt to understand 'social

development', for example, poses this problem. Is 'social devel-

opment' merely a sumination of development in all other fields,

or does it have any distinctive characteristics of its own? If the

former, then obviously to talk of 'social development' is also to

talk of all the other kinds of development which are cncom-

passed in it. On the other hand, if it is something over and

above all of them, then either it has to be treated as itself

sectoral in character or as something emergent from the inter-

relationships between what may be called parts or subsectors

of itself.

Many of these questions have not been faced by writers on

political development. In fact, the relation of sociology to other

disciplines which deal with specific sectors of society has never

been clearly articulated. Besides the Marxists who have been

the most prominent and influential amongst those who have

signalled one particular substructure as foundational and ulti-

mately determining for all the rest, Parsons is perhaps the only

person who has systematically, tried to articulate these relation-

ships. Within the fourfold task of adaptation, goal attainment,

latent tension management, and pattern maintenance and in-

tegration, the political system is primarily supposed to be con-

cerned with goal attainment only, while the economic system

is supposed to be concerned with adaptation and the cultural

system with pattern maintenance and latent tension manage-

ment. The task of integrating all of these is supposed to be the

speciality of the social system, but what exactly the social system

is, apart from the political, cultural, and economic systems, is

not clearly indicated. Also, it is not quite clear as to who sets

the goals which the political system is supposed to try to attain.

And why could adaptation not be treated as some sort of goal

in itself? Similarly, it is difficult to see why pattern maintenance

and tension management do not perform the integrative fune-

10 Political Development

tion which the social system alone is specifically supposed to do.

It may be said that these are just analytic categories which

characterize any action and the so-called concrete subsystems

are differentiated by the predominance of one category rather

than another. But even if this were granted, it does not blunt

the edge of the objections raised. For analytic categories them-

selves should be kept distinct, and it would be difficult for

Parsons to maintain that pattern maintenance and tension

management could be separated, even analytically, from inte-

grative or even adaptive functions.

In considering the problem of any subsector development,

therefore, one has inevitably to face the question as to how it is

related to developments in other sectors. To the extent that the

sector has autonomy, it is bound to have some immanent goals

of its own in terms of which development or lack of development

may be said to occur. Also, as the very concept of autonomy

implies some sort of immanent dletern-tination of the system, the

development or lack of development has to a large extent to be

explicated and understood in its own terms. However, as the

system is actually a subsystem, the autonomy is boun to c

relative in character, and thus determination from the outside,

at least at the margins, has always to be taken into account. Yet,

exactly what the immanent goal of the political system is and

what the immanent causality which operates therein seems to be

nowhere explicitly stated by most writers who are concerned

pre-eminently with the notion of political development. Or, if

it is suspected or even explicitly recognized that there is perhaps

more than one goal immanent to the system, then what the

relationship is between the goals themselves is hardly ever ex-

plicated by these writers.

The trouble, therefore, with the concept of political develop@-

ment is that we do not quite know what is supposed to develop

or whose development we are supposed to discern. Unless this

fundamental point is clarified, the search for criteria is bound

to he diffused and vague, as one would not know what one was

looking for. In a certain sense, we would find this true of most

of the criteria that have been offered by writers in this field.

They are usually so general as to have hardly anything to do

specifically or exclusively with the realm of politics. Perhaps

they are general descriptions of what these writers consider

The Criterion as Participation 11

desirable in their society or even in any society. This reaction is

understandable, as the concern with political development

arose primarily in the context of the failure of many of the new

nations which emerged after the Second World War to achieve

political stability and economic growth.

11

The political system, though a subsystem of the society, is sup-

posed to perform the overall and overriding function of looking

after the society and managing it to the extent that this can be

done at a conscious, corporate level. The first criterion that

comes to mind is, therefore, the extent to which members of any

society participate in the exercise of this function. Certain

groups may be legally or actually deprived of the right to

participate in this process, while even many who have the right

to participate may not choose to do so unless it be made

mandatory for them. The extent of the formal right of participa-

tion in the political process which is concerned with the total

whole, the actual facilitation of the exercise of such a right, and

the actual exercise of the right, then, may be taken as deter-

mining the degree of political development which a society has

achieved when compared to other societies or to itself in a

former stage. In fact, most writers on political development

have used participation as a basic criterion for judging and

measuring political development. But exactly what participa-

tion in the political process is, is. seldom directly discussed. Per-

haps it is assumed that the relevant discussion has already oc-

curred in the debate about democratic and representative poli-

tical institutions. But if that is the end of the matter, there

should be no uneasiness about the populist type of participation

in the political process. Nor, for that matter, should the un-

believably large turnouts in the $ovict and Nazi-style patterns

of election cause such dismay among the democratic theorists of

Western countries.

Deeper than this, however, are the questions relating to the

fact that if the criterion of participation were to be accepted,

then most politics in human history would have to be character-

ized as undeveloped for the simple reason that not only has it

always been a minority which actually participated in the

12 Political Development

political process, but also because the majority generally were

not supposed to participate in it. As most of the existent politics

in the world have been, so to say, non-democratic in the past,

it would be impossible to judge them on the basis of this

criterion and say which is more and which is less developed

even among themselves. They are lumped together and thrown

into the limbo of development where nothing relevant can be

said about them as far as political development is concerned.

In a certain perspective, this may not be considered some-

thing to be deeply worried about, as in the process of socio-

political evolution fundamental breakthroughs may naturally

be expected to occur. And, in fact, as we shall see later on, it

has actually been argued that modernity is such a break-

through in the process of social evolution. But whatever may be

meant by evolution in this field-and we will have occasion to

examine this in detail later on-this would tend to show that

participation' is hardly something immanent to the field of

politics, since otherwise it would have been its central concern

wherever it obtained. Rather, it becomes such a concern only

when a certain level of development is achieved, and this is

perhaps more a result of certain technological breakthroughs,

if 'modernization' is seen as integrally related to 'industrializa-

tion' even if not identical with it.

There are other problems in treating 'participation' as a

criterion of political development. The first and foremost

relates to the fact that it is doubtful whether a majority of the

people can ever actually participate in the political process

except in a marginal or symbolic manner. Any society, in

order to function, has to perform functions other than the

political one. And most of these functions are fairly time-

consuming. The Greek polis, where the male citizens lived what

Hannah Arendt has called 'the public life', had women and

slaves to perform the other functions. Today when we do not

believe that there ought to be slaves in a society, the question is

whether all can live 'the public life' lived by a minority in the

Greek polis and described so eloquently in Arendt's book On

Revolution.' Perhaps automation will permit the slaves and free

human beings to engage in the full-time public activity about

which she writes. But even then, there may be economic pre-

requisites of political activity which everyone mayuot possess,

The Criterion as Participation 13

and there may be large numbers of people who may not want

to devote all or even most of their time to political activity.

This point has seldom been seriously discussed by those

political scientists who have treated 'increasing participation in

the political process' as a criterion of political developme .nt.

They seem to write as if there were no economic costs to politics,

as if all the obstacles to people's participation lay either in legal

disabilities or obstruction by those who did not want any

effective participation by certain groups, ethnic or otherwise.

Also, there seems to be the unstated assumption that if people

had the legal right, the actual facilities, and perhaps the eco-

nomic resources, then they would engage in political activity,

even to the exclusion of other activity if a choice had to be

made.2 But these assumptions are not true. There are sub-

stantial economic costs to political activity and, automation or

no automation, people both have to and prefer to engage in

other activities. Full-time political activity can be engaged in

only by those who either have independent means, or are sup-

ported by somebody else, or are provided for by the party of

which they are members and for which they work. In the last

case, the party itself must have control over economic resources,

and this can come only by having direct command of them or

by serving, to some extent at least, 'the interests of those who

have such command. In the former case, there is bound to be an

erosion of distinction- between party and government and a

tendency towards some sort of one-party totalitarian control of

the state.

The second point is equally important. Most people, at

least in non-crisis situations, have little interest in political

activity. And this for the simple reason that time is a scarce

commodity and if one engages in something, then one cannot

engage in something else as fully. The whole idea of an engaged

or committed consciousness does not merely absolutize the

moral perspective but, what is perhaps even more important,

politicizes it also. The assumption is that moral action is

nothing but political action and that the moral point of view

is itself nothing but a political point of view which, if genuine,

must result in political action. The total politicization of life,

thus, is7 the demand not merely of populist totalitarians, as has

generally been thought, but also of all those who have identified

14 Political Development

the moral with the political and, at least implicitly, of those

who urge 'participation in the political process' as a criterion of

(political development'.

There is still another implication of the 'participation'

criterion hardly noticed by those who have propounded it so

often. And that is the non-differentiation or at least the non-

professionalization of political activity as against most other

activities in the system. Obviously, if everyone can participate

and in fact is expected to participate in political activity, then

there could hardly be any prerequisites required for engaging

,in that activity. This is anomalous, especially in the light of the

fact that most thinkers who treat 'participation in the political

process' as a sign of 'political development' also treat 'differen-

tiation' as a sign of development in general. Yet, if it is a sign of

social development that the realm of politics becomes different-

iated from other realms, then it would also obviously follow

that everybody cannot engage in it to the same extent, unless,

of course, 'differentiation' were. merely to mean 'differentiation'

in the time devoted to it and not the specialized cultivation of

skills for the pursuit of that activity. There is, so to say, a denial

of the need for 'professionalization' for the achievement of

efficiency or expertise in political activity. Yet, the virtues of

'differentiation', as we shall see later, are supposed to lie in its

contribution to greater efficiency. But if this is not true for any

one domain, then one wonders why 'differentiation' per se

should be regarded as desirable or necessary.

The objection is bound to be made that we are misinterpret-

ing the notion of 'participation' as used in the current dis-

cussion about political development. 'Participation', in this

context, does not mean actual participation in the decision-

making processes of the polity. This would be almost impossible

in any large community, as not everybody can be a legislator or

a member of a group that collectively legislates. And if execu-

tive and judicial functions are also regarded as political func-

tions, then it is perhaps even more obvious that everyone,

whether the society be large or small, cannot be involved in a

participatory manner in the performance of political functions.

It is at least theoretically conceivable that technology could

permit the participation of all members of a society in the

discussion and decision on any issue that came before them for

The Criterion as Participation 15

collective consideration. But it would he difficult to think of

ways in which all could he involved in the discharge of execu-

tive and judicial functions. That perhaps is the reason why the

political function is so pre-eminently identified with the enact-

ment of laws and the authority to do so. Even those who have

tried to argue that there is an inalienable political element in

both the executive and the judiciary have generally done so on

the ground that there is an element of rule-making involved in

the exercise of their functions. Cardozo's is one of the best-

known discussions with respect to the judiciary in this con-

teXt.3

'Participation', then, should not be taken to mean actual

participation in the 'law adjudicating' and 'law enforcing'

processes which are generally thought to be important elements

of the total political process. As for the 'law formulating'

process, the thinkers writing on 'political development' have

seldom seriously considered actual participation as a criterion

for its determination, even though there now seems no intrinsic

reason why, in the light of new technological innovations in

communication and computerized calculation, this should not

be regarded as feasible. Perhaps their framework of thought is

still determined by the older situation where the practice of

direct democracy was thought to be intrinsically impossible

because of the large numbers involved, and have not yet caught

up with the possibilities offered by new technological break-

throughs.

There may, however, be another reason for this neglect. The

'participation' envisaged may not be so much for the purpose of

ensuring that everybody has a say in the decision-making pro-

cesses which concern the group as a whole but to ensure that

those who make such decisions do not do so to their own special

or sectional advantage. The right to vote is, so to say, the right

to refuse to re-elect those who have exercised the function of

making the laws and done so poorly in the opinion of those who

are choosing to cast the adverse vote. It is the right to say 'no'

and, by doing so in sufficiently large numbers, to remove from

office those who presumably misused the mandate to rule wisely

and in the interest of the whole. Thus, it should be seen mor 1e in

negative than in positive, forms. It is in insuring against the

possibility of tyranny in the system that the real significance of

16 Political Developinent

'participation' through the right to vote lies'. The primary

purpose of 'participation', thus, consists of ensuring and

strengthening 'political liberty' which may be regarded as a

value immanent to the political realm.

But, surprising as it may seem, the concept of 'political

liberty' plays hardly any role in discussions about political

development. Ludan Pye, who has made a supposedly exhaus-

tive survey of all the definitions offered for political develop-

ment in his well-known work Aspects of Political Development,

barely mentions it. The closest that he comes to it is perhaps in

the definition of political development as the building of

democracy. But that democracy in this context is hardly con-

cerned directly with the issue of 'political liberty' is revealed by

the fact that neither the words 'freedom' or 'liberty' nor the

phrases 'political freedom' or 'political liberty' are to be found

in the index to this book. The whole notion of 'public liberties'

around which the great debate between totalitarianism and

democracy raged seems to have lost all interest for students of

political science concerned with questions of political develop-

ment. In fact, even those who have tried to develop some

measurable criteria of what may be called indicators for poli-

tical development have hardly concerned themselves with the

issue of 'public liberties' in devising their indicators.

The suspicion that 'participation' is not being used by these

thinkers in what we have called the negative or 'public liberties'

sense of the term is confirmed by Pye's statement that 'parti-

cipation may be either democratic or a form of totalitarian

mobilization.'4 But if it can take either of the forms, then

obviously it cannot be linked in any essential way to the notion

of 'political liberty', for the contrast between democracy and

totalitarianism is supposed to lie in this very domain. However,

as already pointed out, as far as Pye is concerned, the differen-

tiation of democracy does not seem to lie in the realm of what

may be called institutional safeguards against the possibility of

tyranny. Rather, he, along with many others, seems to be con-

cerned with what has come to be called in the recent literature

of political science, 'interest articulation' and 'interest aggrega-

tion'. Perhaps it is in the open and almost unlimited oppor-

tunity for 'interest articulation' that the distinguishing charac-

teristic of democracy lies in this framework. It is hopefully

The Criterion as Participation 17

assumed that this unlimited opportunity would facilitate the

achievement of 'interest aggregation' also.

That 'participation' is used in the positive sense can further

be gathered from the fact that many writers have considered it,

to some extent, to be antagonistic to the achievement of effective

capacity or capabilities on the part of the political system. Riggs

has developed a whole thesis out of the supposed dialectical

conflict between participation and capacity and sees in it the

clue to the immanent force determining the development of any

political system.5 And Huntington has seen in the tension

between participation and what he calls 'political institutional-

ization' the clue to both political order and political decay.6

We will have occasion later to discuss in detail the conten-

tions of these thinkers, but it should be of interest here to note

that, even though the relation is supposed to be antagonistic,

participation' is still treated as a criterion of political develop-

ment per se. But if there is a negative correlation between

participation and capacity, and if development is regarded as

enhancement of capacity, then how can participation be

regarded as a criterion of development? Presumably, as in

Riggs, it may be regarded as such because it provides that

negative source of tension which results, at least sometimes, in

a higher stage of development. But then it could not be regarded

by itself as a sign of development. Rather, what is a sign of

development is enhanced capacity, and 'participation' in the

political process becomes one only by virtue of the fact that it

produces tensions which may result in even greater enhancement

of capacity. Thus, in this perspective, it has only an instru-

mental value as far as political development is concerned. And

in case it fails to achieve this enhancement of capacity or, as is

even more likely if Huntington's analysis is to be believed,

results in a decline in capacity, then it can only be treated

either as neutral or as counter-development, depending on

which of the alternatives actually takes place.

The criterion in terms of 'capacities' or 'capabilities' will be

the subject of detailed discussion later on in this work. Here,

however, we would like only to point out the incompatibility

between holding 'participation' as an independent criterion of

'political development' on the one hand, and simultaneously

'dering it as a key factor obstructing 'political develop-

consi

18 Political Development

me-at', on the other. If it is one, then it cannot be the other also.

Yet, most writers tend to argue as if it were both at the same

time, without in any significant way trying to bridge the

apparent incompatibility between the two.

The positive interpretation of the notion of 'participation',

then, may be accepted in the context of its discussion as a

criterion for 'political development'. Yet 'participation', even

in the positive sense, can be of different types, as has recently

been argued by Verba, Ahmed, and Bhatt in their book Caste,

Race, and Polities." According to them, 'participation is, in our

view, not a single, undifferentiated entity. There are alternative

modes of participation that differ significantly in the ways in

which they relate the citizen to his government."' Besides voting,

which is accepted almost without exception as the standard

political act, they mention three other modes: 'Campaign

activity', 'co-operative activity', and 'citizen-initiated con-

tacts'.9 'Campaign activity' obviously refers 'to activity in

political campaigns beyond the act of voting',"0 or, rather,

before the act of voting. Both voting and campaign activity are,

in a sense, direct political acts, assuming a political system

which requires at least some sort of electoral process for the

legitimation of those who wield political authority in the

system.

The other two modes, however, seem basically different in

character. The first, that is, 'co-operative activity', is defined as

activity 'in which the individual works with others-either

informal groups or formal organizations-to deal with the

problems of his community'." The term '.his community' in this

definition is perhaps not meant to be interpreted too strictly,

for otherwise it would exclude activity concerned with causes

which relate to a community that is abstract in character. On

the other hand, if it is loosely interpreted, it would include

activity which transcends national boundaries and thus is, to

that extent, transpolitical in character. Perhaps, therefore, such

exclusion is implied in the definition and only the community of

which one is directly and immediately a member is meant. In

fact, the questions asked to ascertain the respondents' participa-

tion in co-operative activities, as given in appendices B and C of

Caste, Race, and Politics, tend to confirm this interpretational

Yet, whatever be specifically meant by the term 'community'

The Criterion as Participation 19

in this context, it tends to blur the distinction between social

and political activity.

The fourth form of 'political participation' which the authors

have discussed relates to what they call 'citizen-initiated con-

tacts'. By these they mean 'contacts with government officials

initiated by individuals'.13 This category is supposed to provide

an index of 'participation' in the sense that the citizens show by

their actions not only an awareness of the political system and

their expectations from it, but also their initiative in realizing

those expectations from the system. The authors have not made

any relevant distinction between 'citizen-initiated contacts' at a

group level and those at an individual level. Nor have they

considered differences in the content of the citizen's needs in

the context of which the contact with government officials is

made. Nor have they made any distinction between the

legitimacy or illegitimacy of the purposes for the fulfilment of

which the contact is made. The emphasis presumably is on

individual needs as the question is asked in the context of a

person's apprehension of the government as the solver of per-

sonal problems. This is related to some extent to the focus of

the study, which is concerned 'with the way in which deprived

groups use politics to attempt to overcome their deprivation'.14

But however natural in the context of the authors' study, it is

obvious that 'citizen-initiated contact' by a group or its repre-

sentative for the amelioration of collective needs is far more a

political act than an individual initiating a contact on his own

for the fulfilment of his own needs. If the earlier category of

gco-operative activity' tends to blur the line between the poli-

tical and the social, the present one tends to do so between the

political and the personal.

The category of 'citizen-initiated contacts' can, conceivably,

be regarded as an instance of what in the literature of political

science has come to be called 'politicization'. It would be

difficult, however, for 'co-operative activity' to be regarded as

such. It would be such only if its purpose was either to make

demands on the political system or to play some effective role

in the selection of its personnel. In the latter case, it would be

something like 'campaign activity', though far, far wider than

what Verba, Ahmed, and Bhatt mean by the term. In the

former case, on the other hand, it would be very much akin to

20 1 Political Development

what is called 'interest articulation' in the literature of political

science.

Even in the positive sense, then, the concept of 'participation'

can be treated in a wide variety of ways. In fact, the use of the

term 'politicization' has opened the doors wide to almost any

type of relationship with the system being regarded as sqme

sort of 'participation'. Any awareness of the polity in the

cognitive domain and any active relationship with it, whether of

a positive or negative character, can then be interpreted as

some sort of 'politicization' and, thus, some sort of 'participa-

tion' also. It is in this sense that reading newspapers, watching

TV and listening to radio, become as much indices of 'participa-

tion' as membership in political parties, turnout at political

rallies, the percentage of people voting, etc. But through this

extension, the term loses its direct, specific sense of participa-

tion for positive effectiveness in the decision-making process of

a polity. However, even in this specific sense there is some sort

of implicit assumption of legitimacy which makes it seem odd

to say that people taking part in violent or non-violent demon-

strations against the system and going to prison or dying in the

process are 'participating' in the political processes of the

system. Yet there is a large class of political scientists who

treat all evidence of activity which is concerned in any way

with politics as evidence of 'politicization'. In fact, many of

them have a special name for it-'inverse 'articulation by

anomic groups'.",

The term.'interest articulation' is in many of its uses very

close to what in certain other contexts is denoted by 'politiciza-

tion' and in still other contexts by 'participation'. It has itself

been used as a criterion of 'political development', and we will

have occasion to discuss it in that context. But, as far as 1 am

aware, there has been little systematic attempt to differentiate

participation', 'politicization' and 'interest articulation', and

2

delineate the interrelationships between them. Most authors

tend to use these terms interchangeably, depending upon the

context they are emphasizing. Yet it would be useful if the

differences between them are kept in mind. There seems little

point in taking 'interest articulation' as 'participation' in the

political process unless it happens to be what may be called

'structured articulation' required by the system itself. Similarly,

The Criterion as Participa ption 21

all 'structured participation' need not be treated as 'politiciza-

tion'. It may be better if the term 'politicization' is reserved for

areas in which the category of the 'Political' dominates all

others in social life, thought, and action.

But whatever be one's feelings about the way these terms are

or Ought to be used, there should be little dispute over the fact

that if they are treated as criteria of 'political development', then

an increase or decrease in each category should be taken as an

increase or decrease in political development also. Yet an

awareness of this point seems to be absent from the writings of

most of those who show a concern for the problems of political

development. Most of the so-called new nations which emerged

after the Second World War, and in whose context the dis-

cussions about political development originated, started with

universal franchise and have given effect to it in large measure

in their countries. Yet this has seldom been treated as a reason

for considering these countries politically developed. In fact,

the consensus, if any, seems to be that such an enlarged political

participation is one of the root causes of many of the problems

these countries face with respect to their political development.

Huntington goes so far as to relate political instability directly

to political participation and inversely to what he calls 'poli-

tical institutionalization'.16 Assuming that political instability

is a sign of political decay, it would follow that the less there is

of political participation, the less chance there will be for poli-

tical instability in a country. Of course, Huntington treats

political instability as a ratio between political participation

and political institutionalization, but as in most cases institu-

tionalization may be expected to take a far longer time than it

ever takes for political participation to occur, it may be taken as

axiomatic that if a polity seeks both, it would be far easier for

it to achieve the latter rather than the former and thus ensure

the impossibility of its own political development.

A detailed discussion of Huntington's thesis along with a

consideration of stability as a criterion of 'political development'

will be undertaken later on. Here we only want to note that if

an increase in 'political participation' results in political decay,

then it obviously cannot he taken, at least not without any ifs

and buts, as a criterion of political development. But if

$participation' is considered as a value per se which immanently

22 Political Development

belongs to the realm of politics, then its increase should be

regarded as a sign of political development even if it is

considered undesirable on other grounds. And this should

be true even when one extends the notion of 'participation'

to mean 'politicization' in the sense in which violent protests

are supposed to imply some sort of 'participation' in politics on

the part of citizens. Perhaps the only relevant distinction on this

count will be the one between 'structured' and 'unstructured'

participation, and political development will then consist of

the conversion of the latter into the former. Different politics,

then, could be compared on the basis of the extent, range,

intensity, and quality of this participation, and be determined

to be politically more or less developed. Perhaps a participation

index could be developed and the politics ranked in its terms.

But it would not be reasonable then to express dissatisfaction

with a polity on political grounds even when it was doing well

on the basis of the criterion for determining whether it was

politically developed or not.

The objection may be made that we are taking the term

'political development' in too evaluative a sense of the word.

Basically, the term is value-neutral in the sense in which it is

usually employed in the literature dealing with the field.

Almond and Powell, for example, suggest the possibility of

'negative development' when they write that a 'decline in the

magnitude or a significant change in the content of the flow

of inputs may result in "development" in the negative or re-

gressive sense. The capabilities of the political system may

decline or be overloaded; roles and structures may atrophy; the

culture may regress to a more traditional pattern of orienta-

tion.117Similarly, talking even more explicitly concerning 'hang-

ups about evaluation', Almond writes, 'It is symptomatic of the

primitive state of theoretical work in the field that we should be

so anxious about the words we use and the definitions of our

concepts. Biologists and psychologists speak of the growth and

development of organisms, of human growth and development,

assuming that the concept of development includes break-

downs, decay, decline, even the death of the organism. The

literature on economic growth and development is not em-

barrassed by the fact that economics fluctuate in national pro-

duct, that some stagnate, and some decline. We are not bound

The Criterion as Participation 23

by the connotations of the words we use to label our concepts.

These should be viewed as open terms which acquire content

as we use them to order and explain reality."8

Now it is not very clear what Almond is trying to say through

all this. If he means that any characteristic or set of character-

istics which is considered as a criterion of political development

is capable of increase or decrease and thus includes in itself

indications both of political growth and political decay, then

obviously one can have little quarrel with what he is saying.

Any theory of political development would obviously be also a

theory of political decline or decay. But, equally obviously, a

theory is different from the criterion or criteria of development.

True, economists are not embarrassed by facts of fluctuation,

stagnation, and decline in national product; nor are biologists

by the decay and death of organisms. But it is equally true that

they are not in much doubt as to whether an economy is

growing or declining or remaining static or whether an or-

ganism is ill or healthy. The same, unfortunately, can hardly he

said about political scientists and the political development

about which they write so continuously and voluminously. The

day Almond or anybody else achieves this, the controversy

about the concept would cease. However, the situation with

respect to the concept of political development is that nobody

seems to know what constitutes 'political development'. Does,

for example, an increase in 'political participation' constitute

positive political development? Suppo@ing somebody answers

'yes', then he would not be justified in holding any polity to be

undergoing negative political development if 'political parti-

cipation' is increasing in that polity. Also, if there is more

political participation' in one polity than in another, then the

first would necessarily have to be considered politically more

developed than the other. There could also be differing rates of

growth in 'political participation' in different countries, and

these would determine the rates of political development also.

The same obviously would be true of any other criteria which

may he offered for political development.

Yet almost all the criteria which political scientists offer for

'political development' suffer from the defect that their presence

or absence or increase or decrease is seldom uniquely correlated

with what is considered to be either 'positive' or 'negative'

24 Political Development

development. Let this situation be clarified and then we will

know where a country stands with respect to what the author

considers a 'positive' or 'negative' political development. Yet

this is what one seldom finds. Almond talks of economic devel-

opment and suggests that the concept of political development

is equally viable. Yet, if this were so, why is it that we have no

quarterly, half-yearly, or yearly reports on the rate of 'positive'

or 'negative' political development, say, of the United States?

Has any political scientist concerned with political development

tried, for example, to determine whether the 1960-70 decade

was a period of 'negative', 'positive', or 'static' growth in rela-

tion to political development for the United States or, for that

matter, any other Western country? Even if the conclusion be

thought so self-evident as not to require any investigation, the

rates of growth may still'decline or vary between di&rent

countries. There seems something pathological in the almost

exclusive concentration of attention on the countries of Asia,

Africa, and Latin America among thinkers concerned with

political development. Would it not be strange if economists

concerned with economic development had nothing to say

about the econon-iic growth in their own countries?

Almond compares the concept of political development not

only to that of economic development, but also to that of bio-

logical and psychological growth, ignoring the important

differences between the two. One wonders what biological

growth could mean, outside the evolutionary context, except

what is generally known as maturation on the one hand and

health on the other. Maturation, to a great extent, is an almost

inevitable process inherently determined and containing in it

the future seeds of decline and death also. 1 hope Almond does

not mean anything analogous with respect to the concept of

political development. We will have occasion later to examine

the biological analogy in greater detail in connection with the

notion of evolution as applied to social and political fields. But

even here it seems clear that 'political development' is not

being seen on the model of an almost inevitable maturation im-

manently determined, as the complaint usually seems to be that

so many societies fail to make good politically. It is not that

they are stillborn or that they die when young, but that they

do survive and yet somehow fail to mature, which in the bio-

The Criterion as Participation 25

logical realm would be regarded as almost an impossibility.

@ The analogy with health, on the other hand, creates problems

of a different kind. One surely does not get healthier and

healthier and healthier, just as one may get richer and richer

and richer. And, while there are hundreds of ways of getting

ill, there is only,one way in which one may be healthy. It is not

that the phrase 'one is getting healthier' has no application, but

that it has relevance only in the context of recovering from

illness. It would be odd to say 'I am getting healthier' when 1

had not felt ill or weak earlier. Health is not the same kind of

thing as wealth, and Almond does not make clear whether he

conceives of political development on the model of one or the

other. The very fact that he refers to both health and wealth

without showing any awareness of the significant differences

between them may be taken as a sign that he has not reflected

upon the kind of development which 'political development' is.

The same criticism, of course, may be made of all the others who

have written on the subject. They have not even asked whether

'political development'is the sort of development that is capable

of indefinite, incremental growth. Sometimes they seem to ask

this question or something analogous to it. Yet the fact that

they do not stop and seek an answer before moving forward

suggests that. though the question appears to have been asked,

its significance was not perceived at all. Lucian Pye, for

example, asks, '-What is the meaning of "political development"

and what characterizes "modernization" in the realm of poli-

tics? In politics is there the same distinction as in economics

between "developed" and "underdeveloped"? Are there cer-

tain forms and conditions of politics that are necessary to

support, or at least not inhibit other forms of social and eco-

nomic development?"9 Yet, as far as 1 know, he has nowhere

tried to come to terms with these questions. In fact, he does not

seem to have even reflected upon the implications of the ques-

tions asked.

The:first question, for example, involves a distinction between

'political modernization' and 'political development' which

seems to have hardly ever been clarified by Pye or anybody else.,

Similarly, the second question raises in a crucial way the fun-

damental problem of whether the concept of 'political devel-

opment' is analogous in essential respects to that of 'economic

26 Political Development

development' or radically different from it. And, if the latter,

then what is the nature of this radical difference? Are- there,

then, different kinds of development, with almost typal differ-

ences between them? If so, the first task should have been the

analysis, delineation, and classification of different kinds of

development, 'since only then could it be detern-iined to which

type 'political development' belonged. Yet there is nothing of

the kind in Pye or any of the other political scientists who have

written on 'political development'.

The third question raises doubts about the autonomy of

'political development'. If political forms are to be judged as

'developed' or 'undeveloped' only by the fact that they are or

are not conducive to 'social and economic development', then

there is no such thing as 'political development'per se. Rather,

it is to be understood in purely instrumental terms. But then,

many different kinds of instrumentalities may achieve the same

goal, particularly if the goal itself is not too precisely defined.

Also, it is not quite clear as to what exactly is meant by 'social

development' as distinct from 'economic development'. Is it

implied that the two may occur independently of each other, or

that one is a precondition of the other, or that there is some

sort of an inverse relation between them ?

To ask these questions and try to find answers to them is to

become aware that the literature on political development is

silent about them. Lucian Pye raises them, but does not even

attempt any answer. Almond tries to escape these questions by

calling the concepts used in the discussion of 'political develop-

ment' 'open terms which acquire content as we use them to

order and explain reality'. But does this solve any problem?

Fuzziness, ambiguity, lack of clear thought, imprecision in the

formulation of questions cannot be brushed away merely by

calling the terms 'open'. In a sense, all terms having empirical

referents are 'open', but that does not mean that all objections

against any of their specific formulations can be brushed aside

merely by saying that they are 'open'.

The term 'development', then, may be 'open' as Almond

contends, and may even he treated as value-neutral as he wants

us to treat it. But, even then, none of the troubling questions

that we have been raising would cease to exist. After all, if

'development' is treated as a neutral term-and Almond is at

The Criterion as Participation 27

liberty to do so--it becomes something like 'change'. But would

not the same problems arise with respect to 'positive develop-

ment' and 'negative development'? The search for criteria for

'political development' obviously does not relate merely to

finding out whether something labelled 'political' has changed.

This presumably would not be very difficult to do. The

problems basically relate to what is to count as positive 'poli-

tical development' and what as negative. Usually, the term

'development' itself was assumed to have the term 'positive'

implied in it, and almost all the literature on 'political develop-

ment' testifies to this. But even if it were to be disinfected and

made value-neutral as Almond wants, the problems would

reappear with respect to what he himself chooses to call, 'pgsi-

tive' or 'negative' 'political development'.

The same is true with respect to Huntington's claim to have

given up the concept of 'political development'. He writes, 'In

my 1968 book, Political Order in Changing Societies, which other-

wise builds extensively on the 1965 article, the concept of

political development was quietly dropped. 1 focus instead on

what 1 conceive to be the critical relationship between political

participation and political institutionalization without worrying

about the issue of which should be labelled "political. develop-

ment".120 Now, one may not worry about what is to be called

'political development', just as one may choose to cut out the

positive implication involved in the term 'development', but

the obligation to spell out what one considers the positive direc-

tion of change in the realm of politics can hardly be given up so

easily. Though Huntington may not talk of 'political develop-

ment', he talks of 'political decay' all right. In fact, the first

chapter of his 1968 book is entitled 'Political Order and Poli-

tical Decay' in contrast to the 1965 article which was entitled,

'Political Development and Political Decay'. The only change,

thus, is in the replacement of the term 'order' for the term

'development', which presumably provides only a more specific

content to what was meant more generally in the earlier title.

He almost admits as much when he observes in the Preface,

'Economists who write about economic development presum-

ably favor it, and this book originates in parallel concern which

1 have for political stability.'21 Political stability, then, is per-

haps the same as political order, and provides for Huntington

28 Political Development

the criterion for what he considers 'political development'. In

his 1971 article, he says, 'The concept of political development

thus serves in effect as a sign of scholarly preferences rather

than as a tool for analytical purposes.'22 His own preference for

order is fairly clear as he chooses to call the reverse 'political

decay'.

Some of Huntington's arguments against the notion of

'political development' are important and, to some extent,

we ourselves will use them in various parts of our discussion in

this work. But the impression which he tries to create of having

given up the concept of 'political development' is not quite

accurate. Only it is now conceived of as a relationship between

two variables. rather than being singly determined by either of

them. He himself has given the basic equation as

Political Participation

Political Institutionalization' = zull[lcal 'Lnsx:a Dility..

Assuming that political instability is the opposite of political

order, it would follow that

- -. . - - . Political. Institutionalization

Fohtical Urder Political Participation

Further, if 'political decay' is the same as 'political instability',

then it is obvious that for Huntington 'political institutionaliza-

tion' is positively and directly correlated with whatever is the

opposite of 'political decay'. The correlation of 'political parti-

cipation', on the other hand, is negative, and thus he was not

very wrong in titling his 1965 article 'Political Development and

Political Decay'. Only now the dynamic thrust is seen as coming

from the negative factor, that is, 'political participation', and

whether it results in political decay or political order depends

upon the capacity of political institutions to absorb it and, in the

process, adapt to each other. Riggs has developed a slightly

more sophisticated and generalized theory out of this, but at

least he has admitted that what he is talking about is 'develop-

mental conffiet'.24 There seems no reason to think that Hunt-

ington is talking about something which is different in any

essential respect from what Riggs is talking about. We will have

occasion later to discuss in detail the contentions of both with

respect to what they regard as 'political development', but

The Criterion as Participation 29

there seems no reason to think that Huntington does not believe

in something which others call 'political development' and

which he seems afraid to designate as such.

'Participation', then, has been regarded as a criterion of

positive political development by most political scientists.

However, there are some like Huntington who regard it

primarily as a negative factor, while others like Riggs regard it

as that negative element in the dialectics of development which

makes it possible to reach higher levels of political synthesis. But

whether positive or negative, and whether creatively negative

or just negative, it has always played a key role in all thought

concerned with political development. Yet if there is such

diversity in the ways in which it can be understood as a

criterion, ranging from the purely positive to the purely nega-

tive, it is obvious that, apart from the purely subjective idio-

syncrasies of the authors, there must be something besides

participation itself which tends to make some relate it positively

and others negatively to what they regard as 'polit@cal develop-

ment'.

The reason why 'participation' is regarded as a positive

sign relates to the fact that it is only through participation that

one can make known what one thinks or feels or wants with

respect to the system, and that one can play some part in

shaping it nearer not only to the desire of one's heart but also to

the judgement of one's head. But for this reason, it is also felt-

to use a phrase of Almond-that 'the capabilities of a system

may be overloaded', and that the proverbial too many cooks

can indeed spoil the broth. The point obviously is that if

participation' is seen in terms of 'demands' upon the system,

then too many demands may break the system. On the other

hand, if it is seen in terms of 'counselling and taking part in the

decision-making process', then too many counsels and too many

decision-makers may frustrate the process itself. The former is

usually known in the literature as 'interest articulation', while

the latter has been given no specific, distinctive name, though

'interest aggregation' and 'capabilities' refer to some of its

aspects. We will discuss each of these in detail later on.

The notion of 'participation' has recently been modified by

some thinkers. Brunner and Brewer, for example, suggest that a

more useful conceptualization of political participation may be

30 Political Development

found in 'the capacity of a group or section to respond to

changes in its life situation by giving or withholding support for

the government'. And, 'more generally, participation i@ the

extent to which stimuli or felt needs can be converted into

meaningful responses at the aggregate ICVCII.2,1 This is close to

what Almond calls 'interest articulation'. But it seems a little

strange to define 'participation' in terms of 'capacity' which is

basically something dispositional rather than actual. Also it

seems odd that the definition, if taken literally, would exclude

any political concern or response that was related not to changes

in the group's own life situation but to issues of concern to other

groups in the same polity or even in other countries. This would

make all idealistic involvement in politics non-participatory by

definition. The authors, further, fail to see that if 'political

participation' is defined in terms of the capacity to give or

withhold support to the government, then it is only a

minority which can ever, even potentially, participate in the

political process, as it is only a minority which possesses this

capaci@y in any significant or substantial degree. Not only this, it

would, on this analysis, be in the interest of each group to see

that others do not get this capacity. This may occur. But if, in

such a circumstance, 'participation' is still treated as a criterion

of 'positive political development', then the latter can only be

achieved by an egalitarian distribution of all that contributes to

such a capacity. Yet, as such distribution would not be to the

interest of any specific group, and as unselfish participation is

,ruled out by definition, it would follow that positive political

development in the sense of enlargement of participation would

happen only rarely and then too by accident. The hope in such

a situation may perhaps be seen to lie in the possible conflict

amongst those who have this capacity and in their attempts to

augment their capacity by trying to win over those with little

or no capacity of their own except numbers.

It is interesting, however, to see why the authors consider it

necessary to view the notion of 'participation' in this manner.

The reason lies in the f@ct that they found voting turnout rates

in Turkey and the Philippines too high for their taste. These

countries, after all, have to be regarded as politically under-

developed, and if they show high levels of political participation

as measured by voting turnout, then either 'participation' is not

The Criterion as Participation 31

a criterion of 'political development' or voting turnout is not a

measure of 'participation'. The authors chose the latter alterna-

tive. They write, 'In man' countries that are still considered

y

relatively underdeveloped there are already very high levels of

voting turnout. In Turkey, for example, the turnout rates were

39%, 89%, and 77% of the eligible electorate in the general

elections of 1950, 1954, and 1957, respectively. The Philippine

presidential elections of 1946, 1949, 1953, 1957 and 1961 had

turnout rates of 89.6%, 67.7%, 77.2%, 75.5% and 79.4% of

the registered electorate. If the phenomenon called participa-

tion is increasing in the less developed countries, then turnout

rates are not an accurate measure of it. 121 But why not? They

may not be an accurate measure, but they certainly are some

measure of it.

The trouble with most criteria of political deve pnient, as we

shall see later on, is that they either turn countries which are

presumably 'politically developed' into being politically under-

developed or vice versa or both. The only criterion which seems

an exception to this is the criterion of economic growth. But if

that criterion be accepted, then there remains no real need for

thinking about 'political development' in any specific, separate

sense of the term. 'Participation' is a case in point. If voting

turnout, especially in democratic countries, is accepted as at

least one of the key measures of 'political participation', then

the United States appears woefully underdeveloped politically.

'The number of eligible Americans who have actually voted in

presidential elections since World War 11 has ranged from 51.5

per cent in 1948 to 63.8 per cent.in 1960.'27 If one compares

these figures with those for Turkey and the Philippines given

earlier, one sees the degree of 'political underdevelopment'

which the United States suffers in contemporary times. Unfor-

tunately, this conclusion is not very acceptable to writers on

political development' as not only do most of them happen to

3

be U.S.'citizens but also, if they were to accept it, they would

find little to make a country such as Turkey or the Philippines

interesting as examples of emulation for'political development'.

But it is not only the so-called 'underdeveloped' countries

which have a higher voter turnout than the U.S.A. Most

Western European countries seem to enjoy the same advantage.

For example, 'Turnout in Italy and Belgium in the years since

32 Political Develo pment

World War 11 has approximated 90 per cent; in Denmark,

West Gerniany, and Great Britain, 80-85 per cent; and in

Canada, Norway, Finland, and japan, 70-80 per cent.'28 Yet,

it seems diflicult for any political scientist to conclude on the

basis of these figures that the U.S. is far, far more 'politically

underdeveloped' than these countries. The writer, of course,

goes on to say that 'The few cross-national studies conducted

so far indicate, however, that despite the low turnout, other

indexes of participation-political interest and awareness, ex-

pressed party afffilation, sense of political competence, etc.-

tend to, be higher in the United States than in many other

countries, such as France and Italy."" He does not give any

judgement as to the relative weightage of all these factors vis-a-

vis voter turnout, nor does he give any explanation as to why

politics which @core high on other indices should he low on

voter turnout, when perhaps that is the area where citizens can

be most effective in the political system.

The deeper problem with respect to 'participation', however,

relates to the fact that so few people who can participate in the

political process actually do so to any great extent. As Bryce

observed, 'only a small group gives constant attention to

politics, a slightly larger group is interested but comparatively

passive, while the mass of men are largely indifferent'.30 The

only alternative in such a situation seems to be to force people

to 'participate' in politics, to make participation involuntary

rather than voluntary-not a matter of choice, but of com-

pulsion. This, to a great extent, has been the tendency o f

totalitarian politics. Yet there are very few persons who would

consider such 'enforced participation' a sign of 'political devel-

opment'. The very fact that participation has to be forced

shows that it is not desired and that if the enforcement were to

be removed, in all likelihood non-participation would increase

tremendously.

It may be that large-scale participation in the political pro-

cess is a sign not of health but of disease in the body politic.

When the polity is healthy, people can take it for granted and

pursue other interests which they regard as worthwhile. It is

only when they find it impossible to take it for granted, as it

becomes increasingly difficult for them to pursue ends which

they regard as worthwhile, that they begin more and more to

The Criterion as Participation 33

concern themselves with politics. The body politic may be some-

thing like the human body, in that the less you are aware of

it as a problem, the healthier you are. There are obvious ex-

ceptions to this, but on the whole it is a fair description of the

situation.

The 'participation' criterion of political development, thus,

appears to run into difliculties for which there seem no very

adequate answers in the literature' concerning the subject.

First, it is not quite clear whether it is a sign of positive or

negative political development. Though generally it is treated

as a positive indicator, many of the political problems that

plague the so-called developing countries are usually attributed

to it also. Second, it is not quite clear whether 'participation'

is to be voluntary or involuntary in order to be counted a

criterion of 'political development'. If voluntary, it is not quite

clear whether an increase indicates the sorry state of affairs in

the polity or just a growing sense of responsibility and a desire

for self-determination in the populace. If involuntary, on the

other hand, it is not very clear whether it is only formal parti-

cipation which is to be obligatory or whether even the direction

which one's participation is to take is to be prescribed. At an

even more fundamental level, it is seldom made clear what

exactly is meant by 'participation'. Also, as there is a limit to

participation, there would have to be one to political develop-

ment also. The voting age, for example, can be reduced, but

not indefinitely. The franchise can be extended and legal

disabilities removed. But obviously there is a point beyond

which one cannot go. There is such a thing as universal

franchise, and it is not difficult of achievement either. The

obstructions in the w@@ of the exercise of franchise could also

be removed, and thus complete political development could be

achieved on the basis of this criterion.

Is 'political development', then, a sort of development which

can be completely achieved? If 'participation' be the criterion

and if it be understood in the usual sense, then there seems no

reason why this should not be so. But then, 'political develop-

ment' would not he the indefinitely incremental sort of thing

we usually tend to think all 'development' to be. Perhaps that

is the reason why most thinking concerning 'political develop-

ment' tends to concentrate on the countries of Asia, Africa, and

34 Political Development

Latin America, as the U.S. and most countries of Western

Europe may be assumed to have reached the goal already.

Development, of course, need not be conceived of as just

incremental in character. Instead, it may be conceived of as

involving radical breaks between one level and another. The

movement from one- level to another and the relationship

between the levels may be thought of in dialectical terms, but

this is not necessary. Yet, whether it is conceived of dialectically

or not, the idea of development in terms of radical breaks

does not escape the, problem raised by the denial of the possibi-

lity of indefinite incremental growth with respect to 'political

development'. The advocates of socialist or communist notions

of 'political development' find themselves in the same dilemma

as those who espouse what are usually called democratic con-

ceptions. One's ideal paradigm may be the Soviet Union or

Maoist China, just as the paradigm of democratic political

development may be the United States of America or Great

Britain or any other country of Western Europe. But the issue

as to what ''political development' means for such a country

remains the same. The advocates-of each pattern could easily

spell out what it would mean for a polity of the other type to,

develop politically. But what development would mean in

their own case they could hardly tell. To admit the possibility

of 'political development', except in a very, very marginal

sense, is to admit that one. has not achieved the polity one

wanted to achieve. What would it mean for revolution to occur;

say, in the Soviet Union or Maoist China? The question when

posed in terms of 'revolution' brings the dilemma into the open.

But 'revolution' is merely another name for 'political develop-

ment' in this context. What can occur, for those who accept

these nations as paradigms of communist politics, is only

'counter-revolution'. The situation is the same on the other side,

though few appear to regard it as such. But that is primarily

because most writers on such matters tend to accept com-

munist countries as paradigmatic examples of developed poli-

tics. It is, however, not difficult to find explicit statements on the

other side. Euge-ne Kamenka writes, for example. 'The conc@pt

of universality has been exhausted for all practical purposes,

in the attaining of representative government and reasonable

economic affluence. The revolution of the future in advanced.

The Criterion as Participation 35

democratic, industrialized society could only be counter-

revolution, a seizure of power by a group intent on re-establish-

ing despotic rule and a status society.'311

The term 'development', in fact, is used in many senses and

does not always connote the possibility of indefinite growth.

Perhaps 'political development' is a development of the sort

where this connotation is not made. But if this is so, then this is

-the first thing to he clarified..Nornially, it is discussed, debated,

and written about on the analogy of economic development.

But if it does not permit of indefinite growth in principle, it is

different from economic development in certain fundamental

and essential respects, and the analogy then becomes very

misleading.

On the other hand, if it is treated as an ideal which societies

only asymptotically approximate and which they may approach

but never completely realize, and if 'participation' is conceived

of as dchning what this development consists in, then 'parti-

cipation' itself has to be thought of in such a way that it could

be indefinitely approximated to but never completely actual-

ized. ln,such a situation, it obviously has to go beyond voter

turnout and even beyond the other so-called indices such as

political interest and awareness, expressed party affiliation,

sense of political competence, etc., which McClos@y mentions

in his article, cited earlier. But if the sense of 'participation' is

extended beyond what is involved in the notion of 'representa-

tive' government based on universal suffrage, we run up

against what we have earlier called the difficulty of 'involuntary

vs. voluntary participation', and, at a deeper level still, against

the basic asymmetry involved in all power relations themselves.

It may be correct, as Dahl observes, that 'even today what

one ordinarily calls democracies are, as we all know, a very

long way from being fully democratized political systems..'32

But if 'the plateau on which the democracies repose is ... a

long way from what a reasonable observer might regard as the

summit of political democracy', because 'it is obvious that

political influence is distributed with great unevenness',33 then

iparticipation' in the sense of 'democratization' would seem to

mean equal distribution of political influence or, in other words,

equal distribution of political power. But can power be equally

distributed? And even if, by some miracle, someone were to

36 Political Development

distribute it equally@whatever may be meant by that term-

would it remain so distributed for long?

The basic asymmetry which is involved in all power rela-

tionships has seldom been the object of sustained reflection on

the part of those who have conceived of 'political development'

in terms of equality of political power. But if political power is

distinguished from other kinds of power by its ultimate com-

mand over instruments of physical coercion, then equal dis-

tribution becomes even more difficult in its case. The relation

between different kinds of power has seldom been clarified,

but if the political realm claims a certain foundational primacy

because of its control over means of legitimate coercion, then

it is obvious that such a control could not be distributed equally.

Further, if a certain positive relationship be accepted between

other kinds of power and political power in the sense of exercise

of political influence, then it is intrinsically impossible that

political influence could ever be evenly distributed amongst all

members of a polity. The- situation could perhaps be retrieved

theoretically if we- were to postulate that each individual has

supremacy in one particular type of power and if all types of

power were to be treated as equivalent in strength or influence.

This, however, would run against the primacy of political power

over all other powers and against the possibility of some people

combining and thus forming a more powerful combination

against others. The latter possibility is presumably taken care of

by the democratic principle of majority rule, but it reinstates

to some extent the asymmetry between those who command the

majority and those who do not.

Yet, however intractable may be the problem raised by the

asymmetrical character of power relationships, the hoped-for

amelioration through extension of participation in the political

process reveals at least one of its essential purposes. It mitigates

to some extent the unevenness in the distribution of political

influence. And, to the extent that the capacity for political

influence is itself a function of other kinds of inequalities, it

works for their amelioration also. But the type of inequalities

whose amelioration may be sought has to be such that mitiga-,

tion is possible. In other words, they have to be man-made, that

is, social or institutional in origin. Yet this very origin suggests

the difficulties in the way of their removal. There are vested

The Criterion as Participation 37

interests in the perpetuation of existing inequalities, and it is

the task of those who want to remove them to articulate and

attempt to secure their counter-interests. Political development,

then, may be seen as an increase in 'interest articulation', and

the latter may he treated as another criterion in terms of which

political development may be articulated andjudged.

The concept of 'participant citizenship' has been articulated

by Inkeles in terms of freedom from traditional authority,

interest in public affairs, and political rationality. He suggests

that-there is a participant citizenship syndrome which consists

of five factors. It 'includes identification with an allegiance to

supra-local and non-parochial public authority; interest in

civic affairs; information about political figures; participation

in public organizations; and adherence to rational organiza-

tional rules as a basis for running government affairs' .34 Itis not

quite clear whether he would take an increase in this syndrome

as a sign of political development, but as he takes it as almost a

sine qua non of modernity an 'd as, presumably, to be modern is

to be politically developed, it may be assumed that he would

take it as such also. Yet, whether the so-called syndrome be an

empirical fact or not, it is fairly obvious that he has not even

raised the questions we have been concerned with, let alone

made any attempt to answer them. In fact, the continuous con-

fusion between 'modernization' and 'development' seldom

permits most writers on the subject to come clearly to grips

with the problem and to tackle the fundamental issues related

to it.

Inkeles' study, for example, is concerned with the empirical

establishment of what he calls the 'participant citizenship

syndrome' and its specific relation to what may be considered

some sort of 'modernity scale' on which various politics may

ranked. The notion of 'modernity' is generally tied up with

temporal considerations in such a way as to make it impossible

for any country or civilization in the past to be considered

'modern'. On the other hand, it is identified with certain

characteristics which were supposed to be first exhibited in

countries of Western Europe and then taken over elsewhere by

other countries also. It is not made quite clear whether these

characteristics, once acquired either by some process of creative

innovation or by imitation, would last forever, or whether they

4

38 Political Development

could possibly slip away onc 1c again. Is the possession of

'modernity', in other words, a permanent possession? Or can

it be got hold of and lost, like other things in life? Or is it the

sort of thing with respect to which possession may fluctuate?

There, can always be, so to say, 'more' or 'less' modernity, and

there are no reasons why a particular polity may not move

forward or slide back, as the case may be. But to adn-iit the

possibility of sliding back is to admit that time is not the essence

of the matter, for a country which is not 'modern' today could

very well have been so in the past. Yet once this'is admitted

there seems no intrinsic reason why politics in ancient times

could not have been 'modern' in comparison to many that

exist today. Also, by the same logic, those that are modern

today could cease to be so tomorrow.35

In fact, it is a little strange to find someone seriously implying

that the five factors constituting 'participant citizenship' can

only be found in the so-called 'modern societies' in modern

times. It is difficult to believe that someone could be seriously

contending that interest in civic affairs, or identification with

supra-local, non-parochial public authority, or participation

in public organizations, or adherence to rational organizational

rules as a basis for running government affairs, or information

about political figures could individually or collectively be

significantly absent from any large, complex polity at any time,

whether present or past. If it is suggested that it is all a matter

of quantitative mix and significant proportions, then the author

concerned should make clear what he considers to -be the exact

critical minimum which would constitute 'modernity'. Yet this

is seldom even attempted. As we have already pointed out, the

voter turnout proportions for the United States, for example,

would make it relatively undeveloped in relation to many so-

called undeveloped countries.

Inkeles' study, thus, suffers from the basic defect of not even

having raised certain crucial questions, and it is therefore

mostly irrelevant to the issue we are discussing. Even on the

empirical plane, one must conclude that something is seriously

wrong with the study, as at least one of its findings seems com-

pletely mistaken in the light of later developments. According

tolhim, 'only in East Pakistan does the observed pattern support

the unitary conception of the modern political man. There,

The Criterion as Participation 39

those who are active citizens are also consistently more benevolent

toward other groups and more satisfied with the government's

performances'' One wonders what is meant by 'active citizens'

in this context. Everyone who had anything to do with East

Pakistan knew of the deep dissatisfaction felt by the people

there against a government which was controlled mainly by

people in West Pakistan-a dissatisfaction so widespread and

deep-rooted that it later resulted in a civil war leading to the

dismemberment of Pakistan and the establishment of an inde-

pendent country, Bangla Desh, out of what was formerly known

as East Pakistan. Yet this empirical study, scientifically con-

ducted with liberal funds, technical expertise, and sophisticated

methodology, came to an opposite conclusion which, if true,

would have rendered impossible what is already a fact of

history. If such studies can go so far wrong in understanding

present societies, one wonders how far they can be relied upon

for characterizations 'of societies that are past. One should,

perhaps, take what they say not merely with a pinch, but

rather, a ton of salt.*'

* Professor Inkeles in a personal discussion pointed out that my criticism was

misplaced as in the study mentioned he was 'not making generalizations to the

national populations' (p. 1120). But then we may legitimately wonder what is the

significance of his findings regarding the exemplification of 'the unitary conception

of modern political man' in East Pakistan or of those relating to the 'active citizens'

in that country. The reader may judge the matter for hirwelf, as presumably the

presence of these findings would. not only suggest the relative modernity of East

Pakistan in the light of the criteria mentioned but also be regarded as favourable

for the chances of political stability in that country.

NOTES

1. Hannah Arendt, On Revolution (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1973).

2. For an interesting discussion of this, see Robert A. Dahl, After the Revolution?

(New Haven: Yale University Press, 1970).

3. Benjaniin N. Cardozo, The ivature of the 7udkial Process (New Haven: Yale

University Press, 192 1).

4. Lucian W. Pye, Aspects of Political Development (Boston: Little, Brown & Co.,

1966), p. 45.

5. Fred W. Riggs, 'The Dialectics of Developmental Conffict', Comparative

Political Studies, 1 (July 1968).

40 Political Development

6. Samuel P. Huntington, Political Order in Changing Societies (New Haven: Yale

University Press, 1968).

7. Sydney Verba, Bashiruddin Ahmed, and Anil Bhatt, Caste, Race, and Politic.%

(Beverly Hills: Sage Publications, 1971).

8. Ibid., p. 29.

9. Ibid., pp. 29-32.

10. Ibid., p. 29.

11. Ibid.,

12. Ibid., pp. 255, 262.

13. Ibid., p. 32.

14. Ibid., p. 2 1.

15. Arthur S. Banks and Robert B. Textor, A Cross-Poli@y Survey (Boston: M.I.T.

Press, 1963).

16. Huntington, Political Order in Changing Societies, p. 55. Also, 'The Change to

Change', Comparative Politics, April 1971, p. 314.

17. Gabriel A. Almond and G. Bingham Powell, Jr., Comparative Politks: A

Developmental Approach (Boston: Little, Brown & Co., 1966), p. 34.

18. Gabriel A. Almond, 'Political Development: Analytical and Normative per-

spectives', in Comparative Political Studies, 1969, p. 458.

19. Lucian Pye and Sidney Verba (eds), Political Culture and Political Development

(Princeton: Prinecton University Press, 1965), p. 4.

-20. Huntington, 'The Change to Change', pp. 304-5.

21. Huntington, Political Order in Changing Societies, p. vii.

22. Huntington, 'The Change to Change', p. 304.

23. Ibid., p. 314.

24. Riggs, 'The Dialectics of Developmental Conflict', p. 197.

25. Ronald D. Brunner and Garry D. Brewer, Organized Complexi@y (New York:

Free Press, 197 1), p. 1 1.

26. Ibid., pp. 10-1 1.

27. U.S. Bureau of the Census, 1965, p. 384, quoted by I-Ierbert MeClosky in the

article 'Political Participation', in International ~clopedia of the Social Sciences,

vol. 12, p. 254.

28. MeClosky, p. 255.

29. Ibid.

30. Ibid., p. 254.

31. Eugene Kamenka, 'The Concept of a Political Revolution', in Revolution, ed.

Cari T. Friedrich (Nomos VIII, New York: Atherton Press, 1966), p. 134.

32. Dahl, AM the Revolution @', pp. 4-5.

33. Ibid., p. 6.

34. Alex Inkeles, 'Participant Citizenship in Six Developing Countries', The

American Political Science Review, 63 (Dec. 1969), p. 1 1 39.

35. Tome of the issues raised here are closely rel@ated to the question whether there

is any such thing as political evolution. We will discuss this in detail later

in connection (see pp@ 47-65) with the so-called evolutionistic perspective in

the discussion on political development.

36. Inkeles, 'Participant Citizenship in Six Developing Countries', p. 1129.

Italics mine.,

2

THE CRITERION AS

DIFFERENTIATION

(1) Differentiation

'Participation' may be said to be immanently embedded in the

domain of the political itself. And, though we have pointed out

the intrinsic conflict caused by the asymmetrical character of

power, which also belongs inalienably to the domain of the

political, one may yet concede participation to be a moral

demand that arises from and belongs to the realm itself. The

same, however, can hardly be said of the other criterion most

commonly offered by writers in this field. 'Differentiation' is so

often offered as a criterion of 'political development', and by

writers of such different persuasions, that it will not be amiss to

exan-iine it in some detail at this stage. And the first thing to

note about differentiation is that it has nothing to do specifically

with political development. Rather, it is regarded as a criterion

of development in general, and therefore political development,

as a type of development, may be expected to show this

characteristic also. The political character of development,

then, may be considered as detern-iining the fact that differen-

tiation in this domain lies in the realm of institutions and func-

tions which are specifically political in character.

Normally, differentiation is taken as a sign of development

(and by 'development' from now on we will always mean

'positive development') because it is supposed to contribute to

the efficient functioning of the system. But it may also be

implied that unless differentiation has occurred, an entity will

not have come into being, and without this one could not even

talk of development or non-development or underdevelopment.

Differentiation, in this perspective, would be a precondition for

42 Political Development

the emergence of a separate, distinctive entity. But by the same

logic it would not be a sign of development unless it be the

development of the undifferentiated entity from which or

within which it has been differentiated. Yet if the latter alterna-

tive is accepted, the differentiated entity would still be seen in

terms of that within which it has been differentiated and not

in terms of its own separate, distinctive identity. The function

which differentiation was supposed to perform, thus, gets

nullified in this perspective. Further, if differentiation is sup-

posed to be a development of the, undifferentiated, then the

differentiated, in order to develop itself, must become further

differentiated, and so on ad infinitum. Also, in the undiffer-

entiated stage- the differentiations must, to some extent, have

been implicit. Riggs has used the terms 'fused' and 'refracted'

for these notions.

These two dimensions in the notion of 'differentiation' as a

criterion of political development are themselves fused in the

writings of most political scientists on the subject. The separa-

tion of the 'political realm' itself is taken as a sign of social

development, and the further differentiation of the political

realm into specialized institutions concerned with specific func-

tions is taken as a sign of political development. It is not clearly-

indicated whether a further differentiation of these specialized

institutions with t4eir specific functions would be regarded as

development and, if so, of what. Presumably@ on the previous

analogy, it would be a development directly of these institutions

and their functions, and indirectly of the political realm, and

still more- indirectly, of society as a whole. Following this logic,

it may and perhaps will be said that ultimately it is a develop-

ment of the whole human race, and, in fact, of the whole cosmos

itself.

The presupposition that structures and functions are capable,

of infinite analysis is writ large on this way of conceiving the

notion of development. The analysis is not to he merely con-

ceptual in nature. Rather, it is an actual process of subdivision

which perhaps can be carried on ad infinitum. This possibility of

unlimited subdivision is, in fact, the ground of the possibility of

infinite development which otherwise would find its necessary

limitation in the limits to the possibility of differentiation itself

Most thinkers, however, have not concerned themselves with

The Criterion as Diferentiation 43

the problems raised by this requirement of a perpetual possibi@

lity of differentiation as a precondition for the existence of a

permanent possibility of development. If, for any reason, fur-

ther differentiation could not be conceived, or, if conceived,

were not actually feasible, then, in this perspective, develop-

ment would not be possible either.

Differentiation, thus, may be seen either as the coming into

being of something distinctive with an independent separate

being of its own, or as a process which, when it takes place

within an entity; provides for a more effident performance of

the function attributed to that entity. In the former case, the

notion of development does not make sense unless interpreted

in the purely quantitative sense of an increase in the number of

entities in the world. In the second sense, however, one would

have to integrate the function of the.differentiated structure to

that of the one within which the differentiation has taken place.

This integration may presumably be effected by some other

differentiated structure which specifically performs the integra-

tive function, or it may be brought about by the interrelation

between different structures which, occurs, perhaps,. automatic-

ally. The first alternative would probably be regarded as an

example of greater development by those who accep't the idea of

differentiation per se as a criterion of development. But in what-

ever manner the integrative function be performed, the neces-

sity for it -arises because of the fact that differentiation has taken

place. On the other hand, if the so-called integrated differentia-

tion is to succeed, then the function of both entities or structures

have to be in balance with each other. But, in that case, there

seems little reason to call one rather than another a criterion of

development.

There are other difficulties in the notion which have hardly

engaged the attention of those who have sought to find in it a

clue to the secret of what development really consists in. If, for

example, integration is necessitated by the fact of differential

tion, then differentiation per se could not be a criterion of devel-

opment, political or otherwise. Rather, it would be a sort of

negative indication, for whatever it brings into being has some-

how to be balanced by integrative forces or mechanisms which

must be able to cope with it. If this is not done, then differen-

tiation may be just another name for dissolution. Yet, once the

44 Political Develo ,pment

possibility of there being too much differentiation is admitted,

it would follow that differentiation per se could not be taken as

a criterion of development. Rather, the criterion would be some

sort of a ratio between integration and@ differentiation, where

each tends to be balanced by the other. But, as everybody

knows, a ratio is a function of two numbers and the more we

would have of differentiation, the more we would need of

integration, and even though the two numbers may change the

ratio could still be the same. There is no difference, for example,

between 214 and 418. Therefore, if development be treated as a

ratio between integration and differentiation, then, even though

there may be an ostensible increase in both, it would be illusory

to think that there has been any real development.*

The notion of integration, if brought into a discussion of the

problem of development, raises problems of its own. If it is

supposed to occur automatically, it raises the question whether

there can be any such thing as disintegration. The relevance of

the question may be seen if we ask what it would mean for the

universe, meaning by that the totality of all that is. to lack

integration. In a fundamental sense, whatever is, must by that

very fact be assumed to be integrated, since if it were not so

integrated, it would just not be. In the context of a larger

totality, then, there would always be integration, whether there

occurs any differentiation or not.

On the other hand, if integration itself is the function of the

differentiated structure, then the .@hole co-ordinated system

with its differentiated structures along with their differentiated

functions would be a sign of development. But if one asks

'development of what ?'then one would have difficulty in finding

an answer. It could not be a development of itself, for 'develop-

ment' is a comparative term, and the whole differentiated

system is a'sign of the development of something which was

undeveloped before. But if the whole system, including the

integrating structure, has differentiated itself into an autonom-

ous entity, then how can it be considered a development of

anything else ?

The issue may perhaps gain a little more clarity if we ask

* The problenu related to development conceived as a relationship betwee:

two or more factors wW be discussed in Chapter 4, section (8), pp. 160-78.

The Criterion as Differ..ntiation 45

ourselves whether the coming into being of any entity is in

itself a sign of development. This could only be so when it is

taken as a sign of something else, whether quantitatively or

qualitatively or both. In itself, it could not be considered in a

developmental perspective, though development could be con-

ceived of with respect to it or even in relation to entities other

than itself. Thus, the concept of development may be said to be

applied to an entity either in relation to its own previous states

or in relation to other entities having some property or set of

properties in respect of which they may be regarded as rele-

vantly comparable.

Now, in none of these senses can differentiation per se be con-

sidered a sign of development. It may well be such a sign, but it

does not have to be such. Whether with respect to an entity's

own past or with respect to a relevant comparison with some

other entity, there seems no surety that the mere fact of

differentiation by itself would ensure development. In bureau-

cratic structures, differentiation may simply be a sign of what

has been called Parkinson's Law. In the case- of a political

entity like an empire or a nation, it may just he a sign of the

weakening of central authority, or even of an'increasing ques-

tioning of its basic legitimacy. In a social structure, it may be a

sign of alienation or even of an increase in parochial, self-

centred interests.*

The objection may be made that these are not the types of

differentiation which are meant when it is offered as a criterion

of development. But there would then be different types of

differentiation, and it would have to be specified as to what

type is to be taken as a criterion of development. Unfortunately,

the literature on the subject offers little help in this connection.

It talks only of differentiation and does not seem to distinguish

between those types that are a sign of positive development,

and those that are not.

Basicall@, differentiation is supposed to result in a more

efficient functioning of the system and is, therefore, accepted

as a sign of development. But, viewed in this manner, it would

be such a sign only indirectly. The direct sign would be the

* The criterion of political development in terms of interest articulation will be

discussed in Chapter 4, section (1), pp. W94.

46 Political Development

effidiency of the, performance itself. Yet, unless it be assumed

that differentiation always results in an increase in the efficiency

of performance, it would be difficult to hold that it is always a

sign of development. But, though this assumption seems most

difficult to establish, it is taken as almost axiomatic in most

literature on the subject. There seems hardly any attempt to

establish empirically that it.is so. The facts of evolution and the

social and economic benefits associated with the division of

labour are apparently supposed to make the exercise unneces-

sary. But even if the evidence were as decisive as it is usually

thought to be, this would still not settle the issue. It is quite

possible that, the functions we expect from a living organism or

from an economic system are of such a type that they are best

accomplished by a differentiating process wherein each sub-

system performs its own specialized function. But it does not

follow from this that all functions need necessarily be of this

type. Or, even that these functions provide some pre-eminent

paradigm which ought to be accepted till the case for a radical

distinction with respect to some other functions is securely

established. One does not find the functions which a political

system is supposed to perform delineated very clearly in the

literature on the subject.* Nor does there seem to be any

attempt to establish that they would be, better performed if

there were to be a differentiation of structures and functions

And, it does not seem even to be asked whether there is such a

thing as an unlimited possibility of differentiation of both

structures and functions. Further, the ideal of a one-to-one

correlation between structure and function tends to be im-

plicitly assumed, even though according to many of the same

writers the two :@re almost invariably mixed up in actually

existing institutions. Yet, if there are such mix-ups, and if it is

true that even when institutions are specially set up to perform

a particular function they tend to take on other functions also,

then it should be a matter for reflection as to why this happens

to be so. If, in fact, the distinction between manifest and latent

functions is taken seriously, and it is also accepted that these

two kinds of functions are found everywhere and are usually

' Those which have been suggested will be discussed at length in Chapters 3

and 4.

The Criterion as Differentiation . 47

different, then the very notion of a one-to-one correlation

between structure and function is jeopardized at its very core.

For it would then be impossible in principle to have a structure

perform just one function, since besides carrying out the so-called

manifest function, it would also be performing a latent function

which is different from the first.

The criterion of differentiation, then, to say the least, is an

ill-thought-out notion. Yet, as its strength is derived from its

base in evolutionary theory, and as the concept of development

itself is supposed to be grounded in evolution, it will not be

amiss to examine this foundation itself.

1

(2) The Theory of Evolution as a Groundfor

the Criterion as Differentiation

Evolution means many things to many people. For some, it

takes the place of religion in that it provides a grounding for

the belief that there is something inherent in the universe which

makes for progressive development. Darwin himself tried to

make evolution do what was supposed to be a function of the

biblical god, that is, the creation of species. Since then, many

other people with great reputations have tried to discover all

the divine functions in evolution. We need hardly refer to

Teilhard de Chardin's Phenomenon of Man or Sri Aurobindo's

The Life Divine, when we have a supreme example in Sir julian

Huxley, the eminent biologist, who is surcharged with a lyrical

passion for what he himself has called 'the evolutionary vision5. 1

According to Huxley, 'the evolutionary vision ... illuminates

our existence in a simple, but almost overwhelming, way. It

exemplifies the truth that truth is great and will prevail, and

the greater truth that truth will set us free. Evolutionary truth

frees us from subservient fear of the unknown and supernatural

and exhorts us to face this new freedom with courage tempered

with wisdom and hope tempered with knowledge. It shows us

our destiny and our duty. It shows mind enthroned above

matter, quantity subordinate to quality.'?

Now anything that can do all this must be miraculous indeed.

And perhaps Sir julian intends it to be taken in just'that way.

After all, he is an eminent scientist and would not use his words

in too loose a fashion. Yet, it was he who insisted all through

48 Political Development

the Chicago Conference on 'Evolution After Darwin' to

celebrate the Centennial of the Origin of Species that evolution

was 'no longer a theory, but a faet'.3 But if something which is a

fact involves all the value components which he ascribes to it in the

above statement, then it is a very odd kind of fact indeed. It

does not merely involve the identity of the factual and the

valuational, but also a guarantee that there is something in the

nature of reality which ensures the triumph of value over

disvalue or, in more traditional language, of good over evil. But

this, as most students of philosophy would recognize, is usually

regarded as a fallacy. G. E. Moore christened it'the Naturalistic

Fallacy'4 at the beginning of the century and since then it has

generally been referred to by that name. Not all philosophers

are in agreement about it (they hardly agree on anything), but

anyone who does not subscribe to this view usually feels it

incumbent on himself to come to terms with it. Not so Sir

julian, or any of the other luminaries gathered together to

celebrate the Darwin Centennial.

In fact, as one looks through the roster of celebrities who

participated in the conference, one is struck by the fact that

hardly any philosophers were listed. Perhaps philosophy was

not supposed to be relevant to any of the discussions that were

to be held. But if the sort of ideas Sir julian propounded were

considered relevant to the issue of the conference, then it is

difficult to see how the contributions of philosophers who have

concerned themselves with the notion of evolution could have

been considered irrelevant to it. One is struck, in fact, by the

paucity of critical attitudes throughout the conference as

reported in the commemorative volumes. It was as if the

Centennial were a celebration not so much in honour of Darwin

as of evolution itself. To be critical in such an atmosphere

would have appeared a sign of bad manners, if not downright

heresy. It was a meeting of the faithful, and the doubting

Thomases had perhaps been deliberately excluded.

All this may seem unfair to the organizers and participants

in the conference. The reason why everything was discussed

except the notion of evolution itself, we may he told, lay in the

situation itself. Within the scientific community, there is no

dispute about the fact of evolution. As Huxicy said at the very

beginning, in television previews called 'At Random', 'the

The Criterion as Differentiation 49

first point to make about Darwin's theory is that it is no longer

a theory, but a fact. No serious scientist would deny the fact

that evolution has occurred, just as he would not deny the fact

that the earth goes round the sun'. 6 And, slightly later on, 'But

all scientists agree that evolution is a fact. There.are two

problems involved here. First whether evolution has happened

-and there is absolutely no disagreement among scientists that

it has. The second problem is how evolution takes place, and

here there has been argument, although we have made enor-

mous progress in understanding the process of evolution and

the role of natural selection in it.'6

But do all serious scientists understand the same thing by

evolution? Would, for example, everybody" agree with what

Sir julian has written in The Evolutionary Vision from which we

quoted certain passages earlier? And if anyone disagreed,

would he, in Huxley's view, not be a scientist at all, or at least

not a serious scientist? Presumably, Hermann J. Miiller and

Sir Charles Galton Darwin are serious scientists. They were

participants in the Centennial celebration and each presented

a paper there. Miiller's paper was entitled 'The Guidance of

Human Evolution' and Sir Charles Darwin's, 'Can Man Con-

trol His Numbers?' These were later published in Volume 11

of the Centennial proceedings. Yet, any reader of these two

articles 'will find the evolutionary vision of Sir julian absent

from their pages. There is no feeling that 'truth will necessarily

prevail' or that it will 'set us free', whatever may be meant by

these phrases. Darwin's is a frankly pessimistic conclusion, and

he is aware that it is such. He writes, 'I am very fully conscious

that the views 1 have expressed run entirely counter to many of

the optimistic hopes of the present age."' Miiller tries to sound

optimistic, but basically he makes his favourable prognosis

dependent on genetic control and improvement of population,

which is even more difficult than the mere control of population

about which Sir Charles, amongst others, is so pessimistic.

Miiller concludes by saying 'from now on, evolution is what we

make it, provided that we @-hoose the true and the good. Otherwise, we

shall sink back into oblivion."' His words sound almost theological.

And, if everything depends on man's choice of the true and

the good, the situation is hopeless indeed.

It may be said that the diiterence we are pointing to may

Political Development

better be understood as a difference in temperament rather

than a difference in'the substantive positions held about evolu-

tion. It is a difference between pessimism and optimism, even

though the facts discerned and the possibilities envisaged ;ire

the same. After all, Huxicy is as much aware of the alarming

pitfalls on the evolutionary path as anyone else. And though

his list of dangers contains such oddities as 'the rise and appeal

of communist ideology especially in the underprivileged sectors

of the world's people', and such generalities as 'our general

preoccupation with means rather than ends, with technology

and quantity rather than creativity and quality',10 it still shows

an awareness at least of the threat of overpopulation with which

Darwin is concerned, if not of the problem of genetic control

which Miiller deals with in his article. Yet, even if this be true,

it is fairly obvious that Huxley is f@ir less self-critical in ap-

praising what he is writing than are the other two scientists

referred to. It is basically not merely a question of temperament,

but of how much one wants to read into the idea of evolution,

and whether one is prepared to examine critically what is thus

included. The difference, for example, between Huxley's

assessment of Teilhard de Chardin's ideas on evolution and that

of P. B. Medawar can hardly be understood in terms of

differences in temperament between the two authors, but

rather, must be viewed as a consequence of differences in their

ideas about what evolution means."

We have emphasized the Darwin Centennial discussions,,as

they provided the occasion for the largest concentration in

recent times of eminent scientists who had concerned them-

selves with issues relating to evolution. Yet, it would not be unfair

to say that they hardly touched the central core of the notion

itself. Rather, they tended to imply not only that there was

nothing problematic about it, but almost that it was axioma-

tically true. It would not be amiss, therefore, to inquire as to

how far the idea of evolution necessarily involves the concepts

of development and differentiation as many political scientists,

amongst others, have supposed it to do.

Normally, the idea of evolution is supposed to relate pri-

marily to the realm of living organisms and the way they dif-

ferentiated into species over a period of time. The pre-eminent

association of the idea with the name. of Darwin and the title

The Criterion as Differentiation 5 1

of the book in which he propounded the idea are evidence of

this. Yet, no one hesitates to talk about the evolution of the

earth or the solar system or even of the cosmos. On the other

hand, there is equally little hesitation in talking about social and

cultural evolution, or even the evolution of an idea or art form,

or thought system. There should perhaps he little objection to

the use of the word in a loose, popular sense provided this does

not lead to, any serious confusions. Also, it may be legitimate

to extend by analogy a notion that has arisen in a certain field

to other areas where its application helps in understanding

them. Yet, there is always an extension where the analogy is

superficial or even misleading. And, equally, there is looseness

of usage which only confuses thought. Is the extension of the

term 'evolution', then, an example of either of the latter types?

It is well known that the idea of a systematic sequence of

changes appeared earlier in relation to geology and was fairly

firmly established in that field long before Darwin appeared on

the scene. But a mere systematic sequence of changes is not

evolution, for it is 'ust another name for what is usually known

as causality. Within the Darwinian perspective, the systematic

sequence of changes has to be brought about in a certain manner and

has to result in certain consequences in order to be called evolution.

These stipulations relate, on the one hand, to what is known as

natural selection and, on the other, to what is usually called

origin of species. If there were no such things as species, there

would remain nothing to explain, thus rendering the hypothesis

of evolution (pace Sirjulian) unnecessary. Equally, if there were

no such thing as natural selection, then W atever we m ght

postulate to account for the fact of there being species, it would

never be of the nature of what Darwin meant by evolution. It

is only the distinctive linkage of the two which makes for the

distinctive notion of evolution. If even one is absent in a situa-

tion, the concept can hardly be applied to it.

But, however obvious this conclusion may appear, it has been

continuously ignored in the writings on the subject. It never

seems to have been asked by those who have written about

cosmological, geological, or chemical evolution, what it would

mean for there to be species of inorganic matter or for natural

selection to take place with respect to them. Perhaps the

chemical elements could be thought of as species of inor

,game

52 Political Development

matter, or even the ultimate particles of matter, such as elec-

trons, protons, neutrons, and the diverse types of mesons. But

what would be gained by calling them 'species' is difficult to

understand. The basic point is that it does not make sense to

talk about natural selection with respect to non-living matter.

A complex structure may dissolve and we may say that it has

been pronounced unfit to exist by the environment or that it

has failed to meet the challenge of the environment. But this is

only a manner of speaking, and everyone knows it to he so.

Further, there is none of the replication and variation which is

needed before natural selection can play its role. But supposing

there is replication and variation in non-living matter, as some

have argued,n there would even then remain the question as to

which factor is supposed to do the selection, or with reference

to which the process of selection is said to take place. Is non-

living matter itself evolving? And if it is, with respect to what ?113

There are, however, not only complex structures of non-

living matter, but also those that are not complex, but rather

most elementary in nature. Shall we say that there is evolution

with respect to these also? But they are supposed to be the very

stuff out of which the universe is made, and if this is so, how

can they be said to evolve? Many scientists objected in the

conference to Gaffron's use of the term 'chemical selection'

which, according to him, started 'with the solubility of mole-

cules in water'.114 But in order to talk of evolution at this level

we would perhaps have to talk in terms of 'physical selection',

which, if anything, would be still more monstrous. If, as

Dobzhansky has said, 'the term chemical selection' was a

misnomer then there is still more reason to think -that 'physical

selection is such.

.If, on the other hand, we think in terms of energy rather than

particles, it becomes even more difficult to think in terms of a

struggle for survival or natural selection. There are supposed

to be conservation laws which ensure that the amount of

energy in the universe, whatever may be meant by the word,

remains constant. As there is, therefore, neither an increase nor

decrease of energy, there could not possibly be any talk of

evolution with respect to it. One may, of course, amuse oneself

by thinking of the transformation of potential into kinetic

energy as evolutionary in character, or perhaps even of the

The Criterion as Differentiation 53

counter-tendency to the second law of thermodynamics as

having this nature. Many biologists do seem to believe, in the

words of Medawar, 'that evolution flouts or foils the second

law of thermodynamics', even though in his opinion this is a

misconception arising from 'a confusion of thought'.",' But

whether evolution flouts it or not, no one disputes that in the

realm of non-living matter, the second law of thermodynamics

reigns supreme. However, if this is so, it would equally obviously

follow, at least for those who argue for the distinction, that

there can be no evolution as far as non-living matter is con-

cerned. Yet, many scientists hold both positions without seeing

the contradiction involved therein.

One may, in fact, amuse oneself further if one wants to

-think of the various types of energy as species of energy. But as

most types of energy are transformable into one another, this

would destroy the notion of species at its very core. This, in the

eyes of many, would be sufficient to dispose of the application

of the notion of evolution to the realm of non-living matter.

But exactly the same situation obtains in sociocultural evolu-

tion. Even those who are aware that something different is

meant when we talk of sociocultural evolution tend to slur

over the problems involved. Sol Tax, for example, points out

that, 'the term "evolution" is applied to both socially transmitted cul-

ture and gene transmitted biology because neither can establish an

exclusive claim. However ' there is no identity between the two

usages. The cultural processes of continuity and change are

different, and it is only by analogy, if at all, that one can speak

of "natural selection". for example, in the development of

cultures.'-"'

But if there is no identity between the two usages, then why

use the same word to connote two different things? At least 'in

the context of scientific discussion where clarity of thought and

precision are considered so important in expression, it would

presumably be best to avoid such a practice altogether. The

only reason Tax gives for the continued use in both biology and

cultural anthropology of the term 'evolution', even when the

meanings differ, is that 'neither can establish an exclusive

claim' to it. But this is too legalistic a view of the matter and, in

any case, can hardly be considered a sufficient reason for the

retention of a practice that facilitates confusion in thought, if it

54 Political Development

does not actually create and perpetuate it. The term 'evolution'

is so closely associated with the biological realm that its exten-

sion backward into the realm of noii-living matter or forward

into the realm of society and culture cannot but lead to serious

confusions in thought. It is on the basis of these ambiguities that

the thought of a Chardin or a Huxicy thrives. The inclusion of

everything under the rubric of 'evolution' becomes possible, and

we can have statements like the following from the pen of an

eminent scientist without their arousing any debate or disagree-

ment. In talking about the Centennial, Huxley said that 'this is

one of the first public occasions on which it has been frankly

faced that all aspects of reality are subject to evolution, from

atoms and stars to fish and flowers, from fish and flowers to

human societies and values-indeed, that all reality is a single

process of evolution."" But does this mean anything more than

that everything changes? And hasn't this always been known

to man?

On the other hand, if it is contended that evolution is some-

thing more than change, then what the 'more' is has to be

specified. Does this 'more' consist in the specific mechanism

through which-change is brought about, and has it anything to

do with the direction in which change takes place? Normally,

the mechanism is supposed to be 'natural selection', and the

result is supposed to be 'speciation'. But in order that 'natural

selection' may operate, it is necessary that there should exist

what Mililer has characterized as 'the property of replica-

tion of mutations-that is, self-copying and self-copying of

changes','.8 or even 'the ability for continuous mutation' which,

according to Evans, 'seems to be an inherent characteristic of

living cells',19 or what Miiller calls the level 'where an un-

limited number of changes in pattern are possible, each of

which is self-replicating' .20 1-lowever expressed, the point is that

gnatural selection' should have something to play upon or to

select from if such anthropomorphic expressions are to be

permitted

But, whether anthropomorphically stated or not, what is

gnatural selection' supposed to do? It is supposed to eliminate

those mutations or changes which make an organism unfit to

survive and thus leave only those to reproduce which are

relatively better able to survive. This explanation, however,

The Criterion as Differentiation 55

would account only for the origin of species and their elimina-

tion, but not for the simultaneous existence of diverse kinds of

species. For, if many kinds of species may simultaneously exist

in any environment, then it can only be presumed that the

environment is neutral with respect to them. Or that, as far as

the environment is concerned, they are all equally fit and none

may be regarded as better than the, other. It may be suggested

that one possible explanation for the simultaneous existence of

different species is not that the environment is neutral between

them, but that there are different kinds of environments and

that each of the species is fitted to its own environment. This

corresponds ' to some extent, to the notion of 'niche' in the

literature on biological and even cultural evolution. But this

would imply that there is a one-to-one correlation between

each species and its environment and that no two species can

exist in the same environment. This may seem to be logically

very neatbut, unfortunately, the diversity in environment is

generally inferred from the diversity in species, and no indepen-

dent criteria are ever given for determining what is to count as

diversity in environment. The whole contention, thus, becomes

merely tautological in character.

In fact, what constitutes an 'environment' is not clearly

specified in the literature. If, for example, 'environment' in-

cludes other species also, then all the species play a role in the

gnatural selection' of each one of them. In such a situation each

species is exercising a selection role in relation to all the other

species. The simultaneous existence of all the diverse species

may, then, be considered the result of a checkmated position

in which none can win over the others. The equilibrium can be

disturbed only by some relatively favourable mutations within

some species or by some sudden change in the physical environ-

ment which renders some species more favourably situated than

others. But mutations are going on all the time and so are

sudden chan es in the environment. It seems surprising, there--

9

fore, that the orchestrated equilibrium of the simultaneous

existence of so many diverse species should have continued for

millennia-as seems to have been the case in biological history.

On the other hand, it might be asserted that any of the

changes that happen to be severely disequilibrating, whether

changes in species or physical environment or both. tend to set

56 Political Development

the selective activity in motion once more, with the result that

the equilibrium would once again he restored with all the

species at a higher level of survival capacity than before. This,

however, would make the disappearance of species a very rare

phenomenon-far rarer, perhaps, than what we have observed

in biological history.

If, on the other hand, we turn to the question of physical

environment, we find the situation still more baffling. Normally,

we find a great many different species within the same environ-

ment. Certainly, it is true that there are different environmental

regions and that different species are found settled there. But

the converse of this does not seem true, unless it is made to

appear so by a definitional transformation. Within any homo-

geneous climatic or environmental zone, one can find as much

diversity amongst species inhabiting it as one wishes.

But whatever the solution to these problems may be, there

can be little doubt that the exercise of 'natural selection' is con-

cerned only with survival, and this too in the simple biological

sense of the term. There is, and can be, nothing more in the

strict scientific view of the matter. The 'survival of the fittest'

merely means the survival of those who have been fittest to

survive and this, though true, is almost tautological. Perhaps

it is saved from being a complete, tautology by the fact that

survival of any living organism, whether as an individual or as

a species, is not necessary at all. To put it in other words, all

life is an accident and nothing in the physical world ensures

that it is not so. As G. E. Moore pointed out long ago, 'the

survival of the fittest does not mean, as one might suppose, the

survival of what is fittest to fulfil a good purpose-best adapted

to a good end; at the last, it means merely the survival of the

fittest to survive. . . .'21 It is no part of Darwin's theory, he

points out, that 'more evolved' is necessarily equivalent to

'higher', as many have thought and propagated. According to

him, 'that theory will explain, equally well, how by an altera-

tion in the environment (the gradual cooling of the earth, for

example) quite a different species from man, a species which we

think infinitely lower, might survive USI.22

This is the hub of the problem. Is there anything in the theory

of evolution as developed by Darwin to suggest that anything

more than survival is ensured by 'natural selection', or that if

The Criterion as Differentiation 57

something survives, it shows any other fitness besides that

which enabled it to survive? All who have tried to develop a

world-view based on evolution have tended to imply that some-

thing more than mere survival is involved. But they have

seldom given open expression to this assumption, or tried to

defend it by arguments or evidence. Why should that which

survives be necessarily better in the moral, aesthetic, or spiritual

senses of the term? And why should any quality or qualities be

considered indispensable to survival, when what survives is not

so much a fi@nction of itself as of that which performs the select-

ing function, that is, the environment? Environments may

change, and this change may render superfluous or even harm-

ful qualities that were earlier helpful in survival. Further, if the

struggle is for survival, and if surviving species were all selected

on the basis of their possessing qualities essential to survival,

then it is difficult to see what exactly could be meant by calling

one species 'more evolved' than another, if the species which

are being compared are both surviving and, in fact, have

survived for a long time.

This, 1 think, is an important question. If 'survival' alone

matters, and in the evolutionary perspective 'natural selection'

means just that, then there is no point in talking about species

that have not yet been eliminated from the biological scene in

terms of 'more evolved' or 'less evolved'. The only relevant

criterion in that situation would perhaps be the length of

survival andlor the diversity of environments in which a species

survives. Man has had a very short span of biological survival

as compared with many other species, and though his capacity

to survive in many different kinds of environment is well

attested, this may be taken only as enhancing his potentiality

for survival rather than as assuring survival itself.

The point may be clarified in a different way. The capacity

to survive in different enviroifinents only shows that, if any of

the specific environments were to change but remain within the

range where survival has already been shown to be possible,

man would still be able to survive. This only gives a greater

range within which a species can survive. But if there is a

particular environment suited to a particular species, and if

that environment persists somewhere or other and the species

continues to live in-it, then there seems no intrinsic reason to

58 Political Development

think of it as evolutionally 'more evolved' than another. Certain

types of bacteria can survive very high and very low tem-

peratures, and yet this fact alone hardly makes anyone think

of them as more evolved. It may be thought that, by virtue of

the variety of environments in which one species can survive, it

would have the potentiality for existing in larger numbers than

other species that cannot live in several environments. Yet,

however attractive this argument may seem, many of the

species restricted to a specific environment exist in far larger

numbers than man can even dream of himself having.

It appears, therefore, that there is little to choose between

man and other species on the basis of survival. And, if a choice

had to be made, most other species would win in the com-

parison. There is, however, one respect in which man may be

thought to be 'more evolved', in the strictly evolutionistic sense

of the word, and that relates to his capaci@y to destroy other

species or to use them for his own purposes, including that of

survival. If this is correct, such a capacity also provides the

criteria for judging between any species, as to which is 'more

evolved' than another. These criteria would be 'the capacity to

destroy other species', and 'the capacity to use other species for

purposes of one's own survival'.* But, in spite of the persuasive-

ness of these criteria, it does not seem quite clear whether any

species, including man, actually has the first capacity or even

whether it could exercise such a capacity, if it had it, without

destroying itself in the process. As Gregory Bateson remarked in

the Nineteenth Annual Korzybski Memorial Lecture, 'if the

organism ends up destroying its environment, it has in fact

destroyeditSelfl.23Bateson, of course, was referring more to the

natural environment, but his remark is equally apt for the

biological environment. The more we understand the ecological

balance, the more we discover a symbiotic interdependence of

species rather than a competitive fight-to-the-finish between

* There is a slight difference in the two formulations with respect to the capacity

to use others. The one referring to man designates the capacity to use others as

'the capacity to use theni, for his own purposes, including that of survival', while

the generalized formulation restricts use of others to 'purposes of one's own

survival'. The difference derives from the distinctive nature of man which is

different from those of all other species. But in the evolutionistic context it is only

the perspective of survival which is relevant.

The Criterion as Diferentiation 59

them. And, while the elimination of some isolated species might

be practised with success, it is difficult to think of the elimina-

tion of all species.

The symbiotic relation of interdependence, to the extent

that it exists, also disposes of the second criterion ('the capacity

to use other species for purposes of one's own survival'), as the

relationship of 'use' may be considered mutual in character.

The trouble, basically, is that thinkers who offer such criteria

generally forget that in the evolutionary perspective there

cannot be any other value except that of sheer biological

survival. And hence the fact that a certain species flourishes or

survives because it is of 'use' to some other species is irrelevant

to the fact that it survives. 'Being of use' is useful to it, for it

ensures its survival. One might object that if it ceased to be of

guse' in such a situation it would cease to survive. But this is

5

fallacious, for it is very likely that the species would find some

other means for survival. In fact, in such a situation, 'natural

selection' would favour those that are relatively less dependent

for their survival on their being of use to some other species,

and these would then reproduce and survive.

It may be said that the suggested criteria were meant to be

understood in terms of capacity rather than the exercise of

capacity. But even if it be so, 'capacity' has to be conceived of

in such a way that the conception makes coherent sense. In the

evolutionary perspective, 1 suggest that the capacities which

are being offered as criteria for considering one species as 'more

evolved' than another do not make sense. Take, for example,

the capacity to destroy another species or even all the other

species, which is being suggested as a possible criterion of

evolutionary development. Now-, unless we assume the simul-

taneous, sudden destruction of all the members of the species at

once, the evolutionary hypothesis suggests that those who will

survive would develop an immunity to our method of destruc-

tion. And this is what we have found with respect to so many

species we have attempted to destroy. After some time the

surviving members and their progeny over successive genera-

tions develop increasing immunity against the particular

method that was so effective against their members several

generations earlier. But how can anybody ever be sure that all

the members of a species, not to talk of all the members of all

60 Political Development

the species, have been eliminated or destroyed? Evolution, if

we may say so, has and can have no favourites. It has no pre-

ferences between man and any other species. To think it has, is

tG negate the theory of evolution and it is strange to find

eminent biologists doing this and, that too, in the name of

evolution itsel£ The egocentric or rather species-centric illusion

could go no farther.

This may seem to confine the meaning of the term 'evolution'

too much to what Sahlins has called 'specific evolution', and to

ignore what he has called 'general evolution'.24 General evolu-

tion, according to him, consists of the emergence of 'higher

forms of life', which are 'higher' absolutely. It has got nothing

to do with the origination of species which, according to him,

is what 'specific' evolution is concerned with. In his own words,

'it is accurate to say that specific evolution is the production of

diverse species, general evolution the production of higher

forms.'2,5 And, 'the fundamental difference between specific and

general evolution appears in this: the former is a connected,

historic sequence of forms, the latter a sequence of stages

exemplified by forms of a given order of development.'211

Specific evolution is primarily concerned with adaptive special-

ization and accounts for the origination and diversification of

species. In Sahlins' words 'specific evolution is the phylogene-

tie, adaptive, diversifying, specialising, raniifying aspect of

total evolution.127 General evolution, on the other hand, 'is the

emergence of higher forms of life, regardless of particular lines

of descent or historical sequences of adaptive modification'.28

And while 'in the specific perspective advance is character;s-

tically relative-relative to the environmental circumstances',29

'to embrace general evolution is to abandon relativism'.30 For,

'the study of all-round progress requires criteria that are

absolute, that are relevant to all organisms regardless of parti-

cular environments.'31. And the absolute criteria for deciding

which is higher on the evolutionary scale, and which is lower,

may 'be conceived in functional, energy-capturing terms', for

'higher forms harness more energy than lower'.32 Or. 'the

criteria of general progress may be structural, the achievement

of higher organization'.33 'Thermodynamic achievement', Sahlins

writes, 'is the ability to concentrate energy in the organism, to

put energy to work building and maintaining structure.... It

The Criterion as Differentiation 61

is the amount (of energy) so trapped (corrected for gross size

of the form) and the degree to which it is raised to a higher state that

would seem to be evolutionary measure of life.134 Further,

'thermodynamic accomplishment has its structural concom-

itant, greater organization. The relation between energy-

harnessing and organization is reciprocal: the more energy con-

centrated the greater the structure, and the more complicated

the structure the more energy that can be harnessed.'3,1

These diverse ideas are summed up in Sahlins' notion of

'level of integration'. He argues that 'the idea of level of integra-

tion can be broken down into three aspects. An organism is

at a higher level of integration than another when it has more

parts and sub-parts (a higher order of segmentation); when its

parts are more specialized; and when the whole is more effec-

tively integrated.'36 To sum up, in Sahlins' own words, 'Specific

evolution is "descent with modification", the adaptive variation

of life along its many lines; general evolution is the progressive

emergence of higher life "stage by stage". 137Thus, 'the advance

or improvement we see in specific evolution is relative to the

adaptive problem', while 'the progress of general evolution is,

in contrast, absolute, it is passage from less to greater energy

exploitation, lower to higher levels of integration, and less to

greater all-round adaptability'.311

These exhaustive quotations may be expected hopefully to

make clear the difference between the two types of evolution

which Sahlins is trying to distinguish and which, according to

him, have generally been confused in most writings on the

subject. But the distinction itself is overlapping to a significant

extent. Sahlins himself treats 'adaptability' as a common feature

both of specific and general evolution. In fact, general evolution

is supposed to be a movement in absolute terms from 'less to

greater all-round adaptability'. True, it is also supposed to be a

movement from 'less to greater energy exploitation', and 'less to

higher levels of integration', but it is not quite clear whether

these are to be treated as independent of each other or not.

Could we have, for example, 'greater energy exploitation'

without achieving a 'higher level of integration', or vice versa?

The more crucial question, however, is whether one could have

both or any of them without ensuring 'greater all-round adapt-

ability', and if so, would such a species survive for long? To ask

62 Political Development

the question is to answer it. The evolutionary perspective

permits no other value except that of survival to don-iinate the

scene of life, and Sahlins' attempt to get out of the tight noose

of survival succeeds no better than that of others.

Sahlins does not discuss the relationship between the three

criteria he gives for general evolution. But it is fairly obvious

that the first two are basically instrumental for achieving the

third. Yet, if this were accepted, it would make general evolu-

tion as relative as specific evolution, since for Sahlins adapt-

ability is primarily a characteristic of specific evolution and is

essentially relative in nature. On the other hand, if we treat

them as independent of adaptability, it should he possible to

conceive of an increase in them at the cost of adaptability. But

in that case the requirements of competitive survival would

work against those who overshot the mark and forgot that

their basic task was to survive and reproduce, and reproduce

and survive and nothing more.

Even if we forget the essential underpinning and primacy of

survival values, as Sahlins tries to do in his notion of general

evolution, it is not clear what exactly is meant by 'greater

energy exploitation' which is advanced by him as the key

criterion in the new formulation. 'Thermodynamic achieve-

ment or accomplishment' is supposed to be the objectively

measurable distinguishing feature of general evolution as con-

trasted with specific evolution. But if it is a quantitative notion,

it could be measured on@y in terms of some input-output ratio

where the efficiency of the transforming structure would be

reflected in either cutting down the loss involved in the trans-

formation, or in its relative ability of translating potential

energy into actual energy, or in transforming it into a more

serviceable form. This is necessitated by the principle- of con-

se,rvation of energy which implies, in principle, the quantitative

equivalence between input and output. In real terms, therefore,

there can be no gain or loss. It only appears to be so because of

our desires, interests and purposes. The, deeper point, however,

relates to the fact that the criterion of energy-exploitation

cannot but be purely quantitative, in nature. There is little

reason to think. that great qualitative achievements also involve

great expenditure of energy. A person running a race obviously

uses a greater amount of energy than, say, one who composes a

The Criterion as Diferentiation 63

poem or solves a mathematical problem or cogitates about a

philosophical issue. Not only this, one could not even distinguish

between a good or bad poem or between elegant and inelegant

solutions to a mathematical problem or between a profound and

trivial cogitation on a philosophical issue on the basis of the

amount of energy spent on them. In fact, one could not even

distinguish between absolute failure and relative success on any

such ground. Yet, this is what Sahlins requires the criterion to

do. But it is obvious that it is impossible, in principle, for the

criterion to achieve this. One cannot wring out quality from

quantity, however hard one may try. But without this, Sahlins'

criterion is as useless as any other.

Sahlins fails to see the problem as he smuggles in the notion

of 'higher' levels or states without specifying what he means by

'higher' or 'lower' in this context. He argues, 'it is the amount

(of energy) so trapped (corrected for gross size of the form) and

the degree to which it is raised to a higher state that would seem to be

evolutionary measure- of life.'39 Now, not only does he not give

any detailed measurements of the energy so trapped by various

species determining their absolute ranking in general evolution,

but he also fails to specify what it means for the energy to be

raised to a 'higher state', and how it is to be measured.

The utterly unoperationalized use of concepts to demarcate

a fundamental distinction in one of the major areas of biological

theory suggests not only the theoretical naivet6 of the author,

but also reflects on those, who have hailed it as a major achieve-

ment concerning the theory of evolution. As far as energy is

concerned, there can only be 'more' or 'less', but not 'higher'

or 'lower'. Perhaps, Sahlins does mean by 'higher', what is

usually meant by 'more', for there is a usage in which it just

means that. But then it is doubtful if he could establish his

thesis at all, as mos 't of the major achievements of man which

enable him to exploit larger amounts of energy than any other

species on this planet are themselves not the result of the

possession of any greater energy on his part or of its greater

utilization in quantitative terms.

The same may be said With respect to Sahlins' attempt to

correlate 'thermodynamic accomplishment' with what he calls

its 'structural concomitant', that is, 'greater organization'. It

may be so in some cases but there equally are cases where it is

64 Political Develo

,pment

not so. Otherwise, the movement towards simplifying structures

would always mean a depletion of energy, which it does not,

either in theory or practice. As we have already pointed out,

there can be such a thing as 'over-organization' and 'too much

structure'. And, on a purely qualitative level, it would be

equally difficult for anyone to maintain that Baroque is the

highest form of architecture merely because it is more com-

plexly organized than others; or, that the attempt of many

modern artists to achieve almost ideal simplicity of structure is

bound to be self-defeating, as it violates the criterion derived

from a study of what Sahlins calls 'general evolution'.

Thus, Sahlins' attempt to link the notions of diitcrentiated

and complex structures to those of development in the absolute

sense of the term via his notion of general evolution'fails as much

as the attempts of other evolutionists who do not make any

such distinction. All the considerations urged earlier against

the position on evolution typified by a thinker such as Huxicy,

apply equally to Sahlins. And if evolution can provide no

grounding to the criterion of development as 'differentiation,'

it is difficult to believe that anything else could. It was perhaps

natural for political scientists to accept the authority of biology

which had in their eyes the status and prestige of a natural

science. But a more critical attitude would have revealed that

everything which is propagated in the name of 'natural science'

is not 'scientific'. The resurgence of neo-evolutionism in the

social sciences, then, is the revival of a superstition which was

thought to have been banished long ago. Political science can

hardly gain anything by basing its notion of 'political develop-

ment' on such a weak foundation.

NOTES

1. See Sol Tax, Evolution After Darwin, vol. 111 (Chicago: University of Chicago

Press, 1960), pp. 249-61.

2. Ibid., pp. 260-1.

3. Ibid., p. 7 1.

4. G. E. Moore, Principia Ethira (Cambridge. Cambridge University Press, 1903).

5. Tax, p. 41.

6. Ibid., pp. 42-3.

The Criterion as Diferentiation 65

7. 'Everybody', meaning every 'serious scientist', whatever may be incant by

that term.

8. Tax, vol. 11, p. 473.

9. Ibid., vol. 11, p. 460, italics mine.

10. Ibid., vol. Ill, p. 255.

11. See in this connection Sir julian 1-luxley's Introduction to Teilhard de

Chardin's 77m Phenomenon of Man, and the review of the same book by P. B.

Medawar, included in his work, The Art of & Soluble (London.. Methuen,

1967).

12. See in this connection the interesting discussion between Gerard, who ask,

'Why is not the replication of the architecture of a crystal or the replication ol

a branching polymer from monomers, which depends on the preexisting

polymer, life?' and others, in Tax, vol. Ill, pp. 80-4.

13. For a discussion of this question, see p. 41 ff.

14. Tax, vol. Ill, p. 562.

15. Medawar, p. 77.

16. Tax, vol. Ill, p. 280, italics author's.

17. Ibid., p. 249.

18. Ibid., p. 79.

19. Ibid., p. 81, italics author's.

20. Ibid., p. 81.

21. Moore, p. 28, italics author's.

22. Ibid., pp. 47A.

23. Gregory Bateson, Steps k an &ology of Mind (New York: Ballantine Books,

1972), p. 451.

24. Marshall D. Sahlins and Elman R. Service, Evolution and Culture (Ann Arbor:

University of Michigan Press, 1968).

25. Ibid., p. 19.

26. Ibid., p. 33.

27. Ibid., p. 16.

23. Ibid.

29. Ibid., p. 14.

30. Ibid., p. 20.

31. Ibid.

32. Ibid.

33. Ibid.

34. Ibid., p. 21, italics mine.

35. Ibid., p. 2 1.

36. Ibid., pp. 21-2.

37 Ibid., p. 22.

38. Ibid., pp. 22-3, italics mine.

39. Ibid., p. 2 1, italics mine.

3

THE CRITERION AS CAPABILITIES

If 'participation' seemed to emerge naturally as a criterion of

development immanent to the realm of the polity itself, and

'differentiation' as relating to the structure which all politics

,must have, the criterion in terms of 'capabilities' may be said to

belong to the functions which every political system is expected

to perform. And, as any system may work well or ill, better or

worse, we may determine the degree to which it performs its

functions. Also, as presumably all political systems are expected

to perform the same functions, they may be compared with

one another in respect of the way they discharge these functions.

Development in this context would perhaps mean the elabora-

tion of such new political structures as raise the very level of

performance itself. The 'raising of the level' would perhaps

mean a rise in both the floor and the ceiling of the performance

concerned.

The term 'capabilities', on the other hand, has another

dimension which relates it primarily to a polity's relations with

other politics. There certainly are relati 'ons which a polity has

with members and groups belonging to itself, but, in a world

where other politics exist, its 'capabilities' are measured with

respect to what it can do to use, exploit, overcome and even

conquer other politics for its own benefit. In former times,

there was little hypocrisy about all this. It was regarded as the

first duty of a ruler to enlarge his domains, conquer other king-

doms, capture booty and slaves, force them to pay tribute and

accept his suzerainty or sovereignty over them. Until compara-

tively recently, the great rulers in history have always been

those who founded or extended or consolidated great empires.

The art of war, in a certain sense, presupposed 'high capability'

in all fields and was perhaps its ultimate test also. Yet, few thinkers

The Criterion as Capabilities 67

in modern times would be prepared to accept this in its naked

formulation. It is difficult for them to believe that Tamerlane

or Genghis Khan had created a more developed political struc-

ture than the civilizations they destroyed. And if war were to be

accepted as an arbiter of 'political development', then political

scientists would have to welcome it as the ultimatejustifier of all

their hypotheses about which polity happened to he more

'politically developed' on the basis of their measurements.

It may seem a little far-fetched to bring in 'success in war'

as the operational criterion for judging the relative 'capabili-

ties' of different politics. But, basically, there could he no

other criterion, unless we accept that a polity defeated in war

could still be regarded as 'politically developed' in the sense

that it had greater 'capabilities' than the one that defeated it.

As this would seem to many to be almost a contradiction in

terms, there appears no escape to accepting the consequences of

admitting 'capabilities' as the criterion of 'political develop-

ment', unless we are prepared to give up the criterion itself. It

may not he amiss here to note that this is also one of the con-

sequences of the so-called evolutionary perspective in the study

of political development. To be defeated in the struggle for

survival is the ultimate test of evolutionary inferiority. The

business of war is superior to the business of peace which, in this

perspective, is nothing but the continuation of war by other

means. The phrase is that of Clausewitz, but the truth of the

contention is merely a function of the perspective in which it is

embedded.

The existence of politics other than one's own is, however,

logically contingent in the sense that they are not necessarily

presupposed by the existence of one's own polity. To put it in

other words, there is no necessity for there to be politics rather

than just one polity. And, in case there were to be only one

polity, there will he no problem of its proving its superiority in

political development over others through victory in war. But

though a polity may be one, yet even in its case, there is the

problem of its relationship with its own members. And these

relationships can be of various kinds. Also, over a period of time

the relationships may change and thus raise the problem of

political development or decay in a diachronic perspective.

What sort of relationships, then, are to be taken as signs of

68 Political Development

9political development', and of 'political decay'? Considered in

the perspective of 'capabilities' as the criterion of 'political

development', there could be little doubt about the answer.

Only a polity which extracts the utmost out of its members

could be regarded as 'politically developed'. It will be the

degree of exploitation or extraction achieved that would deter-

mine the degree of development attained by a polity. But this

would be to underwrite totalitarian dictatorship as the most

developed form of political system, as presumably it is the most

efficient organizational instrument for the extraction of what-

ever is sought to be extracted by the ruling 6lite of a polity.

Hitler's Germany and Stalin's Russia would be the most devel-

oped politics according to this criterion.

In a certain sense, the very notion of the state as the embodi-

ment of supreme coercive power may be said to underwrite the

primacy of the coercive function which a polity is supposed to

perform. It is a short step from this to regard an increase in the

coercive capabilities of any polity as a sign of its political devel-

opment. And once this step is taken, there is little to stop it

from being regarded as a desirable goal in the direction of

which every polity should try to develop. There is, in fact, a

fundamental ambivalence in the notion of the state as embody-

ing the unity of society in itself and also as being the ultimate

scat of coercive power. The notion of coercion divides the polity

into those who are coerced and those who coerce, while the

notion of unity tries to suggest the common interest of the whole

which is supposed to be embodied in the state. The bridge

between the two conflicting aspects is built by the pernicious

doctrine enshrined in Marxist apologetics that coercion is ex-

ercised in the interest of those who are coerced. There is,

however, the complementary truth in the deeper thought of

Marx that till the actuality of coercion exists, no state can claim

to embody the unity which it ideally wishes to be. This, of

course, is coupled with the Marxist illusion that the continuing

technological miracle of capitalism when combined with the

organizational, institutional structure of a socialist society would

result in the elimination of conflicting class interests which

necessitate the coercive character of the state. But even if the

utopian vision of a society to which the science of economics

would have become irrelevant (because of the non-scarcity of

The Criterion as Capabilities 69

goods and services) were to be accepted as factually possible, it

is difficult to.sce how the essential asymmetry of power-relations

could be avoided without giving up the notion of polity alto-

gether. Perhaps it is felt that the asymmetry of power-relations

is itself a consequence of the existent scarcity of goods and

services, and the abolition of the latter would also mean the

abolition of the former. But in that case a polity would no more

remain a polity. Rather, it would lapse into society from which

all political scientists have tried to distinguish it. Yet, to the

extent that the necessity of the distinction remains, a polity's

claim to represent or articulate the so-called unity of society

would be suspect.

It may be urged, on the other hand, that the functions of the

state may be conceived better in a different way. After all, no

state has ever been valued just for its victories over others or for

its coercive control over its own people. It is the ideas and ideals

embodied in the notion of the welfare state that point to the

way the concept of 'capabilities' should be understood and

articulated. -But this would lead to the question of choosing

between diverse notions of welfare and of exploring the inter-

relations between them. 'Welfare', obviously, is not such a

homogeneous category as many seem to think, nor is the rela-

tion between its different conceptions so positively correlated

as many appear to imply. Even the question of weightage

between different conceptions is not easy to handle, and the

ultimate choice between a laissez-faire notion of the state, which

allows the issue between different weightages to he settled by

the market-mechanism whether of the economic or political

variety, or the @lite decision of a dominant minority, which is

supposed somehow to know the real interests of the people, is

difficult to make. Perhaps, at least on the intellectual plane, the

honest solution may be said to lie in articulating with clarity as

many concepts of 'welfare' as one can think of, provide diverse

weightages in different models. and work out the possible co-

herence and incoherence between them.

But, however honest such a solution may seem, it would

introduce a plurality into the very heart of 'welfare', and thus

jeopardize the idea of 'political development' in terms of which

different politics were sought to be measured and compared. It

'nay be objected that, theoretical subtleties and logical possibili-

6

70 Political Development

ties apart, the notion of 'welfare' belongs primarily to the realm

of material goods and public services with special emphasis on

their just or equitable distribution between groups and classes

of people. Yet, even if this were- to be accepted there would

remain a formidable difficulty in conceiving of 'capabilities' in

terms of 'welfare' alone in total exclusion of all other notions of

'capabilities', specially those that concern the relation of a

polity to other politics. It is possible that a high rate of per

capita consumption of goods and services in a particular polity

is itself a direct consequence of its direct or indirect exploitation

of other politics, making it impossible for the exploited politics

to achieve higher rates of 'welfare' for their citizens. This

situation is not likely to be affected in any substantial manner

by the extent of distributive justice obtaining in a particular

polity. For it is highly probable that a substantially high level

of distributive justice in a particular society is itself ensured by

the fact that it is able to exploit others to a significant degree.

The role of colonial exploitation in the development of indus-

trial societies.of the West is well known. But what is not so well

known is the fact that the ideal of the welfare state with the

corresponding notion of distributive justice might not have

featured in the practical programme of hard-headed politicians

except for the fact that a situation of relative abundance had

been created by that very exploitation of colonial peoples.

The so-called socialist countries are in this respect no different

from those that are called capitalists. The relations of the Soviet

Union to countries of Eastern Europe which it had conquered

niilitarily from Hitler's Germany did not show any marked

difference from those between Western countries and the

territories they had conquered earlier in Asia and Africa.

Marxist thought has always pointed out the crucial importance

of the accumulation of capital. But the need and the necessity

of this accumulation has got nothing to do with either the

socialist or the capitalist character of a polity. It has to do only

with the economic factors involved in the situation. Marx was

saved from this terrible realization by the fact that in his own

thought he relegated this necessary but unpleasant task to

capitalism which was supposed to have completed the process

by the time socialism appeared on the scene. Unfortunately, the

countries in which the communist movement succeeded did not

The Criterion as Capabilities 7 1

have their work of capital accumulation completed by the

capitalists and thus it had to be undertaken by the communists

themselves. In doing so, they not only put the capitalist ex-

ploiters to shame- by showing how the whole thing could be done

more efficiently, but also, incidentally, proved the utter ir-

relevance of the capitalist-communist dichotomy to the issue

concerned.

The deeper assumption of Marx, however, consists in his

belief that there is some sort of upper limit beyond which

further accumulation of capital in significant quantities is not

needed. But this could only be true on the basis of a static

economy which would involve not only a static population and

a static technology, but also a static structure of wants. On the

other hand, one could perhaps assume a moving equilibrium

between the three to give the same result also. But, whether the

situation is conceived of in terms of a moving equilibrium or a

static economy, the assumed conditions seem too unrealistic to

be taken seriously. Even if they were to be realized, it could

only be by accident and for short periods. The need for savings

and capital accumulation for faster rates of economic growth

may, therefore, be assumed to obtain in most societies niost of

the time. And if savings and capital accumulation involve the

postponement of current consumption, necessitating painful

sacrifice on the part of the populace, it would always seem

preferable to impose this on other people or peoples of other

countries, if possible. It is usually done on both the fronts, and

that too simultaneously. But the rigours of internal exploitation

of one's own people can be niitigated to a large extent by the

external exploitation of other peoples. It thus serves in the

economic self-interest of a people to turn a blind eye to, if not

actively connive at and even welcome, the direct or indirect ex-

ploitation of other people. In fact, it is easier in respect of other

peoples as not only are aliens considered barbarians in almost

all cultures, but also because they are too distant for their

sufferings to be visibly registered on the sensitivities of those who

benefit from the exploitation. Of course, the same mechanism

is used for safeguarding one's own psyche against the intrusion

of the fact of exploitation of others even within one's own society

or country. But as there is at least some identification specially

in the context of societies which have become nation-states with

72 Political Development

universal franchise and citizenship, it becomes a little more

difficult to continue to do so than in the case of peoples with

whom one has little, if any, identification.

The notion of distributive justice in the context of material

goods and services in terms of which a polity's 'capabilities' are

supposed to be measured thus makes sense only if the whole

world were to be a unified political system. Yet, if that were to

be the case, the only assessment of comparative 'capabilities'

would be with respect to the world polity's own past, as there

would be no other polity with which it could be compared. This

might be taken as rendering the whole enterprise of finding a

measurable criterion of political development meaningless.

What purpose would it serve to formulate a criterion if there

are no politics to compare? Yet, if multiple politics are to be

necessarily postulated so that criteria for purposes of comparison

may be significantly employed, it is very likely that the so-

called 'political development' of a particular polity may imply

as a necessary precondition the lack of such development in

other politics. And this, not only in the logical sense that 'more

developed' implies the 'less developed', but in the causal sense

that one becomes more developed' by making some other

people or country 'less developed'.

The objection may be raised that we are taking too seriously

the Marxist analysis which predicates economic development

on the necessary exploitation of the producers of their surplus

value, and its utilization as investment for further production.

The term 'exploitation' in Marx is both a technical and a moral

term, the two senses of which are conflated together to produce

the scientific revolutionary ardour which most communists

claim for themselves. But, as psychologists have pointed out,

most violent emotions thrive on confused thought, and the

Marxist revolutionary seems no exception to this. To the extent

that the notion of 'exploitation' is the result of a technical

definition it can have no moral connotation. It may give a

scientific aura, but that is another matter.

The hard core of Marx's definition of exploitation lies in its

being derivative from the more fundamental notion of 'value-

creation' in his system. 'Exploitation' is, on the one hand, a

function of the notion of 'value-creation' in his system and, on

the other, of the fact as to whether the surplus value so created

The Criterion as Capabilities 73

is appropriated by the creator himself or by somebody else. As

Marx does not concede the value-creating function to the

entrepreneur, all collective value-creation is bound, by defini-

tion, to be exploitative in character. Similarly, because Marx

does not accord any value-creating function to the socio-

political functionaries who ensure the existence of conditions

without which no productive activity can occur for long, any

complex society is bound to be 'exploitative' by definition. The

only way to get out of this definitional impasse is to give- up the

definition, and see society as a co-operative enterprise in which

each is necessary for the other. This also could take us out of

the necessity of seeing a polity as an exploitative mechanism.

The functional perspective in the social sciences tries to do just

this; but in doing so, it unwittingly underwrites the, justification

of all existing institutions, whatever may be their complexion

or character. It excludes the idea of 'institutionalized exploita-

tion' by definition andjustifies the status quo, whatever may be

its nature. This, in fact, is the critique from the radical camp

of the structural-functional perspective in sociology. The con-

cept of 'dysfunctionality' tries to take care of this, but in doing

so it takes the heart out of functionalism itself.

The Marxian and the non-Marxian frameworks, thus, suffer

from an identical defect. They make it impossible for a so-

ciety or polity to be both 'exploitative' and 'co-operative' in

character. What is needed, therefore, is a conceptual framework

which, without making all social relations necessarily exploita-

tive, does not gloss over the fact of exploitation itself. This,

however, is not exactly our task here, and may, therefore,

merely be taken as a criterion of the adequacy of any con-

ceptual framework in this field.

The thinking of 'capabilities' in terms of 'social justice',

specially in its economic form, thus, encounters basic problems

which appear difficult to avoid, at least as presented in the

usual form. The other direction which comparison of 'capabili-

ties' in terms of the amount of 'social justice' achieved in

different politics may take, is what has usually been called the

observance of 'due process of law'. Law, in fact, is supposed to

ensure justice, and to the extent a polity is able to ensure that

no discrin-iination is practised in the application of the law to

different classes or castes or categories of persons, it may be

74 Political Development

said to have actualized or achieved a just state of affairs within

its boundaries. The laws themselves, however, may be con-

sidered discriminatory or even unjust in a deeper sense. The

usual Marxist critique tends to emphasize this aspect of the

matter. But, then, it is obvious that the critique of any positive

law can only be undertaken in terms of some ideal notion of

justice which the usual thinking about law designates as 'natural

law'. The critique may, of course, be undertaken from different

viewpoints. But, then, the natural laws implicit in them would

also be diverse, and though there will be a natural tendency to

decide between the different ideals or seek some overarching

coherence or transcending synthesis between them, the result

can hardly be expected to be acceptable to all or even taken as

final by any particular group for all times.

The comparative estimate of 'social justice', then, may per-

haps best be undertaken by finding on the one hand the extent

to which 'due process of law' is observed in a particular polity

and, on the other hand, to discover the extent to which its

positive law departs from the natural law as conceived of or

determined by a particular group of thinkers. The other dimen-

sion which should perhaps equally be taken into account relates

to the actuali@y of discrimination in the application of law to

persons of different economic, social, political or racial status in

a polity. This obviously is different from the degree of actual

observance of 'due process of law' as demanded by the legal

system itself. The former concerns itself with the distortion or

even perversion of the positive legal system by forces extraneous

to it, while- the latter concerns itself with the 'manner' rather

than the 'matter' of justice as ensured by law. The- idea, of

course, is that the observance of due procedure is as important

as the final .udgment reached or delivered in any case. It is

an emphasis on the formal aspect of the matter, a counterpart

of the notion of 'formal truth' in Western logic.

'Social justice', however, forms only one part of the total

spectrum of values which a society tries to realize for itself, and

the 'capabilities' of a polity may be judged by finding the

extent to which it is able to achieve their realization for its

citizens, both individually and collectively. The 'values' whose

realization is to be assessed may be those professed by the

society itself, or those by the thinker concerned. But, whatever

The Criterion as Capabilities 75

the case, they have to be specifically articulated so that the

assessment may be made as openly and concretely as possible.

However, even then the distinction between 'manifest' and

'latent' values, 'verbalized' and 'behavioural' values, and

between 'individual' and 'collective' values would have to be

keptin mind.

On the other hand, the notion of 'capabilities' may be seen

in predominantly 'instrumental' terms, that is, as essentially

neutral between the realization of diverse kinds of value. It

would be like 'wealth' or 'power' which, it is generally ad-,

mitted, may be used for the achievement of different ends,

depending upon what one desires to achieve. And, even though

it may be true that there are many things intrinsically valuable

which cannot be achieved by these generalized instrumental-

ities, it can hardly he disputed that, in certain amounts, they

are the necessary precondition for the realization of any value

whatsoever. This perhaps follows from the fact that our exis-

tence is an embodied existence, and that the notion of the

%realization' of values involves their concrete embodiment in

spatio-temporal reality where it achieves a public visibility

which is different from mere imaginative projection.

Such an 'instrumental-neutral' sense of 'capabilities' has been

worked out in detail by Almond in his 'Input-Output' model

of a political system in which the relationship between the two

is mediated by what he calls 'conversion-functions'. It is the

best-thought-out framework for the understanding of political

systems in a comparative developmental perspective yet to be

offered by any political thinker who has devoted himself to the

task. It therefore deserves the serious and sustained attention

of anyone concerned with the notion of 'political development'

and its availability for a comparative assessment of different

political systems in a cognitively significant and meaningful

way.

The 'Input-Output' model of Almond has been developed

over a long period and adumbrated in a number of books and

articles published at different times. However, it would perhaps

not be wrong to concentrate on only a few focal expressions of

his ideas which seem sufficient for our purposes. These are

found in his book Comparative Politics: A Developmental -4pproach'

and two articles, entitled 'A Developmental Approach to

76 ' Political Development

Political Systems'2 and 'Political Development-Analytical and

Normative, Perspectives'.3

He takes from David Easton the distinction between two

classes of inputs into the political system, viz. demands - and

supports. Demands are further classified under four headings:

(1) demands for goods and services such as wage and hour laws,

educational opportunities, recreational facilities, roads and trans-

portation;

(2) demands for the regulation of behaviour, such as provision of

public safety, control over markets and labour relations, rules

pertaining to marriage and the family;

(3) demands for participation in the political system, for the right to

vote, hold office, petition govermnental bodies and officials,

organize political associations and the like; and

(4) symbolic inputs, such as demands for the display of the majesty

and power of the political system in periods of threat or on

ceremonial occasions, or demands for the affirmation of norms or

the communication of the policy intent from political 61iteS.4

Support inputs also may be classified under four headings:

(1) material supports, such as the payment of taxes or other levies,

and the provision of services; such as labour contributions or

military services;

(2) obedience to.laws and regulations;

(3) participation, such as voting, joining organizations, and com-

municating about politics; and

(4) manifestation of deference to public authority, symbols and

ceremonials."

The output side is also classified into four types of transac-

tions initiated by the political system. These are:

(1) extractions, which may take the form of tribute, booty, taxes, or

personal services; (2) regulation of behaviour, which may take a

variety of forms and affect some subset of the whole gamut of human

behaviour and relations; (3) allocations or distributions of goods and

services, opportunities, honors, statuses, and the like; and (4) symbolic

outputs, including affirmation of values, displays and political sym-

bols, statements of policies and intent."

The inputs consisting of demands and supports are converted

by the political system into 'extractive, regulative, distributive

and symbolic outputs'.7 The political system, so to say, 'pro-

The Criterion as Capabilities 77

cesses inputs, and converts them into outputs'." 'The demands

entering the political system are articulated, aggregated, or

combined; converted into policies, rules, regulations; applied,

enforced, adjudicated."a The conversion-functions of the politi-

cal system, thus, may be divided into.

(1) the articulation of interests or demands; (2) the integration or

combination of interests into policy proposals; (3) the conversion of

policy proposals into authoritative rules; (4) the application of general

rules to particular cases; (5) the adjudication of rules in individual

cases; and (6) -the transmission of information about these events

within the political system from structure to structure and between

the political system and its social and .international environrnents.10

These, in other words, are the well-known conversion-functions

of Interest Articulation, Interest Aggregation, Rule-Making,

Rule-Application, Rule-Adjudication and Political Commu-

nication. The Rule-Making, Rule-Application and Rule-

Adjudication are merely new names for the legislative, execu-

tive and judicial functions of traditional political theory. The

other three, however, have perhaps not been so explicitly for-

mulated before.

This rather detailed delineation of Almond's classificatory

terminology of Input-Output factors in his own words was

necessary in order to get as clear a grasp of his contention as

possible. It all seems very neat, clear-cut and precise till one

begins to examine it closely and ask some pertinent questions.

There is, first, a radical difference on the Input side between

Demands and Supports, and to treat the two together as though

they were of the same type is to confuse the issue at the very

beginning of the analysis. The two may, and actually do, vary

independently of each other and may even be opposed to each

other. Supports, in fact, are treated as almost the same as Output,

except for the fact that there is a difference in the point of view

from which the phenomenon is viewed. For example, the same

taxes or levies which are paid count as support-inputs when

regarded from the viewpoint of the taxpayer or the citizen who

has to pay the taxes or perform the services, and as an output

when viewed as extraction on the part of the political system

from its citizens. One wonders if the enforced collection of booty

and tribute on the part of an exploiting political 6lite would be

78 Political Development

called a Support-Input by Almond. The term' 'support', how-

ever, may not imply that what is given for the system is being

given,voluntarily and willingly, but only that it is being actually

given, whether willingly or not.

The same is true about all the other sub-divisions of the so-

called classification of Support-Inputs and Outputs quoted

earlier. One may, in fact, arrange them in tabular form facing

each other and see the point we are trying to make. The classi-

ficatory schema may be presented in the following way:

Supports (Inputs) output

1. Material supports, such as 1. Extractions, such as tribute,

payment of taxes or other booty, taxes, personal

levies, and the provision services, etc.

of services, etc.

2. Obedience to laws and 2. Regulation of behaviour

regulations

3. Participation, such as voting, 3. Allocation or distribution of

joining organizations, etc. goods and services, honours,

statuses, etc.

4. Symbolic output, such as

affirmation of values,

statement of policies, etc.

4. Manifestation of deference to

public authority, symbols and

ceremonies

The first, second and fourth items are obviously the same,

seen from two different sides. Only item 3 shows a discrepancy

which perhaps is mediated by the unstated assumption that

allocation or distribution is related in some direct or indirect

way to the actual fact of 'participation' in the system. But the

term 'participation' includes so many things that it is difficult to

consider all as Support-Inputs into the political system. In fact,

a closer scrutiny may reveal that it is difficult to distinguish in

many cases between the so-called Support-Inputs and Outputs

of the system. For example, it is not clear why the extractions

effected by a political system should be treated as its output,

when that is what it effectively gets from its subjects or other

politics in the environment for itself. Similarly, one wonders if

the output entitled 'Regulation of behaviour' refers to the actual

enforcement of law or merely to the making of laws which

hopefully will be obeyed by most of the people for whom they

are made. In the former case, they are completely identical with

The Criterion as Capabilities 79

the so-called Support-Input entitled 'Obedience to laws and

regulations'. 'In the latter, they would be identical with the

rule-making function which is supposed to be not an Output at

all but a conversion-function in Almond's system.

The role of conversion-functions will be analysed in Chapter

4, but here it may be pointed out that there seems to be little

consistency in the different Support-Inputs and Outputs that

are given in the table. Thus, while the first cannot be different

even in principle in the two columns, the second can be so only

if it is identified with a conversion-function. The fourth, on the

other hand, may he interpreted either as identical or different

depending upon the treatment of symbolic output, as that

which evokes a manifestation of deference whenever it is dis-

played, or as such whether it does so or not. The third, on the

other hand, bears hardly any relation unless it be assumed that

the distributive allocation of goods and services is in proportion

to one's participatory input into the political system. This

obviously is not the case, specially if we remember all the

ambiguities involved in the notion of 'participation' and the

related discussion concerning it in the first chapter.

The Input-Output model has been borrowed from economics

where it has been a relatively successful tool in assessing the

comparative efficiency of different economic systems. Yet, un-

less certain basic conditions are fulfilled, the model is not

meaningfully applicable, as it may make no sense to talk of

inputs and outputs in the situation. One such condition is the

existence of what may be called a common measure in terms of

which the so-called inputs and outputs may be aggregated,

computed and compared. The other, and perhaps even more

fundamental condition, is the existence of a fairly clear-cut

demarcation between what is to count as input and what as

Output. In other words, there should be fairly determinate

criteria on the basis of which we should be able to judge, at

least in most cases, which is to be regarded as input, and which,

output. The former condition is fulfilled in the field of eco-

nomics by money which functions as the common measure in

terms of which the value of everything may be expressed. The

second condition is also fulfilled almost completely in the case

of individual units, though in the case of large aggregates cer-

tain problems arise. What is input for one unit can be output

80 Political Development

for another, and thus the computation for the total economy

would obviously have to be different in character. Marx saw

this as the key issue with respect to the problem of profit, for

while one- could understand one man's profit as another person's

loss, how could one understand the profit in a total economy

where all the individual profits and losses would cancel out?

An analogous problem in the field of physics may be, said to

arise with respect to the conservation laws,which postulate a

complete constancy of mass orland energy in the total system.

The- problems arising out of the concept of a 'total system',

however, are so purely theoretical that none of the empirical

sciences concern themselves with them in great detail. Also,

at the purely theoretical level, the question always arises

whether the universe can be treated as a 'closed system',

specially when it has to be treated as essentially 'open' with

respect to time. But on the other hand, if it is not a closed

system, how can it be called a 'universe', or considered as a

'total system' ?

Time is essential to any Input-Output analysis. The purpose

of the undertaking is to know what amounts of input of a

particular kind would result in what amounts of output that

we want. For the basic purpose of the exercise is to be able to

control the phenomena to some extent at least'@The investment-

output ratio, for example, is a key factor in the planning of

economic development in any country. One would have to

know what rate of investment is needed to achieve a particular

growth rate in the economy. Similarly, one would have to,know

how much of the investment required is to come out of savings,

whether enforced or voluntary, and how much out of deficit

financing. Similarly, one has to have some idea of the direction

of investment and the so-called gestation period when the out-

put may be- expected.

These are all elementary examples, as every student of eco-

nomics knows. They can, however, he made as complicated

and sophisticated as one likes. The basic point, however, would

remain the same :An Input-Output analysis makes sense only

if we can determine what types of inputs determine what types

of outputs, and in what quantity. Also, we should be able to

control the inputs into the system to some extent so that we may

get the desired outputs. If these two conditions are missing, the

The Criterion as Capabilities 8 1

Input-Output analysis is a futile exercise which may provide

aesthetic satisfaction to those who undertake it, but is utterly

irrelevant for the understanding or the control of empirical

phenomena.

But these conditions are not found in the Input-Output

analysis offered for political systems by Almond. There is not

oni y no common measure in terms of which all the so-called

political inputs and outputs could be expressed, but also no

idea as to what types and quantities of inputs would result in

what types and quantities of outputs. Similarly, it is obvious

that the so-called inputs into the system cannot be controlled

in any significant sense of the term.

Almond, of course, has argued that amongst the possible

inputs in the system, the most important are those put in by

the political 6lites themselves. As he writes.. 'We do not wish

to leave the impression that inputs necessarily come only from

the society of Which the political system is a part, and that the

political system must be viewed only in "conversion" terms.

It is typical of political systems that inputs are generated

internally by political @lites-kings, presidents, ministers, legis-

lators'and judges."' It may, therefore, be legitimately held that

to the extent the inputs are generated by the political @lites

themselves, they can also be controlled by them. And if they

also form the most important part of the inputs, the control

exercised by them would become crucial also.

Unfortunately for Almond's analysis, his contention not only

cuts at the root of the Input-Output analysis, but also ignores

the fundamental difference between the inputs generated by

the political 6lites and those generated by all the rest for the

system. There seems to be a built-in structural conflict between

the inputs originating from the political 6lites and those ori-

ginating from others who do not occupy the position occupied

by the political @lites in the system. This arises mainly from the

fact that, while the major interest of the political 6lites is to

continue to occupy, strengthen and improve the positions they

already hold, the interest of those outside is to oust them from

the positions they are in. The so-called interest-aggregation

function about which we shall have more to say later on, finds

its essential limitation in the natural self-interest of the political

@lite to strengthen and perpetuate itself. This is perhaps a part

82 Political Development

of what are called the 'system maintenance and adaptation

functions', but it is clear that the terminology adopted merely

glosses over the essential conffict involved in the situation.

A deeper question arises with respect to the contention that

the political 6lites themselves generate demand-inputs into the

political system. Normally, a system does not have demands of

its own, except perhaps for its maintenance and perpetuation,

which mostly happen to be fairly conservative in character. The

Input-Output analysis takes the system for granted and works

only on the assumption that no arbitrary inputs shall be

generated by the system itsel£ The system's neutrality and

instrumentality is an essential prerequisite for any Input-

Output analysis to be successfully applicable also. The conten-

tion, therefore, that the most important inputs into the political

system arise from the political 6lites themselves renders the

whole Input-Output model irrelevant for purposes of political

analysis, unless we treat the political 6lites in this role as out-

siders to the system. This, however, would save the model at

the expense of making it almost impossible for empirical appli-

cation. If the political @lites occupying positions of power are

analytically treated as outsiders making demands on the

system, then the system would become almost metaphysical in

character. Or, alternatively, the system would become an

elaborate game where the same set of persons are alternatively

seen in their role of making demands on the system and then

in the role of fulfilling the dem -ands. made on them by the

system. This may be welcome to protagonists of the Theatre of

the Absurd, but presumably not to those who claim to be

political scientists.

The measurement of the 'capabilities' of a political system

in terms of Input-Output ratios on the model of economic

theory thus runs against some basic and fundamental difficulties

which do not appear easy to overcome. Perhaps it may be said

that the heart of the political system lies in what Almond has

called the 'conversion-functions', as it is primarily through them

that 'output' is realized by the political system. It may, then,

be in the performance of the 'conversion-functions', that the

concept of political development might find its sure footing and

in terms of which different politics could be compared. 4

detailed consideration of 'conversion-functions' is therefore.

The Criterion as Capabilities 83

required to find out whether they could adequately fulfil the

task of serving as possible criteria for judging political develop-

ment.

NOTES

1. Almond and Powell, Comparative Politks: A Developmental Approach (Boston:

Little, Brown & Co., 1966).

2. Almond, 'A Developmental Approach to Political Systems', World Politics,

vol. XVII, no. 2, January, 1965.

3. Almond, 'Political Development: Analytical' and Normative Perspectives',

Comparative Political Studies, vol. 1.

4. Almond, 'A Developmental Approach to Political Systems', World Politics,

vol. XVII, no. 2, January 1965, p. 193.

5. Ibid., pp. 193-4.

6. Ibid., p. 194.

7. Ibid.

8. Ibid., p. 195.

9. Ibid.

10. pp. 196-7.

11. Ibid., pp. 194-5.

4

THE CRITERION AS CONVERSION

FUNCTIONS

The 'conversion-functions' are divided by Almond into six

separate functions which, though interrelated, are yet regarded

as relatively autonomous in character. They are designated as

Interest Articulation, Interest Aggregation, Political Commu-

nication, Rule-Making, Rule-Application and Rule-Adjudica-

tion. The last three are the well-known functions of government,

traditionally designated as the legislative, executive and judi-

cial functions. Interest Aggregation is perhaps nearest to what

in traditional political theory is known as justice. Interest

Articulation is perhaps a new function explicitly ascribed to or

expected of a political system. On the other hand, political

communication is presupposed by all the other functions as

without it they could not be performed at all.

The conversion-functions may legitimately be regarded as

the heart of the political system, and thus it is reasonable to

expect that the criteria of political development may be found

there. The conversion-functions, however, happen to be both

relatively autonomous and interrelated in significant ways with

one another. Ii would therefore be desirable to consider them

both individually and in interrelationship with each other.

(1) The C@iterion as Interest Articulation

Interest articulation is regarded by Almond as 'particularly

important because it marks the boundary between the society

and the political system'.' He defines it as 'the process by which

individuals and groups make demands upon the political deci-

sion makers'.2 Even the differences between di&rent types of

political systems may be understood in terms of 'the forms which

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 85

interest articulation takes, the degree to which interest articula-

tion structures are specialized and autonomous and the style of

interest articulation' .3 Almond has divided his discussion of the

matter into four parts, viz. (1) the kinds of structures which

perform the interest articulation function; (2) the variety of

channels through which demands are articulated; (3) the

styles of interest articulation; and (4) the effects of moderniza-

tion on articulations

It is obvious, therefore, that to the extent interest articulation

is to be treated as a criterion of political development, it would

have to be considered in these dimensions. However, while one

is fairly clear that the degree of specialization and autonomy in

the structures that perform the function of interest articulation

and the varieties of channels through which the demands are

articulated would usually he accepted as indicating political

development, it is difficult to see what forms or styles of interest

articulation would be regarded as indicators of political devel-

opment.

The interest articulation structures have been classified

according to two major components: 'the type ofgroup initiating

the articulation, and the type of access channel through which it

passes the message'.5 Besides the generalized fact that indivi-

duals are 'articulators of their own interests'," and that there

are 'anomic interest groups'," the major division is between what

have been called 'nonassociational interest groups"' and 'institu-

tional interest grou

.ps'.9 Now, it may he taken for granted that,

given the perspective of the current writings on political devel-

opment, an increase in interest articulation would he taken as

a positive indicator of political development. But it is not quite

clear whether equal weightage is to be given to all the forms of

interest articulation. For example, should an increase in the

nonassociational interest group in relation to the institutional

interest groups be taken as indicating political development or

not? Similarly, if the reverse tendency is observed, how are we

to interpret it? Also, is an increase in the anomic interest groups

to be taken as an indicator of political development or political

decay? This is important, as the interest articulation of anoriiic

interest groups consists of 'riots, demonstrations, assassinations

,and the like''10 If treated as positive indicators along with all

other forms of interest articulation, we would have the problem

7

86 Political Development

of treating its absence as a counter indicator of political devel-

opment in many societies. In fact, riots, demonstrations,

assassinations, would have to be welcomed and even planned,

given such a positive interpretation of interest articulation of

anomic interest groups. On the other hand, if we treat it as a

negative indicator we would have the added problem of

balancing the weight of the negative indicators against the

positive. Further, if we have to distinguish 'between (a) spon-

taneous violence by anoniic interest groups, and (b) violence

and demonstrations as a means of access, which any group

may use'," we would have to face the added problem of either

regarding both as negative indicators or only one, and, if so,

which.

The problem gets more complicated if it is accepted, as

Almond and Powell do, that 'demonstrations and mass vio-

lence' may be 'an integral part of the system itself'.12 One

wonders what such a statement means. The reference to Peru

is not of much help as it is confined to the labour groups which

use it as a means 'to bring pressure to bear upon the centralized

executive'."3 Also, if 'violence always has the possibility of

passing beyond the control of its promoters',14 and if such a

'passing beyond' is accepted as undesirable, it is difficult to see

how violence could be treated as an integral part of the system

unless there are structural mechanisms to see that it does not

pass beyond some permissible lin-tit specified by the system

itsel£

The problem of associational interest groups and their

relative weightage vis-a-vis non-associational groups on the one

hand and institutional groups on the other, would also have to

be satisfactorily resolved if interest articulation is to be treated

as a criterion of political developments

Besides the problems posed by the diversity in structures

through which the conversion-function of interest articulation

is performed, it may be presumed to become even more com-

plicated if we are also expected to take into account the diversity

of access channels and the styles of interest articulation. Both

are supposed to be important in the classificatory scheme

elaborated by Almond and Powell, and if interest articulation

is to be treated as a criterion of political development, they

too must be taken into account.

The Criterion as Conversion Fun,@tions 87

The question of channels and means of access is, as Almond

and Powell urge, 'largely @x question of political communica-

tion'.'.5 But if so, it overlaps with another conversion-function

which is supposed to be independent and autonomous in

character. The interrelations between different conversion-

functions will he the subject of detailed discussion in section

(8) of this chapter, but the fact of significant overlapping

between them raises problems of its own. Political communica-

tion and channels of interest articulation are merely two names

for the same reality, just as style of interest articulation is the

same as designated by the term 'political culture'. Political

culture, of course, is wider than the style of interest articulation

as it includes patterns of political behaviour in other realms also.

But 'channels' of interest articulation are not a sub-sector of

political communication; they are identical with it. Such an

identification will become untenable if the 'communication'

of interests that are aggregated is also considered as political

communication. But, then, the so-called rule-making, rule-

application and rule-adjudication activities would also be seen

as performing the function of political communication and,

thus, fall under it.

The concept of 'communication channels' is wider in fact

than those which are supposed to subserve only the function of

political communication, or even just that of interest articula-

tion. It is doubtful if communication channels are ever so

specialized as to subserve only one function, he it political or

any other. Normally, the channels are neutral with respect to

the messages conveyed through them. However, when the

channels primarily consist of persons, there may be substantial

selectivity and systematic distortion in the messages that are

conveyed. Perhaps the distinctive nature of political commu-

nication may lie in the fact that it consists primarily of persons

who try to bring various matters to the notice of those who are

in a position to take effective decisions with respect to those

matters. There would then be the spedfic problems relating to

selectivity and distortion which are peculiar to human agents

of communication. But whatever be the problems, they would

hardly affect the basic identity of 'channels' of interest articula-

tion and political communication, as pointed out earlier.

The channels described by the authors range from physical

88 Political Development

demonstrations and violence to the formal and institutional

channels such as established political parties, legislatures,

bureaucracies and mass media. In between these two extremes

comes what they have called 'personal connection'. and '61ite

representation'. Similarly, in the discussion of political com-

munication, they have designated the major types of commu-

nication structures as '(1) informal face-to-face contacts, which

spring up more or less independently of other social structures;

(2) traditional social structures, such as family or religious

group relationships; (3) political "output" structures, such as

legislatures and bureaucracies; (4) political "input" structures,

including trade unions and similar interest groups, and political

parties; and (5) the mass media'.16

If we compare the two lists given above, one in the context

of interest articulation and the other in the context of political

communication, it is obvious that they are the same. The

channel designated as 'personal connection' in the context of

interest articulation has merely been bifurcated into two in the

context of political communication and designated 'informal

face-to-face contacts' and 'traditional social structures'. One

significant omission in the list of political communication

structures is the lack of any mention of physical demonstrations

and violence, which is supposed to play such an important role

in the channels of interest articulation that the authors have

gone out of their way to point out that it may be treated in at

least some cases as an integral part of the system itself. In fact,

the footnote on page 82 in connection with james L. Payne's

book Labour and Politics in Peru goes on to suggest that the 'views

of possible roles of violence long held by Western political

scientists"'7may just be ethnocentric. But if this is so, violence

would have to be taken as a positive indicator of political devel-

opment for, presumably, the ethnocentricity of western political

scientists lay in regarding it as negative in character. The still

more significant feature of the quotation designating the types

of communication structures, however' is its explicit admission

of political 'input' and 'output' structures. The signfficance of

this admission, particularly in relation to the conversion func-

tions and our earlier discussion on construing political develop-

ment in terms of input-output ratios, will be discussed later on.

Besides the diversity in the structures of interest articulation

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 89

and the channels through which they make themselves felt,

there is diversity in the styles of interest articulation. As

Almond and Powell write, 'The performance of the interest

articulation function may be manifest or latent, specific or

diffuse, general or particular, instrumental or affective in

style.'.18 Besides these, there is 'the distinction between a

pragmatic, instrumental style and an ideological one', which

'is particularly important in interest articulations The dimen-

sions in which the distinctions of style have been articulated by

the authors are too ivell known to students of political science

to need explication here. They are fairly close to the pattern-

variables of Parsons discussed earlier. The onl '

y important

departure from the Parsonian scheme lies in the admission of

the dichotomy, pragmatic vs. ideological. The use of the term

'instrumental' in the quotation is not very happy as it had

already been used by the authors as a contrast to 'affective'

and it does not exactly connote the contrast to the 'ideological'

which is sought to be conveyed by the term.

Further, it is diflicult to see how the contrast 'ideological-

pragmatic' could refer to s@yles of interest articulation. The

reference to catholic and communist groups in France and

Italy is hardly illuminating, as they are distinguished by the

content of their demands and their views about the nature and

function of political systems. It is not a question, therefore, of

style at all, but rather of a fundamental difference in the way

one conceives of the nature of a polity. In a sense, the other

contrasts also refer more to the content rather than the style

of interest articulation. However, perhaps the more relevant

point in the context of any discussion of political development

is to discover as to which of them are to be regarded as positive

or negative indicators of such development.

The Parsonian variables have been closely linked to the

dichotomy of tradition and modernity with which most socio-

logists and political scientists approach social and political

phenomena. As modernity is almost always treated as the

equivalent of development, the criteria characterizing modern-

ity are also treated as indicators of development. Thus it

is that manifestness, specificity, generality, and instrumentality

are usually treated as indicators of modernity and thus of

development also. There are certainly those who talk of the

90 Political Development

modernity of tradition and even question the identification of

Weberian 'rationality' with development.211 But such voices

are few and far between. The dominant majority still interprets

the notion of development in Parsonian and Weberian terms.

As Almond and Powell point out; 'The more latent and diffuse

the style of interest articulation, the more difficult it is to

aggregate interests and translate them into a public policy

which will alleviate sources of discontent.'21 And they write

further, 'rigid ideological perspectives, highly particularistic

demands, and emotionally charged expressions of desires also

make reconciliation of diverse interests more difficult than

when the style of these interests is more pragmatic and ins-

trumental'.22

The above interpretation of the styles of interest articulation

in the context of political development sees them primarily in

terms of their facilitating or hindering interest aggregation. But

if this be the case, then interest articulation per se cannot he an

index of political development in any significant sense of the

term. Rather, it would be the aggregation of interests which

would be central to the matter. But before we turn to a dis-

cussion of interest aggregation, it would be advisable to con-

sider the three dimensions of interest articulation together.

The predominant structures through which interests are

articulated, the type of access channels that are habitually

used and the styles which are most frequently adopted are the

three major dimensions in which the phenomenon of interest

articulation is to be assessed in relation to political development..

Normally, it may be assumed that an increase in institutional

and associational groups increasingly making use of political

parties, representatives in the legislature, bureaucracies and

the mass media for articulation of their interests in a pragmatic

manner and formulated with clarity, specificity and generality,

is a sign of political development in a society. On the other

hand, if non associational or anomic groups increasingly emerge

on the scene utilizing violence, demonstrations and riots for

the articulation of demands which are diffuse, particular, emo-

tional and ideological in nature, it would presumably indicate

political decay rather than political development in a society.

However, for those who opt for a dialectical view of develop-

ment such phenomena would have to be interpreted differently.

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 9 1

They would he seen as providing that dialectical tension which

would most probably result in a synthesis of conflicting interests

at a higher level. Also they would be seen as evidence of either

the absence, insufliciency or breakdown of the usual access

channels for the articulation of interests in a political system.

In other contexts, it might merely be evidence of extra pressure

generated by organized interests which are also using the

legitimate access channels for pressing their demands.

The problem posed by the diverse and conflicting interpreta-

tions of the same phenomenon depending upon the context in

which it is seen, the values in terms of which it is evaluated and

the understanding of the dynamics of the situation in terms of

what it is supposed to develop into, creates insuperable difficul-

ties in the way of any straightforward interpretation of any

phenomenon as an indicator of political development. Perhaps

the solution would lie in the explicit articulation of the values

in terms of which the evaluation is being done, the context in

which the phenomenon is being placed and the dynamic inter-

relationships on the basis of which the future is being pro-

jected. But the moment.this is done, alternative contexts, values

and dynamic interrelationships would come into the picture

and thejudgementaboutpolitical development begins to depend

upon the choices one makes regarding them. Also, the moment

all these factors are taken into account, the judgement would

become so subtly qualitative in nature as to lose all relevance

for purposes of quantitative measurement and comparison. It

would become more like the judgement of historians, and the

whole attempt to render the study of political science 'scientific'

would relapse into the situation from which it was sought to

be retrieved.

The deeper problem, however, relates to the assumption that

the articulation of any and every interest is desirable in a

polity, and that the task of a political system is to reconcile and

aggregate all interests so that they may be satisfied to the

maximum. The assumption, it is generally forgotten, pre-

supposes not only the primacy of politics but also its totaliy vis-

a-vis the social system. Such a totalitarian view of the function

of politics may be natural and perhaps even welcome to

practising politicians, but that it should be so to political

scientists also is surprising indeed. For, it should be obvious to

92 Political Development

them that if freedom is one of the central values to be preserved,

safeguarded and enhanced by the political system, it is essential

that freedom from politics itself be seen as one of its essential

components. It is not exactly a happy situation if people con-

tinuously think in terms of their interests, articulating them and

presenting them as demands to be fulfilled by the political

system. Political scientists hardly realize how much their view

of what may be called'political welfare'is built on the economic

model. Instead of 'wants', they talk of 'interests', and as 'wants'

for the economist are and ought to be unlimited, so also for the

political scientist 'interests' are and ought to be unlimited. But

as economists are discovering that 'unlirnitedness' of wants is

essentially suicidal when confronted with the essential 'limited-

ness' of non-renewable resources, so also political scientists

might discover increasing articulation of interests to c a

menace to the health and stability of a political system.

: The other assumption of those who write of interest articula-

tion in the context of political development appears to be that

the- 'interests' of various groups are ultimately harmonious in

character. For if this were not so, the more the interests were

articulated the more would they tear the polity apart by the

essential impossibility of the resolution of their conflict. The

Marxists, -along with all who have a dialectical view of devel-

opment, take just such a view of class interests. They treat them

as essentially irreconcilable and thus as the ultimate motive

force for the revolution through which alone antagonisms will

be resolved. But while the revolution reverses the position of

those who hold power, it does not abolish the conflict of interests

amongst the various groups, which is a result of that relative

scarcity of goods and services which renders, in principle, their

equal distribution impossible. The only recourse in such a situa-

tion is to suppress the articulation of interests as much as

possible, and to replace the notion of 'wants' with 'needs' in

the economic sphere and of 'interests' with 'values' in the

political sphere. The term 'values' refers to something for the

sake of which the 'interests' of individuals and groups, however

large, are sacrificed in a deliberate, self-conscious manner. The

use of brute, total and naked force for the achievement of these

objectives is well known to students of recent political history.

But what is not so well known is the fact that any society which

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 93

conceives of itself in terms of egocentric interests cannot but

lead to the development of an increasingly anarchic situation

which can be retrieved only by a dictatorship of some sort or

other. That this has not yet occurred in many western democra-

cies where the view of society as a field of competing interests

is propounded is merely due- to the fact that some- overarching

value system beyond the competing interests still obtains in

those societies and that, fortunately, many of them do not

practise what they preach.

The situation in the so-called developing countries, how-

ever, is radically different in that they seem to take the 'interest

articulation' view of a democratic polity too seriously and thus

consider it obligatory to encourage as much interest articula-

tion by as many groups as possible. This, however, leads only

to a situation of continuously increasing anarchy which is then

sought to be stopped by one form of totalitarian control or

other. The counterpart of Adam Smith's 'hidden hand', though

not explicitly formulated in democratic political theory, has

yet to be postulated to make it function. But as the 'hidden

hand' is provided only by cultural and motivational con-

straints, it may not he available at hand to counteract the drive

towards anarchy inherent in the 'interest' view of politics pro-

pounded by many political scientists who have recently written

on the subject.

There is, however, a deeper distinction from the realm of

economics which, if not noticed, may lead to even greater

disasters for political thought and consequently for political

practice also. Economic theory at least ensures that if the con-

ditions of perfect competition were realized, prices would

stabilize at a point maximally advantageous to everyone con-

cerned. It may be true that the existence of quasi-monopolistic

institutions on the one hand and the differential distribution of

income on the other perpetually stand in the way of the achieve-

ment of conditions of perfect competition in any society what-

soever. But at least the theory assures us that if it were to be

achieved, maximal satisfaction and utilization of resources

would be ensured. Unfortunately for political theory, it can

ensure nothing of the kind. Even if each person were to arti-

culate all the interests he has, there is nothing in the theory to

show that they must reach an equilibrium point where maxi-

94 Political Development

mum satisfaction will be ensured for all the interests of all the

people.

It may be urged that the articulation of interests may range

from the mere expression of a demand to a sustained and con-

certed action for its achievement even at the cost of staking

one's life for the fulfilment of the demand. The genuine intensity

of the demand could thus be weighed on a graded scale deter-

mined by the actual sacrifice one is willing to make for its

fulfilment. The sacrifice would thus be the cost that one is

willing to incur for the fulfilment of one's interest and the

equilibrium point reached when one of the parties to the con-

flict of interests decides that it is not in its interest to make any

more sacrifices for the fulfilment of its demands. The limiting

case would be reached, as in the case of war, when one or both

the parties decide to fight to the finish till one or the other is

completely subjugated or annihilated. This would be the

analogue of the price-theory in economics, where the effective-

ness of demand is measured by what one is prepared to pay for

it. But to judge the effectiveness of an interest in terms of the

'force' that one is prepared to exercise for its achievement is to

revert back to a view of politics propounded by Thrasymachus

in Plato's Republic and Hobbes in his Leviathan. There is, of

course, no intellectual harm in this provided it is done openly

and with full consciousness of all the consequences. The

equilibrium point on such a view, it should be clearly under-

stood, has nothing to do with the so-called 'maximal fulfilment

of diverse interests'. Rather, it is a situation where those who

have the utmost power rule, and those who have lost the battle

for power have either already lost their lives or preferred to live

in subjugation or slavery.

'Interest articulation', then, can hardly serve by itself as an

indicator of political development. In different contexts an

increase in it either in terms of extent or intensity or both may

mean a growth in the political awareness of a people or just an

overloading of the political system leading to its breakdown

and decay. In fact, as in most cases the demands on the political

system would tend to outrun its capacity to meet them, the only

likely result would be increasing revelation of the incapacity of

the system to meet the demands made upon it, resulting in its

replacement by a system which does not permit the freedom of

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 95

'interest articulation' by the citizens, or restricts it severely. It

may be suggested, therefore, that the heart of the problem of

political development should be sought in 'interest aggregation',

rather than in 'interest articulation', since whether the interests

are articulated or not the task of a polity is to aggregate the

diverse interests to the utmost possible extent.

(2) The Criterion as Interest Aggregation

To turn from interest articulation to interest aggregation as

a criterion of political development is to turn from what is

demanded of a political system to what it actually delivers to its

members for whom it is supposed to function. And there can

perhaps be little doubt that a political system should ultimately

be judged by what it does for its citizens. However, if what is

done is seen in terms of 'interests' and that too of those who are

able to articulate them most effectively, there would be an

in-built distortion in the criterion itself. For the interests of

even those who are not able to articulate themselves ought to

be of paramount concern to the polity. And, at a still deeper

level, what should engage the attention of a polity is not so

much the satisfaction of interests as the facilitation of the

realization of value or values for its people.

The term 'interest aggregation', however, is unfortunate in

another respect. Even if we talk in terms of 'interests', what

is sought to be achieved is not so much an aggregation as a

reconciliation of diverse and opposing interests. The term 'ag-

gregation' is too summative in nature to convey the difficulty

and complexity of the task involved. Further, in the specific

technical sense in which it is used by Almond and Powell, it

connotes only the intermediate stage of aggregation rather than

the final stage where what is aggregated takes the form of

positive enactment as law. It is related more to the phase where

policy alternatives are formulated rather than to that where a

final choice with respect to policy alternatives is made. Accord-

ing to Almond and Powell, 'The function of converting de-

mands into general policy alternatives is called interest aggrega-

tion.'23 Also, it is made explicitly clear that the term 'interest

aggregation' is reserved 'for the more inclusive levels of the

combinatory process-the structuring of major policy alterna-

96 Political Development

tives and also distinguish it from the final process of authorita-

tive rule making'.24

It is of course conceded that every articulation of interest

involves an 'interest aggregation' of some sort, and that com-

plete aggregation is made only at the level when an authorita-

tive rule is finally formulated. As the authors write, 'interest

aggregation can occur at many points in the political system',

and that even 'a single individual may take into account a

variety of claims and considerations before articulating his own

demands' .25 In fact, 'some degree of aggregation is almost

inevitably carried out at all levels from individual interest

articulation to the final decision-making' .26 But if this is the

situation, what is the point of treating it as a separate category,

completely dissociated from interest articulation, on the one

hand, and rule-making, on the other? The only justification

offered is that unless there are some such midway institutions

specializing in the task of aggregating diverse and different

interests that have been articulated at various levels in the

system, the final decision-maker will be overwhelmed by the

indefinite multiplicity of interests pressing for his attention and

be either completely immobilized from taking any decision or

forced into erratic or impulsive decisions.

But 'immobilism' or 'impulsive decisions' are not exactly a

function of the 'non-aggregation' of interests in a polity because

of the absence of specific, differentiated structures devoted to

the performance of that task. The first usually results from the

fact that the conflicting interests seem so balanced against one

another that it is difficult to favour one or the other without

disturbing the unity and peace of the polity in a substantial

manner. On the other hand, it may also be a result of the

psychological inability of the political elite to take difficult and

unpleasant decisions which may disturb the status quo in a sub-

stantial manner. But whether the reason for 'immobilism' lies

in the first or the second or a blend of both, it can hardly be

said to be due to the fact that a polity has not evolved dif-

ferentiated structures to perform the task of 'interest aggrega-

tion'. Similarly, it is difficult to believe that 'impulsive' or

'erratic' decisions have anything to do with the fact that the

articulated interests have reached the decision-makers in an

'unaggregated' manner. Rather, more often, they are the

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 97

result of a crisis situation which makes unexpected demands on

the decision-makers who also happen to be temperamentally

incapable of reacting coolly to a crisis situation.

The authors recognize, that, in certain circumstances, 'im-

mobilism' may be the only sound policy for the decision-

making @lite as the status quo represents the best compromise

between warring interests in the situation. They write, 'the

possibility must be kept in mind, however, that in systems

with high levels of conflict and disagreement over policy direc-

tion, the maintenance of the status quo may be as satisfying to as

many groups and individuals as any single possible pattern of

change.12" But it is not made clear how the creation of dif-

ferentiated, interest-aggregating institutions would be of any

special help in achieving this. The so-called 'immobilism' in the

sense of maintaining the status quo derives not from the presence

or absence of these institutions, but from the internal social,

economic and cultural structure of the society in which the

decision-maker is situated and of which he is also an integral

part. The decision-maker, of course, need not be a single person,

and, in fact, seldom is. But that would scarcely affect the situa-

tion except in making it more complicated, as the plurality of

decision-makers may represent a diversity of interests amongst

themselves.

However, this diversity and plurality of interests does not

disappear even after their supposed aggregation by the dif-

ferentiated structures evolved by the so-called 'politically more

developed' societies. For, according to the authors themselves,

interest aggregation is only concerned with 'converting demands

into generalpolicy alternatives'.211 But assuming that the alternatives

are real alternatives in the sense that the adoption of one leads

to consequences which are diametrically opposed to those which

would follow from the adoption of the other, it is diffieu t to

discover what advantage the decision-maker gets by the crea-

tion of differentiated structures for aggregating interests. The

aggregated policy alternatives would be so contradictory in

nature that the dilemma of the decision-maker faced with the

perennial task of reconciling the irreconcilables would, if any-

thing, be more aggravated. He would certainly gain a clearer

consciousness of the choices involved and the relative costs that

each choice entailed in the circumstances concerned. But this

98 Political Development

task is in no way dependent on the existence of differentiated

aggregating structures. Rather, it is a function of the knowledge

of causal interrelationships that obtain in the relevant fields

and, in fact, are generally available to the decision-maker

whether such differentiated institutions for interest aggregation

exist or not. On the other hand, the sharpness in the formulation

of policy alternatives which happen to be mutually exclusive

and dichotomous in character, would only render the task of

the decision-maker more difficult, as he does not have to adopt

one of the contradictory alternatives formulated by the dif-

ferentiated structures devoted to the task of interest aggregation,

but, rather, to evolve a new alternative which maximizes the

interest-satisfaction of all concerned.

The above view of the decision-maker's function assumes

that he himself does not represent any specific interest or

interests in the society concerned. For, if he were to do so, he

would have to adopt the policy alternative which maximally

aggregates the interests he represents, and ignore completely

the interests which are conflicting or antagonistic to his own.

Many theories of political life tend to argue that such is actually

the case, and that the whole discussion of the decision-maker

serving some overarching public interest which somehow

transcends and reconciles conflicting private and group interests

is just a fagade which deceives nobody. The Marxist theory of

state is honest enough to propound this view of political life

explicitly, but somehow forgets to apply the truth to its own

case, thus indirectly justifying the necessiy of the fagade in all

cases. Yet, the very fact that such a necessity is felt by all

holders of public office is indicative of the fact that the essence

of the notion of functioning in a public capacity is always

conceived of in such a manner, and only that exercise of the

function is considered legitimate which is exercised with such an

end in view. But if it is impossible to exercise the function in

such a-way then the purpose of the polity is defeated at its

foundations, and both liberal and radical solutions are doomed

to failure from the very start.

The in-built hopelessness of the situation is masked by the

fact that theoreticians tend to postulate a freedom for them-

selves which they consider impossible for others and which

their theory rules out in principle, or a society in which there

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 99

are no incompatible interests at all and to which perhaps the

notion of 'incompatible interests' does not apply in principle.

Usually the two tend to go together. The theoretician blithely

assumes that not only is he free from all the determinations

which others are subject to, but that out of a society where it

is impossible for any decision-maker to transcend his particular

class interests and to think and act in terms of the interest of the

whole, would emerge another where there being no classes,

the decision-makers would think and act only in terms of the

interest of the whole. There is, of course, the further point

whether in a class society there could he any such thing as 'the

interest of the whole'. But then the paradox would become

deeper, as what we are asked to believe is the possibility of the

emergence of a society where there would not only be no

incompatible interests to reconcile, but also no possibility for

any such incompatibility to ever arise in future from a society

where this was impossible in principle.

For once, the possibility of competing interests is admitted in

a polity, the decision-maker would either have to be given the

task and the capability of reconciling these interests or the

polity would have to continue to subdivide till it reaches

autonomous units with homogeneous interests or accept a per-

petual alternation between diverse interests or groups which

dominate- each other either by force or fraud or both.

Marxists, for example, make an exception in their own case

and think they can transcend the, determination, which nor-

mally should be their fate, of working to realize the interests

of the class into which they happen to have been born by a bio-

logical accident. Equally, they tend to postulate the existence

of a society in which the-re will be no conflict of interests at all,

or, if there is conflict, that there will be no doubt as to which

are the legitimate interests that ought to prevail. The former is

the well-known notion of the classless society towards which

all history moves and which alonejustifies all history, as without

it, it would be a tale of senseless injustice and irredeemable

horror. The latter is the well-known dictatorship of the pro-

letariat which is a necessary instrument for the, realization of

the former. There is also perhaps the assumption that the

proletariat constitutes the majority of the people, and that in

some metaphysical sense its interests represent the interests of

100 Political Development

the whole. The majority, of course, may range from 51 to 99

per cent and to the extent it approximates to the latter, the

metaphysical sense also tends to coincide with the empirical.

But as in most countries where Marxist revolutions have taken

place, the peasantry formed a major part of the population and

as, according to most Marxist thinkers, the peasantry is not

only no part of the proletariat but has interests that conflict

with those of the latter, the interests which the dictatorship

pursues in the name of history on behalf of the proletariat tend

to be more and more metaphysical in character and the

divergence between the empirical and the metaphysical tends

to widen. On the other hand, the advanced industrial countries

where at one time the proletariat really constituted the majority

and in which Marx thought the socialist revolution would take

place, have shown a disquieting decline in the proportion of

the proletariat in their post-industrial phases. It is not only the

white-collar worker who begins to outnumber those engaged in

the industrial field, but also those who work in what has come

to be. called 'the knowledge industry' who begin to outnumber

both .29 The decline in the proportion of persons engaged in

agriculture, which was such a marked characteristic of western

countries in their first phase of industrialization, is followed by

a second and a third phase when the proportion of people

engaged in industrial production first declines relatively to

those engaged in the service industries and then to those

engaged in the knowledge industries. The dictatorship of the

proletariat in these countries, therefore, would represent the

actual interests of a minority which only by some metaphysical

sleight of hand could be made out to represent not only the

interests of the whole but of the future also.

The importance of the notion of the decision-maker as a

person who tries to reconcile conflicting interests is that if his

function is conceived of in this way the 'interest aggregation'

performed by the so-called intermediate structures of Almond

and Powell, instead of helping him, would make his task even

more difficult. For, according to them, the task of the interest

aggregating structures is not to reconcile divergent interests

but to aggregate 'the articulated interests into major policy

alternatives' .30 Now, though the authors have not clearly spelled

out what they mean by 'policy alternatives', it may reasonably

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 101

be assumed that the alternatives so formulated are exclusive in

the sense that if one of the policy alternatives for implementa-

tion is accepted one necessarily excludes the satisfaction of all

those interests which are presumably aggregated in the other

policy alternative. Not only this, the alternatives so formulated

are presumably exhaustive in character. If so, the decision-

maker is left in an impossible position where he can hardly

exercise his function, for he can only choose out of the policy

alternatives which aggregate opposing interests into sharp,

clear-cut dichotomies and, in doing so, become the instrument

for the realization of one set of interests against others. The

close relation of the interest-aggregation function to the struc-

ture of political parties in Almond's presentation strengthens

this interpretation even more, as the so-called 'policy alterna-

tives' can only be formulated by different parties which

presumably represent opposed and conflicting interests.

It is true that bureaucratic structures are also supposed to

perform the function of interest aggregation and, presumably,

they would be concerned with what we have called the recon-

ciliation of diverse interests rather than their formulation in

sharply opposed and exclusive alternatives, which political

parties are supposed to do. But then it is difficult to see why

bureaucracy should formulate alternative policy proposals

except in the sense that there may be alternative ways of

reconciling the interests. Yet, even if it be conceded that it is

tenable to speak of alternatives in such a context, it is clear that

the bureaucracy itself would have to work out the cost-benefit

ratios of the different strategies of reconciliation, and re-

commend the strategy which does so in the best possible

manner.

It is, of course, true that the bureaucracy, like political

parties, might have its own particular interests to foster' But,

in that case, it would not be performing the function specific to

itself. On the other hand, the very raison d'@tre of political parties

is supposed to be the articulation, propagation and fulfilment

of someparticular interests against others. In fact, the unawareness

of the radical distinction between the sort of interest aggrega-

tion that is demanded from bureaucracy and that.which is

supposed to be performed by political parties is perhaps the

central weakness of the authors' discussion regarding this issue.

102 Political Development

But the moment such a distinction is made, one is bound to ask

what is gained by the sort of interest aggregation which political

parties are required to perform in the Almond-Powell model?

The authors are aware of the dangers which a divided, frag-

mented polity faces if its members articulate their diverse

interests in irreconcilable terms. But they forget that the

function they ascribe, or rather prescribe, for political parties

does just that.

Their plea, of course, is that the bureaucracy cannot exercise.

its function effectively unless there are other agencies which

perform the same function in an autonomous, independent

fashion. They contend that 'in order for the bureaucracy to

aggregate effectively, a system with a strong and effective

decision-making center outside of the bureaucracy itself is

generally necessary. Without such a center the bureaucracy

may not he able to maintain its autonomy and coherence.131

But, first, this refers only to the independence and autonomy

of the decision-making centres from those that perform

the interest-aggregating function. And, secondly, it says noth-

ing about the necessity of a plurality of interest-aggregat-

ing institutions functioning independently of each other.

Even if such a necessity be admitted for the reason that sep-

arate agencies working independently of each other might

arrive at solutions which a single agency working on its own

may not possibly envisage, it by no means follows that such a

function tan only be discharged most effectively by political

parties, as the authors seem to think. Nor does it follow that it

will be facilitated if some institutions aggregate interests not

in the sense of reconciliation of conflicting interests but in the

sense of formulation of policies devoted to the achievement of

one set of interests against others. For, this is usually what

political parties do and also what they are s 1upposed to do in

the model set for them by Almond and Powell. It may be noted

in passing that a political party does not and cannot sugge 1st

policy alternatives, as the authors seem to think. Rather, each

political party can only suggest one policy alternative which is

such as to maximize, if followed, the interests it represents. The

other alternatives can only be formulated by other political

parties or by the bureaucracy or other institutions concerned

with the task. The alternatives so formulated are supposed to

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 103

he considered by the decision-making authority, which may

choose any one out of them or formulate a new one on its own.

The relation of the decision-making authority to the various

agencies which formulate the policy proposals for its considera-

tion is, however, not the same. The policy alternative proposed

by the political party which happens also to be the ruling

party is in a totally different position than all the other alterna-

tives proposed by other institutions. It occupies a pre-eminent

position in the sense tha 't the ruling wing of a political party is

supposed to implement the policies formulated by the party,

and if it deviates from thein, it does so only marginally.

Thus, if a political party is conceived of as the representative

of only a certain group of interests, it is almost inevitable that

its ruling wing does nothing else but cater to those interests. On

the other hand, if a political party is conceived of as a specific

viewpoint for the reconciliation of conflicting interests or as a

particular manner of reconciling these interests, it becomes the

bounden duty of the ruling wing to take note of all the alterna-

tive proposals for reconciliation and try to adopt the one which '

in its judgement, has the possibilities of achieving it to the

maximum extent.

It is a well-known fact that whenever a political party comes

to power, its ruling wing feels constraints and obligations which

it had not even suspected earlier, and of which the non-ruling

wing generally remains unaware. This has often created ten-

sions between the two wings, specially in cases where the party

comes to power for the first time and, even more so, when the

party conceives of itself in ideological terms. Perhaps we could

distinguish between parties that conceive of themselves as the

representative of some particular interests only, and those that

do not conceive of themselves in such a manner. The particular

interests may he those of a class or caste or race Or region or

religion or linguistic group. But in all such and similar cases,

the political parties ought to be regarded as performing only

the function of interest articulation and not of interest aggrega-

tion, except in the trivial sense in which the articulation of any

interest already involves some sort of aggregation or other. It

is only when a political party conceives of itself;is representing

not this or that interest but rather the interest of the whole that

it may he said to be perforn-iing the function of interest aggrega-

104 Political Development

tion primarily. However, it is difficult for any political party to

perform this function with great effectiveness unless it comes

to power, and even then it is only its ruling wing which ap-

prehends the problems and difficulties of reconciliation in their

totality.

Political parties, thus, do not seem to be such efficient

instruments of interest aggregation as Almond and Powell seem

to think. Nor is it clear, as they seem to imply, that a political

party's interest-aggregating function frees the decision-maker

in carrying out his task more effectively. Rather, it should be

seen as a constraint on the decision-maker, as a continuous

pressure on him to subordinate interest aggregation in terms of

the polity and society as a whole, for which he feels responsible,

to the interests of the political party which he represents and

which seldom, if ever, coincide with the interests of the totality.

The authors are, of course, aware of the problem of fragmenta-

tion in aggregation patterns, but they do not quite see that the

way they conceive the role of political parties in the function of

interest aggregation, cannot but lead to the augmentation of

such a situation. And, though it may he accepted that 'the

emergence of fragmented policy alternatives in the aggregation

process is "caused" by basic cultural and economic features of

the society, it,,tan be alleviated or exacerbated by the way in

which mediating interest aggregation is performed"32 it is

difficult to believe that political parties are the institutions par

excellence for achieving such alleviation, or that they invariably

or predominantly do so.

In fact, there is an inverse relation between interest articula-

tion and interest aggregation in the sense that the task of

aggregation becomes increasingly difficult as the number of

articulated interests increases. But as increase in interest arti-

culation is itself seen as a sign of political development, it is

obvious that if aggregative processes do not keep pace with it,

the polity would become increasingly fragmented, which would

be a sign not of political development but of political decay.

And, as articulation is always easier to achieve than aggrega-

tion, it is bound to run ahead of the latter and make its task

increasingly difficult, if not impossible. Such an inverse relation-

ship between the criteria offered by the authors for political

.development is not confined merely to interest articulation and

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 105

interest aggregation. Rather, as we shall see in section (8), it

is a feature of other criteria also.

Besides the so-called structures of interest aggregation,

Almond and Powell regard the style of interest aggregation as

equally important for indicating whether a polity may be

regarded as politically developed or not. By style, the authors

refer to 'the way in which the structure performs the function.

the general operating rules it manifests'.33 They distinguish

between 'three ditterent styles of interest aggregation, cor-

responding roughly to increasingly secularized political sub-

cultures of the interest aggregation structures'.34 These styles

are characterized as 'pragmatic bargaining, absolute-value

oriented, and traditionalistie'.35 The third. that is the tradi-

tionalistic style, is presumably supposed to characterize all past

societies, while the first two are supposed to differentiate the

totalitarian regimes of the fascist and communist varieties from

the democratic. At the heart of the pragmatic-bargaining style is

supposed to be 'the accommodation of diverse interests', and

Compromise and the atmosphere of the market place are

supposed to dominate the process of interest aggregation'.36 On

the other hand,.in the absolute-value oriented style of interest

aggregation, 'a rigid framework is imposed upon the expression

and aggregation of all group interests'.37 Also, 'such a style

often results in the systematic exclusion of the demands and

interests of major groups in the population'.311 Thus it is not only

that the articulation of interests is rigidly controlled in the

absolute-value oriented style of interest aggregation, but that,

though the interests pursued are supposed to represent the real

or true interests of all, in fact they are only the interests con-

ceived of by a minority in the name of the totality, even when

most of the actual groups constituting the population reject

the formulation.

The. distinction between the 'apparent' and the 'real' interests

is, thus, at the heart of the absolute-value oriented style of interest

aggregation, it being assumed that the so-called 'real' interests

are unknown to all except the privileged few, or rather the

privileged one, who alone may know what they are. But, then,

there seems little point in calling it interest aggregation, as it

is not diverse interests which are aggregated in this style;

instead, the very notion of diversity of interests is denied and

106 Political Development

relegated to the realm of the 'apparent' rather than the 'real'.

It belongs, in Plato's terminology, to the realm of opinion rather

than knowledge. But in this sense it would be wrong to say that

the so-called traditional societies of the past have not been

characterized by this style of interest aggregation. Most theo-

cratic states, particularly those belonging to the judaic tradi-

tion, have always thought of themselves as defenders of the

Faith and in possession of Truth, as against the false knowledge

of the heretics and infidels. In this respect, there is little to

choosf-vetween these states of the past and the fascist and com-

munist states of today.

The objection may be raised that the ideological posture of a

society only affects the rhetoric used and, perhaps to a lesser

extent, the style adopted for purposes of interest aggregation

rather than the fact that there remain diverse and conflicting

interests demanding such aggregation. That such interests are

deemed as 'apparent' rather than 'real' does not affect the fact

that they have either to be extirpated completely or placated to

some extent. As it is usually not possible to achieve the former

totally, the latter has to he attempted even when not approved

or liked. Not all the heretics can be killed, or all the profit- or

power-seekers eliminated. And if this cannot be done, then

these persistent and conflicting interests will have to be defused

in some manner or other. The actual practice of openly ideo-

logical r6gimes, whether of the religious or the secular variety,

seems to confirm this. Most religious @@gimes have to come to

terms with the existence of heretic minorities or even of heretic

majorities within their own midst. A classic case of the latter

was Islamic rule in India where a religious ruling minority had

to come to terms with a ruled majority belonging to a different

religion. The Mughal Empire sought to solve the problem by

inducting first the Rajput nobility and later the antagonistic

Marathas into their administrative system. Later, the British

Empire adopted the same policy, though in a more openly

secular framework than that of the Mughals. The secular

dictatorships of Hitler and Mussolini, specially in their imperial

phase, did not last long enough for this truth to he perceived.

But the Soviet variant of the pattern has shown, specially in its

relations with East European countries, an evolution which

may he regarded as analogous.

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 107

Yet, even if it is conceded that the task of interest aggregation

remains to a great extent the same under ideologies of different

persuasions, it may be accepted that they can make a significant

difference at some stages in the development of a polity. This

will be specially true of the early stages when ideological

passions are high, the search for ideological purity absolute

and the urge for implementation of the ideal imperative. But

even at other times, the Mullahs and the Pandits, or, to use more

sophisticated terminology, the ideologues of the party, have to

be placated, for they and their rhetoric provide legitimacy to

the 6lite in power. In fact, it may be hazarded as a hypothesis

that, in the later stages of a polity' the strength of the ideo-

logues would be a function of the weakness of the ruling i61ite

and the difficulties it may be facing at home or abroad.

Thus, as the absolute-value oriented style of interest aggrega-

tion is found in large parts of human history, the attempt to

distinguish it from the traditionalistic style does not seem very

happy. Further, Almond and Powell's definition of the tradi-

tionalistic style is such that it will be found in most politics,

except at the moments of'their revolutionary beginnings.

'Traditionalistic styles of aggregation', write the authors, 'rely

upon the patterns of the past in suggesting policy alternatives

for the future.'39 But this is not an unusual phenomenon at all,

and the policies of all the politics most of the time may be

characterized in some such terms. It is surprising to find authors

who have written so much about'political socialization' treating

as 'traditionalistic' a reliance on patterns of the past even for

suggesting policy alternatives for the future.

It may be true, as Toynbee has pointed out, that this is the

bane of all politics and the fundamental cause of their decline

and decay. The idolization of an ephemeral self or technique or

institution may be the cause, as Toynbee contends, of the fact

that societies, nations and individuals tend to fall in love with

that which once was successful in meeting a challenge or over-

coming a difficulty in the past. But this is only another name for

the learning process through which we assimilate the present

into the past; if sometimes the assimilation is unwarranted be-

cause the present happens to be sharply dissimilar from the past,

the action based on the assimilation might prove disastrous for

the actor concerned. But this is a risk inherent in the situation,

108 Political Development

and unless the actor is sensitive to both the similarities and the

differences in the situation, he is unlikely to respond cre-

atively to the changing situation. This is as true of the field of

knowledge, as that of action. Significant breakthroughs in the

former are as much the result of getting away from the accepted

paradigms of explanation as the revolutionary breakaway from

the traditional patterns of response in the case of the latter. But

neither knowledge nor action will be possible, if new paradigms

are set up each day and new revolutions proclaimed each hour.

Continuity is at the heart of civilization and consists in nothing

else except the reliance on patterns of the past for acting in the

present so that some determinate, desirable future may be

realized.

As for the pragmatic-bargaining style, it not only assumes an

actual diversity of interests, but also of their social legitimacy.

To the extent that actual diversity of interests may be said to

characterize all societies, such a style of interest aggregation

may also be expected to be found there on almost a priori

grounds. However, as pointed out in our discussion of the

absolute-value oriented style of interest aggregation, unless this

actual diversity is provided an ideological legitimacy in the

political system, there will be a continuous tension and strain

between what the ideology demands and what the actual

exigencies dictate in the situation. The Hindu world-view

legitimizes such a plurality and diversity at the empirico-

religious level, while the liberal-democratic view seeks to do the

same at the sociopolitical level. In a certain sense, the legitim-

ization of interest articulation already entails the legitin-tization

of the plurality and diversity of interests. And once the plural-

ity and diversity of interests is accepted as legitimate, the

pragmatic-bargaining style of aggregating these interests will

also be accepted and adopted openly. But accepting the

legitimacy of plural and diverse interests may also lead to the

increasing fragmentation of a polity, making the task of integra-

tion more and more difficult.

Fragmentation, in fact, is the third parameter in terms of

which the discussion about interest aggregation has been

carried on by Almond and Powell. But the context in which

they consider the problem of fragmentation relates primarily

to patterns of interest aggregation. The focus of attention is on

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 109

whether the structures performing the interest-aggregation

function do it in such a way as to reduce the fragmentation or

sharpen it even further. That a certain amount of fragmenta-

tion exists in the polity is assumed; the only relevant question

in this context is supposed to be whether the specialized and

differentiated structures designed to aggregate these interests

do so to lessen the antagonisms and the differences amongst the

various -interests, or to increase them to breaking point. But if

the task of the differentiated structures is to aggregate the

various interests, it is difficult to see why they should do it in

such a manner as to aggravate the divisions and cleavages

amongst the various interest groups. Perhaps the clue to this

seeming anomaly lies in the fact that the interest-aggregating

structures are supposed to convert demands into poli@y alterna-

tives which, because they are conceived of as mutually exclusive

in character, sharpen and intensify the implicit differences and

oppositions between the interests of the various groups. Further,

hs these policy alternatives are supposed to be formulated

primarily by political parties opposed to each other, the likeli-

hood of their formulating the policies in such a manner as to

be sharply opposed to each other is perhaps greater than it

would otherwise have been. On the other hand, it should also

not be forgotten that the parties have to seek the widest electoral

support to come into power and thus have to formulate their

policies in such a way as to aggregate the interests of the largest

number of groups as far as possible. This perhaps is the reason

why in most countries where democratic parties function, they

tend, to approximate to each other at least in their verbal

pronouncements over a period of time. On the whole, the

aggregating function is perhaps better performed by the

bureaucracy than political parties, even though this is contrary

to what the authors think.

1 It may, therefore, be safely said that it would only be in

extraordinary circumstances that aggregating structures would

help increase the fragmentation of a polity. On the other hand,

the emphasis on interest articulation can certainly lead to a

fragmentation of the polity, as each interest so articulated

would clamour for its satisfaction at the expense of others. Not

only this, the very fact of thinking in terms of interests tends to

fragment a polity. It may, of course, be contended that all

L.-B. S. National Acadeiny

of Administration, Mussoorie A@C

Ace. NO ..............

Dath ................ . ............ ~........

1 10 Political Development

politics are in fact fragmented and that the articulation merely

brings this fact out into the open. But there can be little doubt

that the fact of articulation itself makes the interests far

sharper and more defined than they would otherwise have been.

Also, the fact of articulation makes one far more identified with

the interest than one would otherwise have been. All dictator-

ships know this so well that they do not allow free articulation

of interests, except sometimes as a ruse to tempt the differences

to come into the open so that their proponents may be elim-

inated from the body politic. The classic case of such a

strategy was Mao's call in China 'to let a hundred flowers

bloom, to let a thousand thoughts contend', resulting in the

rolling of heads of all those, who were innocent enough to

believe him. Thus, if fragmentation has to be avoided on the

ground that it is a negative indicator of political development,

one would have to throttle not only all unlicensed articulation

of interests but also all thinking in terms of 'interests'. And

this is what all totalitarian systems attempt to do. Yet, it is

difficult to believe that they would be regarded as paradigmatic

examples of political development by anybody, including

Almond and Powell themselves.

The authors are, of course, aware of the difficulties created

by interest articulation for modernization and political devel-

opment. As Almond and Powell point out, 'clearly the tendency

of social and economic modernization to expand communica-

tion levels, to increase inclinations toward participation, to

widen the gap between rich and poor (at least in the short run

in many cases), and generally to increase the number of autonomous

demands arising from the socie@y, places growing stress upon the

aggregation structures.'40 The, stresses are relieved by many

modernizing systems through the creation of 'a controlled form

of participation and a hierarchical and unified aggregation'.41

But how can this authoritarian solution be characterized as

'development' when it seeks to negate the very features sup-

posed to constitute the core of political development? There is

little consolation in being told that 'even in cases of "authori-

tarian" solutions, the divisions and conflict often reappear in

new form within the ruling party or the elite itself'.42 Factions

or divisions in such a situation do not represent the interests of

those outside the system who constitute the majority, but only

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 111

of the various sectors of bureaucracy and the military which

alone have, access to the decision-makers in case they happen to

be different from them.

Interest aggregation, then, as a criterion of political develop-

ment seems to be full of so many holes as to be hardly capable

of holding any water, at least in the form in which the authors

have presented it in their work. According to them, the

existence of differentiated structures dedicated to the task of

interest aggregation is a sign of political development, provided

the whole task is performed in a pragmatic-bargaining style

and with a view to alleviating and bridging the differences

that obtain between diverse and conflicting interests of various

groups and classes constituting the polity. The aggregation

structures, it should be remembered, must not only he dif-

ferentiated from the major interest. articulation structures, but

also from the central decision-makingx, structures. The love of

differentiation and the market-place is writ large on such a

contention, but it is difficult to see how the so-called pragmatic-

bargaining style of interest aggregation becomes relevant to an

institution which is specifically differentiated to perform only this

task. In case it is really differentiated, it cannot enter into a

dialogue- or a process of give-and-take with other interest

groups' for it has no interests of its own and thus can only try to

reconcile the diverse and conflicting interests of others to the

best of its ability. Also, as it has been made mandatory for such

an institution to propose policy alternatives for the consideration

of decision-makers, it can devise different valuational criteria

in terms of which the alternative reconciliations could possibly

be attempted. The public debate could perhaps then be

focussed on the justiflability of the criteria themselves in terms

of which the reconciliation ought to be attempted.

Almond and Powell have not only felt no necessity to for-

mulate any such criteria, but they appear to be 'Completely

unaware of the problem itself. Further, they do not seem to have

noted the contradiction in saying that 'some degree of aggrega-

tion is almost inevitably carried out at all levels from individual

interest articulation to the final decision-making'43 and the

demand that 'aggregation structures must be differentiated

from the central decision-making structures' and that 'they

must also be differentiated from the major interest articulation

112 Political Development

structures'.44 Also, that if this demand for differentiation is

made essential for considering a polity developed, then at least

the presence of political parties cannot be regarded as such,

for they not only are, 'major structures for performing the

function of interest aggregation', but also play an important

role 'as institutional interest articulators'.4.1 Further, while

pragmatic-bargaining style may possibly prevail within a politi-

cal party, it can do so only because it also performs the role of

interest articulation. Otherwise, there would be little meaning

in talking about pragmatic-bargaining between different in-

terest groups, as in a developed polity they are supposed to

articulate only their own interests and not enter into any

bargaining with each other in order to place their aggregated

demand before decision-makers. It may be suggested that this

is just the task which the differentiated interest aggregation

structures should undertake. In other words, they should help

the various interest groups to come together and enter into a

meaningful dialogue so that they could bridge their differences

and reach an agreed solution. But then there would be no

poli@y alternatives for them to present to the decision-makers, only

the agreed decision which would be presented by the parties

themselves without the intermediacy of the differentiated

aggregation structures. In fact, within this perspective, these

structures would become increasingly redundant as the interest

groups would begin to enter into direct negotiations with each

other and thus begin performing the function of interest ag-

gregation themselves.

The specific criteria of interest aggregation offered by the

authors are thus of little help in understanding the notion of

political development. Besides the difliculties we have already

pointed out, there is the added difficulty that they do not seem

capable of quantitative measurement. For purposes of com-

parison, therefore, they can hardly be of much use. But if they

cannot do this job, they are irrelevant to any discussion of

political development, as the comparison between different

politics and of the same polity at different times is the very

purpose for which the concept was formulated. It may he added

that the concept of interest aggregation gains credence as a

Prima facie criterion of political development because of its

generalized sense of reconciliation of diverse and conflicting

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 113

interests, which is one, of the primary tasks of any polity. But it

is not clear whether the specific technical sense in which

Almond and Powell use the term achieves this end necessarily,

or even in a pre-eminent manner. In fact, they themselves

fluctuate between the technical and the general use of the, term.

In the technical sense, for example, such a statement as 'some

degree of aggregation is almost inevitably carried out at all

levels from individual interest articulation to the final decision-

making',41 is meaningless, for neither the individual nor the

final decision-maker 'convert demands into general policy

alternatives'47 in terms of which the function of interest ag-

gregation is defined at the very beginning of the discussion.

(3) The Criterion as Rule-Making

The policy alternatives proposed by the differentiated struc-

tures of interest aggregation have ultimately to be placed before

the decision-maker or decision-makers, who have to make the

final decision. The choice may be made between the alternatives

proposed or some further alternative that may be formulated

and opted for by the decision-makers. But whatever the choice,

it has ultimately to issue in an authoritative pronouncement

embodying the final decision in a rule which gives the verdict

on the diverse and conflicting interests clamouring for satisfac-

tion. It may thus be regarded as the crucial place in which the

criterion of political development may be found. And, in fact,

it does occupy such a place in the so-called conversion-functions

of Almond's list. After the interests have been articulated and

aggregated, the laws have to be formulated which try to satisfy

the interests to the extent it is feasible and desirable to do so.

The rule-making function, then. may be regarded as the politi-

cal function par excellence and those who are after the holy grail

of political development presumably hope to find it there.

But assuming that we can find it there, it would be relevant

to ask where exactly we shall seek to find it. Shall it be in the

number of rules made or in their contents or in their relation-

ship to the interests that have been articulated and aggregated?

One looks in vain in Almond and Powell for an answer to

this question. Rather, their interest centres only on whether

or not differentiated rule-making structures have emerged in

114 Political Development

the political system, and whether or not 'the legitimacy of a

process whereby new rules are made by secular political

institutions'48 is acknowledged. Besides these, perhaps, the

authors' only other,focus is on whether there has been a 'shift

from the traditional to constitutional restraints on political

actions'.49 Their emphasis is thus primarily on distinguishing

between traditional and modern political systems, assuming as

a matter of course that what is modern is bound to he 'more

developed' also. But, as we have already pointed out a number

of times, a differentiated structure does not ensure anything by

virtue of its 'differentiation', except perhaps the clear-cut loca-

tion of responsibility for the functions performed or not per-

formed.

As for 'the legitimacy of a process whereby new rules are

made by secular political institutions', the contrast between

the sacred immobilism of traditional societies and the secular

dynamism of modern ones is perhaps too overdrawn. The myth

of keeping the revealed rules intact by a process of continuous

reinterpretation in the light of changing needs imposed by a

changing environment, is paralleled by the continuous amend-

ments to the constitutions of modern states, resulting in changes

affecting the very fundamentals of the constitutions under the

camouflage of keeping their sacred constitutionality intact.

Constitutions, in fact, perform the same function as the revealed

rules of ancient times and are treated in the same way. They

are not as 'secular' as is usually made out by writers on political

theory. Perhaps, the very concept of a 'constitution' is un-

secular. How can something unchangingserve as a standard

for processes and situations which are essentially changing in

character? Even the distinction between those parts of a con-

stitution which cannot be changed and those which can, along

with the due processes of changing them, is not unknown to

traditional societies with their revealed rules that they are

supposed to follow. The, distinction between Sruti and Snkrti

in Hinduism and that between Sunna and Sharia in Islam are

only the most conspicuous examples of this.

The obsession with the contrast between tradition and mod-

ernity appears to have blinded many political scientists to the

fact that traditional societies were never as unchanging as is

usually made out, or that modern societies are not as changing

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 115

as many have unquestioningly assumed them to be. The so-

called substitution of traditional restraints on political action

by constitutional ones is doubly spurious for, as everyone- knows,

all law is given content by a process of continuous interpretation

on the part of the judiciary and is subject to subversion by

political pressures of the most diverse kinds which can only

be resisted, if at all, by the traditions of the polity that have

become so ingrained in all the various segments of the political

6lite that they are restrained from violating the constraints, not

from any outside authority, but from within. This is usually

called 'political culture' in recent writings on political science,

but, in fact, it is merely another name for tradition which is

anathema to the protagonists of political modernization. Basi-

cally, all constraints are rooted either in the internalized pro-

cesses of socialization, which is merely another name for

tradition, or in mere- brute and naked fear of violence, which is

a denial of all culture and civilization. When the former are

absent, constitutional restraints are of little avail as the history

of most constitutional governments in the Third World so

graphically shows. In such situations, anyone who can mobilize

the organs of violence may nullify the constitutional con-

straints with such case that one wonders if they were ever there

at all.

The differentiation of institutions devoted to the task of

law-making and the replacement of traditional restraints on

political action by constitutional ones could, then, hardly be

regarded as criteria of political development. In fact, Almond

and Powell themselves appear doubtful whether such dif-

ferentiated, clear-cut structures can be located. Their very

reason for preferring the use of the term 'rule-making' for

'legislation' relates to the fact that 'the term "legislation" seems

to connote some specialized structure and explicit process, whereas in

many political systems the rule-making function is a diffuse

process, difficult to untangle and specify.'50 Lest it be thought

that such a diffuseness is characteristic of only traditional politi-

cal systems, the authors warn that 'in most political systems,

but particularly in modern democratic ones, the performance of

rule-making, like that of articulation and aggregation, will be

dispersed and delegated.'." According to them, not only this

but the whole problem of identifying the rule-making structures

116 Political Development

in political systems is 'one of specifying the whole set of agencies

and institutions involved in the process, determining the kind of

things they do, the way they do them, and how they interact to

produce general ruies.',12 But if this is the situation not only

with respect to rule-making but also regarding interest articula-

tion and aggregation, what happens to the contention that

'political development has been defined as the increased dif-

ferentiation and specialization of political structures and the

increased secularization of political CUltUrel ?53 Perhaps, like

politicians, political scientists are not expected to be consistent '

or perhaps their left Viand forgets what their right hand has

written. In any case, the two statements read together would

make the realization of 'political development' almost im-

possible in principle. This would be true not only in

respect of 'the differentiation and specialization of political

structures', but also of the 'secularization of political culture'.

It is debatable whether the concept of culture can be under-

stood in purely secular terms, if culture is taken to mean not

only the style and pattern of behaviour in any particular

domain, but also the values one tries to realize and actualize

therein. The ideals ofjustice, equality and freedom even in the

sociopolitical realm can hardly be understood in purely posi-

tivistic and behaviouristic terms. But even if the possibility is

admitted at the purely theoretical level, it is difficult to see how

any actual empirical society could be characterized as such.

The whole mythology of constitutions, courts and legislatures,

with their sacred oaths and solemn rituals, rnilitates against

this secularization. The non-secular character of all this is

hidden from the political scientist because of the language he

uses to describe the phenomenon. The deeper reason, however,

lies in the parochial culture-centredness of the western psyche

which equates sacredness, with theocentricity and thus treats

all thought which does not accept the existence and authority

of God as secular in character.

The emergence of differentiated rule-making structures, the

legitimation of rule-making by secular structures and con-

stitutional restraints on political action, thus, are not of much

help as criteria of political development. Can the thinking in

terms of quantity or content be of more help in the matter? An

increase in the amount of rule-making can be taken as an index

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 117

of political development only if rule-making per se is regarded

as a criterion of political development. Some people, of course,

might treat it as such, particularly as traditional politics are

not supposed to make any rules and modern politics perhaps

do nothing else. But an increase in the quantity of rule-making

may be taken to indicate that the society is facing increasing

problems which it is trying to solve through legislation. Yet,

if this is the interpretation, a relative decline in rule-making

after such an increase would alone indicate that it has been

successful in solving the problems for which it was undertaken.

On the other hand, it may he urged that the increasing com-

plexity of societies demands increasing legislation for their

regulation and that the latter always lags behind the former. It

can even be urged that the rules themselves may give rise to

new and more complex problems whose solutions require the

enactment of fresh rules, and that this cycle may go on ad

infinitum. There is, thus, the possibility of a completely im-

manent necessity for a continuous increase in the rule-making

function without influence from any external factor.

Yet, whatever the reasons behind the quantitative inter-

pretation of rules as an indicator of political development, it

will hardly be disputed that it is the easiest to fulfil and that,

in fact, most so-called underdeveloped countries would rank

quite high on that count. On the other hand, if we choose to

take the content of the rules into account and base our criterion

of political development on that, we would open the whole

issue of criteria once again. For, unless we decide what ends the

rule-making function is to subserve or achieve, it would be

futile to look into the contents of those rules when judging the

political development of the polity concerned. The question of

ends, however, is seldom directly raised in most discussions of

political development. It is assumed that if there is the widest

possible participation in the political process and institutional

mechanisms for the articulation of as many interests as pos-

sible, it would somehow be ensured that the rules made by the

decision-making authorities would satisfy the largest interests

of the greatest number of citizens of the polity. The deeper as-

sumption, perhaps, is that there can be no a priori determination

of ends which the rules ought to fulfil. Rather, each person is

the best judge of his or her own interests, and the task of the

9

118 Political Development

political authorities is only to ensure their reconciliation and

satisfaction to the greatest extent possible. However, even in

such a situation the authorities cannot escape the responsibi-

lity of ascribing differential weightage to the diverse interests

that have been articulated and brought to their attention by

those who have tried to aggregate them. All interests cannot

be given equal weightage, letting only the number of persons

who share an interest count in the final calculation. Perhaps

the notion of the 'greatest good of the greatest number' does

just this. But even there one has to decide whether the interests

of the underprivileged, even if they be in a minority, should

or should not be given more weightage than others. The dis-

abilities resulting in deprivation could arise either from natural

or social factors, but in either case the dilemma of choice would

remain the same. The only difference would perhaps be in a

feeling of guilt arising from a sense of responsibility in the case

of the latter which will be absent in the former. Still, as man's

capacity to modify and improve upon the resources of nature

increases, the distinction tends to get increasingly blurred. On

the other hand, social constraints may be felt to be more

difficult to overcome as they are not only man's own creation

but are internalized within his being to such an extent that

he begins to define himself in those terms. To fight against

them is to fight against oneself, and that is not only a difficult

thing to undertake but almost impossible to succeed in.

It is, thus, the relation of rules to interest articulation and

aggregation that may be said to provide the criterion by which

we may judge whether the content of the rules that are for-

mulated by the decision-making authority or authorities con-

note political development or otherwise. The amount of

interests satisfied and the amount of differences reconciled in

proportion to those that have been articulated and aggregated

could be the measure of political development of a polity. It is

not, of course, very clear whether the proportion should be

calculated in terms of the interests articulated or in terms of the

interests aggregated by the differentiated structures which are

entrusted with the performance of that task. Almond and

Powell themselves have not made it clear whether, in their

view, the decision-making authorities are supposed to take into

consideration only those interests which are presented to them

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 119

by the aggregating structures, or whether they want them to be

free to take into account even those that might have been left

out completely by the aggregating institutions for one reason

or another. In the former case, the proportion would have to be

calculated on the basis of the aggregated interests alone, while

in the latter, the aggregated interests might even be completely

ignored and the proportion calculated only on the basis of the

articulated interests. As the authors fear that unless there are

intermediate aggregating structures, the decision-makers will

be overwhelmed by the sheer volume of demands and thus be

rendered helpless to construct effective and consistent policy, 5 4

it may he taken that they would opt for the alternative that only

the aggregated interests should engage the attention of the

decision-maker. But in that case one would also have to develop

a measure of the relationship between the interests articulated

and the interests aggregated, for it would be naive to assume

that the aggregating structures would have taken into account

the largest possible number of articulated interests and recon-

ciled them in the most efficient manner possible. For, if it were

really so, one wonders what would remain for the final decision-

making authority to do except perhaps to look after its own

vested interests which it might have considered impolitic to

articulate publicly. But if those occupying the decision-making

position can have a vested interest of their own, so can those

who are given the task of interest aggregation. Besides this,

they occupy a strategic situation where they may accentuate

or underplay any interest or group of interests in such a way as

to brin them to the attention of the decision-maker or to keep

1 9

them away from it. It would become imperative, therefore, for

the decision-making authorities to keep a critical watch on the

aggregating authorities and to judge their performance in rela-

tion to the interests that have been articulated. But if they have to

be aware of the articulated interests, there seems no reason why

they should not directly take them into account in their rule-

making function and let it therefore bejudged in relation to that.

Perhaps the only reasons why they may try to avoid doing

this may lie in their desire to have all the possible alterna-

tive ways of aggregating the articulated interests spelt out

for them along with their respective costs and benefits so that

they may be able to make some sort of rational choice between

120 Political Development

them. But in that case it is difficult to see how political parties

and the usual type of bureaucratic structures could perform

the task of aggregation, as the authors appear to think. Perhaps,

the government would have to establish independent, autono-

mous structures specifically entrusted with the task of aggregat-.

ing the articulated interests in as many diverse ways as possible.

But even then the problem of unarticulated interests would

remain, and there seems little reason to justify the ignoring of

an interest on the ground that it has not been articulated. The

capacity to articulate is itself a function of many factors which

may not be available to large masses of people in a society. In

most underdeveloped societies illiteracy and poverty combine

to render a vast majority of people inarticulate. It would be an

act of utter irresponsibility on the part of decision-makers in

these societies, therefore, to pay attention only to those interests

that have been articulated and to ignore the rest. If they are to

take into account the unarticulated interests, they would have

first to face the problem of how to locate them. An articulated

interest may at least be presumed to be the interest of those who

have articulated it, but the same can hardly be said of interests

that have not even been articulated They are ascribed to

people in the conviction that in case they were able to articulate

their interests, they would do so in that manner.

The problem of unarticulated interests which are ascribed

to people by the decision-making authority raises not only the

question of the correctness of such an ascription and the possible

weightage that it should be given in relation to the interests

that have been articulated, but also the whole issue of what may

be called the apparent vs. real interests. If decision-makers can

decide about these interests, this can only be because they have

some criteria for judging the matter. But if some criteria are

available for deciding about the real interests of the people,

there seems little reason for not applying them in those cases

where some group or groups have articulated their own

interests. The criteria claim a universality and objectivity

which makes it irrelevant whether people have articulated their

interests or not, and makes equally irrelevant the content of

what they have articulated, in case they have done so.

However. if this be adn-dtted, the whole attempt at articula-

tion and aggregation of interests would be an exercise in futility,

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 121

and it would be meaningless to judge of the contents of the rules

that have been made in the context of the interests that have

been articulated or aggregated. Rather, the rules would have

to be judged in the light of criteria on the basis of which the

needs of the people are determined. It would, then, be the

extent to which the ideal structure of needs, as determined by

the criteria, is embodied in the rules made by the decision-

makers that would determine how far a polity can be considered

politically developed or not. The extent of embodiment would

be an index of political development and the dispute, if any,

would relate only to the criteria on the basis of which the real

interests of the people are calculated and determined. Even here

it is possible to argue that any a priori determination of interests

is not necessary, as the type of interests that rule-making can

fulfil may belong only to groups and not to any particular

individual, and hence are capable of extrapolation to analogous

groups which have not been able to articulate their interests

for some reason or other. Along with this, a persistent attempt

could be undertaken to provide opportunities for articulation

to all those who have been deprived of them, and to elicit

their opinion on those which have been ascribed to them, not

on any a priori grounds, but on the ground of their presumed

similarity to groups which have articulated their interests.

The rules, it should be remembered, are not made once and

for all; nor, for that matter, are the interests so articulated.

There is a continuous interaction between the articulated and

aggregated interests, on the one hand, and the rules that are

made to satisfy them, on the other. The interests themselves

may change o-ver*a period of time or the rules made to satisfy a

particular set of interests at one time may result in the creation

of new problems which demand rectification by new rules. It

would he difficult, therefore, in such a situation to judge

whether the contents of a particular set of rules are designed to

satisfy a new set of interests, which have emerged because of a

change in the situation, or to meet problems created by the

promulgation of rules in the past, or because of an inadequacy

in the past rules revealed by the way they have been found to

work in practice.

The disentanglin - of these three factors is necessary for both

9

theoretical and practical purposes, as the concept of political

122 Political Develo

.pment

development is essentially comparative in character and thus

requires for its application the comparability of the present

situation with the past in relevant respects. In case, therefore,

the interests which are sought to be satisfied by rule-enactment

in the present have themselves arisen because of changed cir-

cumstances, the rule-content cannot be relevantly compared

with the rules in the past to determine whether any develop-

ment has occurred in the political field or not. All the rules, for

example. that have had to be enacted because of the introduc-

tion of the automobile and the aeroplane can hardly bear

comparison with the laws, or their absence, relating to vehicles

in the past. Similarly, if the laws enacted merely try to rectify

the problems created by the laws made in the past, they cannot

be treated as a sign of political development in the same way as

those that try to fulfil the same interests in a more comprehen-

sive and better manner. In fact, the problems created by the

enactment of a law should be placed on the debit side of the

evaluation of that law. However, as this can only be known after

the enacted law has functioned for some time, the evaluation of

all rules in terms of their content would have an in-built error

difficult to compute at the time of their promulgation or even

soon after.

The comparative assessment of political development in

terms of rule-making seems, thus, a most hazardous undertak-

ing unlikely to achieve definite results in any meaningful sense

of the term. If it is the number of rules enacted that are taken

as a measure of the political development of a country, it

would be the easiest thing for a polity to score on this count as

there is nothing easier than the enactment of rules by any

authority empowered to make them. On the other hand, if

content is to be taken into account, the criteria in terms of which

the judgement about the content has to be made have to be

spelt out andjustified. In case the criteria are treated as trans-

temporal in character, in terms of which each polity at any

time of its existence can be measured and compared with

every other, the essential time-bound-character of rules which

are formulated in specific situations to meet particular problems

would be lost sight of. On the other hand, if they are judged in

respect of the articulated and aggregated interests of a parti-

cular people, there will not only be all the difficulties we have

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 123

mentioned earlier, but also those relating to a comparative

assessment of political development between different politics

and between different stages of the same polity.

The difficulties in the latter case emanate from the fact that

the amount and diversity of articulated interests would hardly

be the same in any two cases, thus vitiating the comparison at

its very foundations. In fact, wherever the relationship com-

puted is a ratio between two quantities, the larger the de-

nominator, the larger the numerator has also to be. But, in

terms of ratios, the relationship may remain the same, even

though the two quantities may increase enormously, and thus

hardly show any development. Further, if political moderniza-

tion entails an increase in interest articulation, as is usually

thought by most thinkers, it would put an increasingly greater

strain on the rule-making function and, in_ most cases, it can

be said with fair confidence that it is likely to lag behind. But

if this is true, then a decline in political development would be

almost in-built into the criteria of political modernization, a

consequence that would scarcely be welcome to those who have

thought and written on the subject.

A deeper objection to taking rule-making as an index of

political development consists in the contention that the exact

content of the rules cannot be determined without reference to

the way the rules have been given a concrete interpretation by

the courts. As courts are the final adjudicators with respect

to what the,law means, it is meaningless to judge them without

reference to it. Cardozo"5 argued the point forcefully a long

time back. But as judicial interpretation never ends, we would,

on this view, he left with nothing but provisional interpretations

of the rules for purposes of comparative evaluation. However,

as a detailed discussion of rule-adjudication as a criterion of

political development is to be undertaken in section (5) , as

also the relationship between the different conversion-functions

in section (8), it would be best to discuss the point in those

contexts.

Another, and perhaps even more fundamental objection to

taking rule-making too seriously as a criterion of political devel-

opment, relates to the fact that rules by themselves do not indi-

cate anything except perhaps the intentions of the decision-

maker. It can be taken seriously only if they are not merely

124 Political Development

enacted and placed on the statute book, but also implemented

and enforced in actual practice,. This, however, leads directly

to the discussion of rule-application as a criterion of political

development, and hence we will discuss it in the next section.

(4) The Critedon as Rule-Application

There can be little doubt that unless the rules enacted by the

decision-making authorities are applied and actually obeyed

and observed, they remain mere ritual gestures on the part of

the ruling @lite, proclaiming at best their intentions to do some-

thing. But as 'to rule' means 'to be able to enforce one's will',

the non-implementation of a rule also pr?claims, to a certain ex-

tent, the ineffectiveness ofthe rulers to rule. The rules, of course,

may be enacted merely to proclaim the intention of the ruler

or even to deceive people into thinking that something is

intended to be done, but in most cases it may be presumed that

it is not so and that the authorities really mean to fulfil what

they have enacted.

Yet even if it be conceded that rule-application is at the heart

of the matter, it is still not quite clear how to find the extent to

which rules have been effective in fulfilling their purpose, for

this is the meaning of rule-application. But if this is the mean-

ing, then it is not merely the rules whose effective application

is to be judged, but rather the purpose which their enactment

was designed to achieve. As the rules have been made in the

context of interest articulation and interest aggregation, it is

obvious that the purposes they are intended to fulfil relate to

the satisfaction primarily of those articulated and aggregated

interests and, perhaps, secondarily, of those which have re-

mained unarticulated for some reason or other, but deserve

satisfaction in the judgement of the authorities who have to

take a decision in the matter. However, in such a situation it

is not the individual rule which would have to be judged in the

context of the interests that it is supposed to fulfil, but rather

the totality of rules in relation to the totality of interests. The

rules, then, should not be taken in an isolated, atomic manner,

but rather as constituting an interrelated whole which in its

totality tries to realize the interrelated totality of interests

which is judged to be both feasible and worth realizing. This,

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 125

it should be obvious, applies equally to rule-making and rule-

application. With rule adjudication, the presupposition is

brought into the open, as the courts in exercising their judicial

function have to treat the whole set of laws as constituting an

organic whole possessing a coherent structure. Each seeming

incoherence is smoothed out by a clever and subtle interpreta-

tion, for the presupposition always is that the existing body of

laws can never be incoherent.

We need not go further into details regarding rule-adjudica-

tion here as we propose to devote section (5) to its consideration

later in this chapter. But as far as rule-making and rule-applica-

tion are concerned, the issues raised by the proposal that it is

the totality of rules that should be taken into account and not

the individual rules alone, have to be discussed here. The first

and foremost of the issues raised by this perspective relates to

the time-span which should form the unit for consideration of

the totality of rules enacted within that period. The problem

arises because rules are continuously enacted by the decision-

making authorities, and any delimitation in such a situation is

bound to appear arbitrary, unless some criteria are given which

may reasonably be justified. The situation gets additionally

complicated by the fact that, as the totality is supposed to be

organic in character, any addition to it is bound to change its

character. This, however, would arise primarily in relation to

the rules as they are enacted by the decision-making authority.

As far as the issue of rule-application is concerned, it is further

complicated by the fact that a certain time-interval would have

to be posited between rule-enactment and rule-application so

that the latter's effectiveness could he judged. However, as all

the rules are not made simultaneously, the time-interval re-

quired for judging the efficacy of rule-application cannot but

vary for different rules that have been enacted at different

times.

The problem can perhaps be more clearly stated in the

following manner. As the rules are enacted at different times,

the time-interval after which they are to be judged in terms of

the efficacy of their application cannot be the same for all of

them, unless they are treated either atomistically or divided

into units determined by the time of their enactment. Both the

alternatives have difficulties of their own. The first not only

126 Political Development

gives up the notion of organic totality, but also flies in the face

of the fact that many laws tend to form clusters and that a law

is enacted, not in a vacuum, but in the context of other laws on

the same subject. The second alternative would make the laws

under the unit a complete jumble of disparate laws, but in that

case the choice of the unit in terms of the time when the laws

have been enacted would have only pragmatic justification in

its favour. The unit of time could perhaps be- a particular

session of the legislature and the time-interval for evaluation

could perhaps be the period during which fresh elections are

held to decide who shall be the decision-makers in a polity. But

this would confine the criterion only to those politics which

have an electoral system and hold periodic elections to decide

who shall constitute their ruling 6lite for a limited period.

Perhaps one could have different time-intervals for different

politics depending on the nature of their political systems. Not

merely this, one could also take into account the level of the

development of the communication system to decide on the

probable time-interval for judging the effectiveness of the

implementation of any enacted law or sets of laws. It is obvious

that it would be unfair to have the same time-interval for

societies at different levels of communication systems.

At a still more sophisticated level, one could distinguish

between the contents of enacted laws and place them in dif-

ferent categories so that the time-interval may be allowed to

vary with relevance to the probable time that one may regard

as necessary for the purposes embodied in the different contents

to be fulfilled. There obviously are ends which, due to their

very nature, take a longer time to fulfil than others. Anything

that tries to make a change in the sociocultural habits of a

people, for example, may be expected to take a long time to he

even moderately effective. The same may safely be hazarded

for any change that is supposed to affect the totality of the

population, or even a large majority of it. The difficulties in

the process of effective implementation in the first case are

derived from the nature of the changes that are sought to be

made, while in the case of the latter they derive, primarily from

the numbers that are supposed to be affected by the change.

There is also a third category which relates to what has come

to be called 'the vested interests' of the ruling 6lite of a country.

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 127

These 'vested interests' do not relate so much to the socio-

cultural behavioural patterns rooted in the historic past of a

people, as to the economic and power structure of a society

wlkere particular classes, individuals or groups of people enjoy

certain privileged positions which they try to defend at all

costs against attempts to oust them. Rules tending to adversely

affect their position are usually rendered ineffective by various

means at the disposal of these power groups themselves. The

nullification of these rules in the process of their implementa-

tion is derived, therefore, not from the deep-rooted psycho-

cultural habits of a people or because of the largeness of the

numbers involved, as in the- first two cases, but because of the

structural position of the rule-makers themselves.

It may appear strange that rule-makers should frustrate the,

implementation of those very rules which they themselves have

made. For, one might well ask, if they did not want the rules to

be implemented, why should they have enacted them in the

first place? Unless we- assume some masochistic perversity on

their part, there would seem little reason to believe that they

would indulge in such a fruitless exercise. But such a doubt,

however seemingly legitimate, rests on assumptions which

themselves are extremely dubitable. First, it is assumed 'that the

ruling class is unified in terms of its interests, and that, hence,

there can be no discrepancy of interests between those who

enact the laws and those who try to frustrate their effective

implementation. Secondly, it is assumed that the ruling elite

is static in its composition and structure. The third assumption

may be said to relate to the genuineness of the motives of the

rule-making authorities. It is naively believed that rules are

always made to be implemented.

All three assumptions are, in fact, highly questionable. The

ruling class is always divided within itself, and the rules are

frequently enacted to harm the interests of other sections of the

ruling class which, then, try to frustrate their actual implemen-

tation by all the overt and covert means at their disposal. On

the other hand, as new claimants are always arising to enter the

ruling class through factors over which there is little control,

there is always an attempt at accommodation and compromise

by taking the edge off their resentment and providing limited

entry at some level in the hierarchical structure of the ruling

128 Political Development

strata. Many laws can be understood in this light. However, as

the ruling @lite is always reluctant to part with power as far as

possible, it tries to deceive the clamouring claimants with the

illusion that something is being done while, in fact, it does not

really intend to do anything in the matter. Perhaps most of

the socioeconomic legislation which seeks to effect any serious

redistribution of power and resources tends to be a compromise

between these two approaches. The first attempt usually is to

create the illusion of giving with the understanding that if the

illusion does not succeed in deluding, some minimal concessions

may actually he given. Even this is usually sought to be done

at the expense of that section of the power 6lite which is opposed

to those who actually occupy the seats of power.

The problems created by a differentiated consideration of the

contents of rules for purposes of evaluating the effectiveness of

their application are, thus, enormous. It is, therefore, surprising

to find an almost complete absence of any discussion concerning

these issues in the writings of most thinkers who have addressed

themselves to the problem of political development. Even

Almond and Powell who have introduced the notion of

'conversion-functions' of which rule-application is a part, and

who have devoted a whole section to its discussion in Chapter

VI of Comparative Politics: A Developmental Approach, show hardly

any awareness of the issues involved. They seem to be primarily

concerned with the differentiation of rule-application structures

and a delineation of their major types, particularly in the

context of a bureaucracy as discussed by Weber and Fainsod in

their works. The focus of their attention, therefore, is not on

the content of rules made and how the diversity in content may

set problems for judging the effectiveness of rule-application

as required by the search for criteria of political development.

The reason for this lies in the assumption that the differentia-

tion of rule-application structures would enhance the perform-

atory capabilities of the political system. According to them

'the presence of differentiated and well'-developed structures

for rule application greatly expands the capability of a political

system to manipulate its environment'.,"

This, of course, is merely a particular application of the

generalized contention that the differentiation of structures

and functions leads inevitably to enhanced capability and

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 129

development, and has already been discussed in detail earlier.

The sinister tones of the phrase 'to manipulate its environment'

are perhaps unconscious, though shades of the biological theory

of evolution as popularly understood lie too clearly to be

entirely neglected. As the manipulative view of environment

is writ large on the predominantly technological understanding

of modern science, its acceptance by political science need not

occasion any surprise. But what should cause some concern is

the fact that political thought in countries which claim to be

devoted to the cause of political liberties is so fascinated by

considerations of efficiency and power. However, as we have

already discussed in detail the criterion in terms of 'capabi-

lities', we need not discuss the matter once again. Still, the

role that bureaucracy is supposed to play in the enhancement

of 'capabilities' and the modernization of political systems

needs some discussion. But before we do this, we shall pay some

attention to other parameters which are also regarded as

relevant to the consideration of rule-application as a criterion

of political development.

The differentiated structures created to discharge the func-

tion of rule-application may do so with varying effectiveness,

and in significantly different styles. As Almond and Powell

point out, 'Needless to say, not all the differentiated rule-

application structures which can be found in primitive and

modern political systems operate with the same style and level

Of effeCtiVeneSS'57; 'they may differ in complexity, in hierar-

chical structure, in degree of autonomy, and in impartiality of

rule enforcement'.rl" But though the authors have mentioned

these aspects in which the differentiated structures devoted to

the task of rule-application may differ, they have neither dis-

cussed them in detail nor indicated how they are to be evalu-

ated in the context of political development. Nothing, for

example, is said about the different styles in which the dif-

ferentiated rule-application structures may operate, and

which, if any, may be treated as indicators of political de-

velopment. Presumably the authors did not want to repeat

what they had already said about styles in the context of

their discussion about interest articulation and interest

aggregation. But even the enumeration of styles in these

two cases is not the same, and it is not clear which we are

130 Political Development

supposed to transpose to the case of rule-making structures. In

the case of interest articulation, the differences in style are

articulated in terms of the Parsonian pattern-variables, while

in the case of interest aggregation they are articulated primarily

in terms of the pragmatic-absolute dichotomy. Both have

already been discussed at length in the sections relating to

interest articulation and interest aggregation respectively. But

whatever the difficulties found in those contexts, the problem

in relation to rule-application is, which of the two is to be

considered relevant in this context? Should we say, for example,

following the interest articulation model, that the performance

of the rule-application function 'may be manifest or latent,

specific or diffuse, general or particular, instrumental or affec-

tive in style'?511 Or should we follow the interest aggrega-

tion model, and say that the three styles in which the rule-

application function may be performed are 'pragmatic bargain-

ing, absolute-value oriented, and traditionalistic'?60 But the two

classifications are so far apart that it is not clear which should

be chosen in the context of rule-application, and on what

grounds. The 'traditionalistic' style, of course, may be said

to be overlapping' as the pattern-variable classification itself

is supposed to he made in terms of tradition and modernity.

But it is difficult to understand what exactly could be meant

by 'traditionalism' in the context of rule-application. Further,

there seems little reason to think that differences in style would

be confined only to the classificatory types elaborated by the

authors in the context of interest articulation and interest

aggregation. However, as the authors themselves have said little

in the matter, it is difficult to judge its relevance as a criterion

in the context of our discussion on political development.

On the other hand, even though Almond and Powell have

not said much about the other differences in terms of com-

plexity, hierarchical structure, degree of autonomy and impar-

tiality of rule-enforcement, it is easy to guess how they would

treat them as indicators of political development. Perhaps the

more complex, the more hierarchical, the more autonomous,

the more impartial a differentiated structure devoted to rule-

application is, the more politically developed it is likely to he

considered by the authors. But even here the situation is not

clear. One is not quite sure if complexity and hierarchy are to

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 131

be regarded as positively correlated to political development.

Perhaps the more complex a structure is the more difficult it

is for it to discharge its functions. Also, if too pronounced a

hierarchy is considered incompatible with democratic values,

it may not be palatable to those who consider Homo Hierar-

chicus61 to he a characteristic of decadent Asian, or rather,

specifically Hindu, civilization. Not only this, an elaborate

hierarchy can interfere with the efficient functioning of any

institution, as is well known in India where almost all functions

are subdivided and correlated to a hierarchical ranking in

terms of the status of those who perform those functions. The

subdivision can be carried on almost indefinitely, as any task

can be divided in such a manner that each part is performed by

different persons, making each dependent on the other. The

so-called division'of labour, when linked to status considera-

tions on the one hand and to employment considerations on the

other, may lead to increasingly inefficient performance instead

of what was so glowingly ascribed to it by Adam Smith.

Complexity and hierarchy, thus, cannot be treated without

reservations as positive indicators of political development. As

for the autonomy and impartiality of rule-enforcement, they

are perhaps stronger candidates for being treated as positive

indicators. Yet even in their case, there seem to be some limita-

tions. Autonomy, for example, cannot be treated as unaccoun-

tability and is at least primafacie incompatible with the demand

for impartiality of rule-enforcement. For if impartiality of rule-

enforcement is itself to be enforced, there has to be a curtailment

of the autonomy of the differentiated structures entrusted with

the task of rule-application. In fact, the more differentiated and

autonomous the rule-application structures become, the more

do they develop vested interests of their own. The issue is

discussed by Almond and Powell in the context of bureaucracy,

but they have not related it to the issues of autonomy or

impartiality of rule-enforcement, nor, for that matter, to those

of hierarchy and complexity.

Bureaucracy, in fact, is a generalized name for all dif-

ferentiated structures performing the rule-application function.

The importance of bureaucracy as an indication both of

modernization and political development is well known to

students of the social sciences since Max Weber brought it to

132 Political Develo ,pment

their attention. His linking of bureaucratic structures with

formal-rational authority, as distinguished from traditional and

charisniatic authority, made it the pivotal point in all thought

about modernization which is equated with rationality on the

one hand and impersonal, rule-deterniined behaviour, on the

other. We need not discuss in detail the adequacy of Weber's

conception of bureaucracy or even of the later attempts of,

say, Simon62 and Parsons63 in this regard. The, important point

in the context of our discussion is not how bureaucracy is to be

conceived or characterized, or even whether Weber's emphasis

on formal rationality was misplaced as it 'led him to overesti-

mate the efficiency of formal rationality and to underestimate

the extent to which patrimonial features can help to overcome

bureaucratic pathologies'.114 What is of greater significance is

the fact that this differentiated structure which is given the

task of rule-application begins to have interests of its own and

to use its power for its own ends. As Almond and Powell argue,

'bureaucracies tend to monopolize outputs', as 'only bureaucrats

enforce laws, policies, or decisions'."rl But if such is the situation,

then it is difficult to see how the differentiation of structure has

really helped the situation. Rather, it has created an additional

problem of seeing that the newly created differentiated struc-

ture does not begin to subvert the purposes for which it has been

created.

The authors appear to consider this aspect of the problem to

be so important that they are even prepared to assert that

'political development subsequent to the Age of Absolutism

in Western Europe may be viewed in part as a process of

growth of agencies intended to direct, control, or limit central

bureaucracy'.66 And further that, 'the art of modern rulership

consists not only in the'prudent search for appropriate goals

and policies, but also in learning how to interact with this

massive and complex set of instrumentalities, and in knowing

how and when to press it and coerce it, how and when to

flatter it and reward it, how to teach it, and how to learn from

it.167 Yet, if this is the situation, one may legitimately wonder

who is the master and who the servant in the situation, or even

whether it is correct to say that it is a differentiated structure

devoted to the task of rule-application. In fact, if we remember

that 'in addition to having this monopoly of rule-enforcement,

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 133

bureaucracies are t , ypically of great importance in the processes

of rule-making""' and that 'the decisions made by political

6lites, whether they be executives or legislators, are also based

in considerable part on the kind of information which they are

able to get from administrative agencies',"9 then we begin to

understand why 'political scientists quail before the task of

generalizing about the importance of bureaucracy',"' which

'is a technical-instrumental monster'."" The authors do not

seem to have noticed the contradiction between the so-called

'technical-instrumental' nature of bureaucracy and its sup-

posedly essential role not merely in rule-making, but also in

interest articulation as 'interest groups, political parties, and

the public are dependent on information transmitted by ad-

ministrative officials'.72 If the role of bureaucracy is crucial at

the stage of both interest articulation and rule-making, it is

difficult to see how the institution of bureaucracy is dif-

ferentiated with respect to the performance of its function which

is supposed to be the reason for considering it an index of

political deve 'lopment.

It may be suggested that we should distinguish between the

primary and secondary functions of any institution, and that

if we do so we would discover that the primary function of

bureaucracy is still rule-application, while all the other fund-

tions happen to be merely secondary. Also, the tendency of any

differentiated institution to develop vested interests of its own

and even to usurp.functions not belonging to itself, is too

generalized to be considered a specific peculiarity of bureau-

cracy alone. Yet, even if all this be admitted it does not help

us at all in knowing whether a particular polity is developed or

not. Are we supposed to accept the fact that the development

of bureaucracy per se is a sign of political development? If this

were so, there would seem little point in the authors saying that

'the art of modern rulership consists ... in knowing how and

when topress it and coerce it, how and when to flatter it and

reward it', 73 and that 'political development ... may be viewed

in part as a process of growth of agencies intended to direct,

control, or Limit central bureaucracy'."14 This is so obviously an

obstructionist view of bureaucracy that one wonders how,

within the perspective, it could ever come to be regarded as

constituting development per se. Rather, it is apprehended as

10

134 Political Development

something that naturally tends to get out of hand, to develop

purposes of its own, to thwart and obstruct what it is asked to

do-something in the nature of a necessary evil which one

wishes one could do without, but which cannot be eliminated

because of the way the world is constituted.

Perhaps the criteria in terms of which bureaucracy may be

viewed as an indicator of political development may be found

in Fainsod's typology regarding bureaucracies, which Almond

and Powell have discussed at sonic length in their book.

According to them, 'Fainsod's classification is based upon dif-

ferent relationship patterns between bureaucracies and the

political agencies. He suggests five patterns: (1) representative

bureaucracies; (2) party-State bureaucracies; (3) military-

dominated bureaucracies; (4) ruler-dominated bureaucracies;

and (5) ruling bureaucracies.'75 The first type is characteristic

of a political system 'in which the ultimate political authority

is determined by a competitive political process',76 while the

second 'is characteristic of totalitarian r6gimes and other

one-party-dominated political systems'.77 The second type is

'characterized by the superimposition of a political bureaucracy

upon a functionally differentiated and technically competent

governmental bureaucracy'. '18 The third type 'describes systems

in which one component of the bureaucracy-members of the

officer corps-takes control over the civilian bureaucracy'.711

The fourth type coincides with Eisenstadt's' 'bureaucratic

empires'."" The reference is to classical. empires which were

maintained by autocratic rulers through the instrument of a

bureaucracy. The fifth and final category is one 'in which the

bureaucracy itself provides the ruling element in the political

,system'.$' The difference between this and the military-

dominated bureaucracy is that here a 'civil bureaucratic clique

possesses the authority', while in the former it is the military

group which dominates the scene.

Fainsod's scheme is primarily classificatory and one may

only surmise its relationship to political development. It is

obvious that the last three types can hardly be considered to be

positive indicators of political development. The ruling bureau-

cracies and military-dorainated bureaucracies destroy the

differentiated role of bureaucracy altogether, while the ruler-

dominated bureaucracies may be ruled out as royalty seems to

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 135

be out of favour with contemporary thinkers on political devel-

opment. Out of the two remaining claimants, it is obvious that

representative bureaucracies would be considered more lik 1ely

candidates than party-state bureaucracies, as the former allow

a greater competitiveness in the political process, thus permit-

ting the conflicting interests to come into the open. However,

this is basically the, perspective of interest articulation, and

intrinsically it cannot he regarded as a criterion of political

development arising immanently from the field of bureaucracy

itself. In fact, as a differentiated structure devoted to the

performance of the rule-application function, it is not clear why

party-state bureaucracies may not be considered as more

efficient, specially as the superimposition of a political bureau-

cracy an the so-called technical bureaucracy may be taken to

ensure not only that it functions effectively but also that it does

not develop any illegitimate vested interests of its own. The

necessity of some such control of governmental bureaucracies is

admitted by Almond and Powell, and they even concede that

'there are similar tendencies in democratic SySteMSI.82 They

point out, for example, that, 'in recent decades in the develop-

ment of the American political system, it has been found that

the only way in which the executive and legislative branches

can exercise relatively effective control over the bureaucracy is

through the development of their own specialized bureau-

cracies'.83 But once the necessity of political control of the

bureaucracy is accepted, it is difficult to set any limits to it

unless some reasons are given which prescribe when and

why those limits are to be drawn. The development of a poli-

tical bureaucracy to control other sectors of the bureaucracy is

analogous to niilitary-dominated bureaucracies on the one hand

and ruling bureaucracies on the other. In all three, a particular

sector of the bureaucracy controls the others, and bureaucracy

as a whole tends to monopolize all the political functions. On

the other hand, it is difficult to see why the ruler-dominated

bureaucracies should be considered less politically developed

than representative bureaucracies, unless one wants to bring

the criterion of representation into the picture. Also, if the

criterion of competitive representativeness is given up, there

would be little to differentiate between ruler-dominated

bureaucracies and party-dorninated bureaucracies, as all

136 Political Development

totalitarian parties are ruled by a single person whether he be

called a comrade or Fiihrer. Nor can the claim to represent

the real interests of the people be considered the sole privilege

of totalitarian dictators, as the same claim is made by rulers of

the traditional type aIso. Nor, for that matter, can the mode of

succession be taken as a relevant differentiating factor, as the

struggle for succession may and, in fact, did occur in the case of

traditional rulers, just as modern totalitarianisms are not

immune from attempts at hereditary succession, specially in

their Asian setting.

Fainsod's typology of various kinds of bureaucracies is, thus,

of little help in finding the criteria of political development.

Basically, there seems to have been little discussion about this

aspect of the matter. What appears to have engaged the atten-

tion of Almond and Powell is the necessity of a bureaucracy for

any political development whatsoever. But this only makes it a

necessary condition in the technical sense that, without it, no

political development impossible. However, as is well known, a

necessary condition is not a sufficient condition and hence its

presence cannot be taken as an indicator of political develop-

ment. It is merely a precondition which, by itself, cannot ensure

anything one way or the other. And, in any case, as bureau-

cracy is only a generalized name for all rule-application struc-

tures, the issues that we have raised earlier with respect to

rule-application as a criterion of political development still

remain relevant. After a rule has been made, it may be said

that the relevant thing is to determine whether it has actually

been applied in practice or not. In other words, the central

question is whether the rule or rules so formulated are obeyed

or not, and in case they are not obeyed, what is done in the

matter. However, as everybody knows, this is not the task of the

rule-application structures. Rather, it is the task of those who

adjudicate and impose sanctions in case the rules are not obeyed

and exemplified in conduct. The clue to political development

thus may be found not in rule-making or rule-application, but

rather in rule-adjudication which may be taken simultaneously

to determine what the rule specifically means and also whether

it has been observed in a particular case or not.

The Criterion as Conversion Functions

137

(5) The Criterion as Rule-Adjudication

As a rule which is enacted has to be applied in order to serve

the function of rule-making, so also is it necessary to judge whe-

ther the rule has been correctly applied or not, whether it has

been applied at all orjust ignored or even violated in actual prac-

tice. The adjudicative function thus may be regarded as the

most important and central in any consideration of rules which

have to be observed in order that they may presumably fulfil the

purpose or purposes for which they were enacted. In a formal

sense, what the rule really prescribes can only he decided by

the adjudicating authority. But if the issue is not brought before

the adjudicating authority, it is usually presumed that the way

those entrusted with the task of rule-application are interpreting

them in practice is the way in which the adjudicating authori-

ties would uphold them also. However, once the issue is brought

before the adjudicating authority and the interpretation dis-

puted, the presumption is broken and it is clear that the rule

means what thejudges hold it to mean.

On the other hand, judges can only pronounce a judgment;,

they cannot carry it out or ensure that it is carried out. In

times of political crisis, it is well known that the judiciary

tends to lose its independence and becomes increasingly an

instrument of those who wield actual power. Yet, once the

crisis has passed, one has to revert again to the restitution of

the adjudicating mechanisms and ensure that judgments enjoy

both independence and effectiveness to some extent.

The independence and effectiveness of the adjudicating

structures in a polity, thus, may be taken as a criterion of

political development. The differentiation of such structures

and the respect, autonomy and citectivity that they are granted

would thus be an indicator of the extent to which a society may

be regarded as governed by law rather than by brute and naked

force. The taming of force is a perennial task of all civil society,

and this is perhaps best achieved by developing a rule of law

which defines what is to count as a legitimate exercise of power

and what as its blatant abuse. The notion of legitimacy is

closely allied or perhaps even derived from the notion of 'lawful'

and thus shows the central importance of the adjudicating

function in a civil polity.

138 Political Development

But, however much we may accept the importance and cen-

trality of the adjudicating function, it is difficult to see

how it can be treated as an indicator of political development.

Shall we say that, if there are differentiated structures devoted

to the task of rule-adjudication, it may be taken as a sign of

the polity being developed in the positive sense of the word?

But this may be deduced from the generalized criterion of

development as differentiation of structures and functions which

we have already discussed at length elsewhere. Or, shall we

look into the form of its functioning or the contents of its

decisions to judge whether it is developed or not? The form of

its functioning is, in a sense, determined by the law of the land

along with what has come to be called the civic or political

culture of a society. A judgment on the contents of judicial

decisions, on the other hand, would raise the whole question of

values in terms of which development has to be understood or

defined.

It is perhaps advisable to turn away from these formal and

material criteria and concentrate on the sheer quantity and

volume of cases brought before the courts and adjudicated by

them within a given period of time. An increase in the number

of cases brought before the judiciary could then be taken as an

index of political development. All the sophistication which

has been developed in connection with the measurement of

quantitative indices in other fields could be transferred and

applied to this domain also. We could thus devise methods to

find out per capita litigation rates for different countries and

judge their c 'omparative political development in these terms.

It is, of course, not clear from the literature in the field whether

an increase or decrease in the litigation rates would be taken

as a sign of political development. Lucian Pye, for example,;

asserts that 'by 1900 one Bengali out of every seventy-four

was engaged in some form of litigation'. and that 'in Java after

the Western impact it appears that the rate of litigation not only@

kept pace with, but indeed exceeded, the rate of population

growth.'84 Similarly, 'in Rangoon before World War 11,

interest in the working of law took on a sporting quality. Asian

business houses customarily set aside each year surplus funds

that were invested in energetic searches for profitable law-

suits."15

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 139

Now, neither India nor Indonesia or Burma are usually con-

sidered by writers on political development to be politically

developed. Hence it is unlikely that an increase in litigation

rates is being regarded by Lucian Pye as an indicator of positive

political development. But if increasing recourse to legal

adjudication through differentiated formal structures created

for that very purpose is not treated as a sign of development, it

can only be because an increase in conflict of interests is treated

as a counter-indicator of development. But if that be the situa-

tion, it would be difficult to hold any increase in interest arti-

culation or interest aggregation as indicating political devel-

opment also. For, in most cases, interests happen to conflict and

that is why they have to be aggregated or adjudicated. The only

difference between adjudication and aggregation in this respect

is that, while the former tries to reconcile diverse interests to

the maximum possible extent, the latter tries to determine the

rightness or wrongness of the conflicting claims and pronounces

on their legitimacy or illegitimacy in terms of the prevailing

legal rights in the society to which the conflicting parties appeal.

Also, an increasing recourse to rule-adjudication may be taken

as a sign of increasing awareness on the part of the people of

their rights and of a willingness on their part to settle conflicts

through formal-legal procedures rather than resort to violence.

At a deeper level it may even be taken to indicate a faith in the

system rather than alienation from it and, if so, it would have

to be taken a's a positive indicator of development.

The ambivalence with regard to all the indices of political

development and the double standards employed in their

application is perhaps nowhere more evident than in Lucian

Pye's remarks about the quality and patterns of lawsuits in

Burma. To quote in full, he writes. 'Asian business houses

customarily set aside each year surplus funds that were invested

in energetic searches for profitable lawsuits. Young solicitors

were employed to rack their brains and dream up ingenious

suits, and older rogues with scheming minds would, for a

customary commission, assist in spotting likely targets for such

suits.""' Now, it is difficult to believe that Pye does not know

that such a situation obtains in the United States, specially in

the fields of medicine and insurance. It is well known that

claims for damages under the law of torts have been carried to

140 Political Development

such an extreme as to jeopardize the healthy functioning of

many professions in western countries. Yet, in their case it is

interpreted as an indication of the individual's consciousness

of his rights and thus a positive indicator of political develop-

ment. The absence of cases under the law of torts, on the other

hand, in a country such as India is usually taken as a counter-

indicator of civic development, for it is interpreted to mean lack

of consciousness on the part of the citizens of their rights against

others. But when a different phenomenon is observed in the case

of Burma, Pye, instead of being happy with the situation, prefers

to lapse into a satirical vein and suggest that there is something

radically wrong with Asian peoples who cannot work western

institutions as they were meant to be worked.

In fact, the contention becomes explicit when Pye writes

about the fallacious assumptions which lie behind the western

approach to law, and whose fallaciousness became explicit only

when transplanted to Asian soil. According to him,

the underlying assumption of the Westernized and codified legal

system was that all possible problems could be classified according to

categories, that the examination of the data would reveal which

category was appropriate to the particular case or issue, and that,

once category and data were so clarified, a standardized process of

reasoning and interpretation would bring anyone versed in the ways

of the law to the proper judgment. The fallacies in these Western

assumptions about the process of adjudication were readily manifest

once codified legal systems were introduced into Asian and African

societies."'

But if the assumptions are fallacious, it is difficult to see why

they should not be fallacious in western countries also. If it is

an illusion 'that all possible categories of problems could be

initially defined to prevent the need for any expostfacto judg-

ments, and that the data or facts could "speak for themselves"

in the sense that once brought to light,they would somehow

automatically inform all under what category of the law they

should be properly classified',$" then it is difficult to believe that

it would not vitiate every action based on such an illusion. One

wonders what illusions Pye entertains about the legal system as

it operates in western countries. Surely, neither in science nor

in law do facts 'speak for themselves', nor is it true that any set

of facts could be categorized in only one way. If that were so,

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 141

the legal profession would have ceased to be attractive and

lucrative long ago. It is because there is no unique category of law

under which any human action has inevitably to be considered

that legal disputes arise and that, even after all the debate and

discussion has occurred and the evidence recorded, no one knows

what the judge's decision in the case will be.

The deeper source of the trouble, however, seems to be that

the issue of political development is treated primarily as a

problem of non-western countries or even of countries other

than the United States,of America. There appears to be an

implicit a priori assumption underlying the writings of most

authors on political development that as far as western coun-

tries are concerned there is no problem of political development.

Or, in case there is, it pertains only to such countries as Italy

or France or Spain, that is, those countries of western Europe

which have not yet achieved the maturity of the U.K. or the

U.S.A. As the U.K. in any case has lostits economic supremacy,

the mantle of economic and political maturity has fallen on the

United States, and as most writers on political development

happen to belong to that country it is perhaps natural for them

to look for issues surrounding the problem of political develop-

ment in countries other than their own. But the best way to

understand a problem in the social or human sphere is to

discover an analogue in one's own experience, as that alone

can supply the clue to that inner understanding without which

external dissimilarities may lead one to posit a difference where

there may be none, or perhaps even a difference of a totally

different kind.

However, the situation is even more intriguing. Not only is

there no dearth of intellectuals in the United States who are

hypercritical of their own country, but also the normal norms

of scientific investigation demand that anyone proposing a

criterion for anything should treat it as a culture-invariant,

that is, as an indicator of the same phenomenon wherever it be

found, whether in one culture or another. A culture, of course,

may be treated as an organic whole but in that case it would

perhaps be impossible to compare different cultures in terms

of isolated elements with regard to which they may be com-

pared andjudged. The only way this could be done would be te

compare the functions which the elements perform in different

142 Political Development

cultures, but this assumes that in terms of function most cultures

would be the same or at least similar in essential respects. Most

writers on political development tend to assume this, and hence

even if they subscribe to the organic totalistic view of society or

culture, there is no reason why they should fail to see the same

phenomena in their own country which they nd in countries

they deem to be politically undeveloped.

Perhaps the difference may relate to the weightage given to a

particular factor in the total assessment of a polity. But, if so,

the problem of weightage has to be brought into the open and

it has to be shown how the indicators of a negative kind are

cancelled by the presence of other positive factors. Or, if it be

maintained that the very negativity of the factors is affected by

the contexts in which they occur, and that it is meaningless to

talk of positive and negative indicators in isolation, then it is

incumbent on those who argue this way to specify the contexts

in which an indicator would be interpreted as positive or nega-

tive in nature. Nothing of the kind has been done by any of

these thinkers. In fact, they are as far off from the organic

theory of society as anybody can be. Yet, even if they were to

he organic in their view of society-and functionalism of a sort

can perhaps lead in that direction-, they would have to face

the equally baffling problem of how to compare two societies

conceived as organic wholes except by positing a concept of

some ideal society which transcends them both and in terms

of which they may be judged.

Any comparative judgment regarding different legal struc-

tures leads straight into the baffling problem of legal positivism.

If we agree with the legal positivists that there is a radical dif-

ference between 'law as it is' and 'law as it ought to be', then

it is obvious that two existing legal structures cannot be signi-

ficantly compared as qua existing they have both to be conceded

the status of laws. It would then be only in the external context

of moral considerations that the two legal structures could be

judged. On the other hand, if we accept Fuller's concept of the

so-called 'inner morality of law', we could perhaps judge

between two existing legal structures with respect to the extent

to which they have realized this 'inner morality' which is

immanent within the notion of a 'legal system' itself. The

classic controversy on this issue between H. L. A. Hart and

The Criterion as Conv@rsion Functions 143

Lon,, L. Fuller is too well known to be repeated here.119 What

may, however, be pointed out is that the issue is at least as old

as Plato and relates, at least at the philosophical level, to all

comparisons between any two objects or sets of objects, rather

than to the specific sphere of law alone. Every entity in order

to be that entity must possess the properties that entitle it to be

considered that entity. Thus, in a sense, hardly any entity

could be compared with any other of its own class, provided it

has been correctly classified in terms of the essential properties

on the basis of which it is supposed to belong to that class. In

other words, the comparison may only be done in terms of

accidental or adventitious qualities, and never in terms of

essential qualities. On the other hand, if even the essential

qualities are supposed to be embodied more or less, as Plato

seems to hold, then it would follow that no object could be

correctly classified as none could exemplify or embody the

ideal completely. Not only this, a more difficult problem

would relate to the apprehension of the ideal in terms of which

the particular exemplifications are to bejudged. Unless some

special faculty of rational intuition be postulated or one accepts

the Platonic notion of remembering, one would have only the

concrete embodiments to intuit the ideal, and in this one

would always be on hazardous ground, as not only is there no

certainty that the concretely encountered instances would point

unmistakably to one ideal alone, but also because they would

always form an infinitely small part of what will be, encountered

in the future. The recourse to the well-known law of large

numbers in the field of statistical theory would perhaps be of

little avail; it is not only questionable on philosophical grounds,

but a significant difference may also be presumed between the

apprehension of an ideal through its concrete exemplifications

and the apprehension of a law, even if it be conceived in a

statistical manner.

On the other hand, even if we re-fuse to accept the Platonic

assimilation of the natural world to that in which values or

ideals may be said to inhere in the very apprehension of reality,

law by its very nature would seem to belong to the latter

category. Yet, even if this be admitted and the claim of Fuller

to the necessary existence of some 'inner morality of law' be

conceded, there remains the problem of the relation of the so-

144 Political Development

-5

called 'inner morality of law' to its 'outer morality'. Fuller

conceded that 'in the life of a -

moralities of law reciprocally influence one another; a deterio-

ration of the one will almost inevitably produce a deteriora-

tion in the other'.911 But the problem is not so much of a causal

influence, as whether the one can possibly be judged in terms

of the other. Can, for example, the inner morality of law he

judged at the bar of morality that is external to it? Once this

is conceded, Hart's distinction between 'law as it is' and 'law

as it ought to be' would be reinstated irrespective of the fact

whether law may be said to have an 'internal morality' of its

own or not.

But the distinction is meaningful only if the 'law as it ought

to be' is allowed to shape and influence the 'law as it is'. This

would be as true of Fuller's 'internal morality of law' as of

Hart's 'morality' which is supposed to be wholly 'other' than

law, for even Fuller's 'inner morality of law' is not completely

realized by every legal system that is known by that name. But

this itself, as is well known, is the subject of one of the most

fundamental disputes in the philosophy of law. The Hart-

Devlin controversy on the enforcement of morals is as famous

as the Hart-Fuller controversy on the separation of law and

morals."' It has been contended by Hart, amongst others, that

it is not the task of law to enforce public morality. The point

was made in the context of a debate which arose out of what

has come to be called 'Shaw's case' and Lord Devlin's Mac-

cabean lecture, entitled The Enforcement of Morals. The judges

in Shaw's case had observed that 'the courts should function

as the custos morum or the general censor and guardian of the

public manners',112, and Lord Devlin argued in his famous

lecture that 'the suppression of vice is as much the law's

business as the suppression of subversive activities'. 93

The issue, however, is a far wider one than the immediate

contexts in which it arose. It relates to the whole issue of law

and morality on the one hand, and to the function of law, on

the other. If it is not the task of law to enforce morals,

is its function? Hart has, of course, distinguished between

positive and critical morality on the one hand and

private and critical morality on the other, and has tried

argue that it is not the task of the law to enforce private

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 145

morality, even of the positive kind, that is, that which obtains

in society at any particular moment of time. But the question

is not whether there is any realm of private morality which law

should never enforce. The question rather is what role should

critical morality play with respect to positive morality, both

of the private and the public kind on the one hand, and positive

law on the other. Once it is admitted that critical morality has

a role to play and that the demand for a change in positive law

on the basis of its moral evaluation is justified, it follows that

the moral critic by virtue of the fact that he desires the laws to

be changed concedes that the enforcement of morals is at least

one of the important functions of law, even if besides it there

be many others. The separation between 'law as it is' and 'law

as it should be' would lose all meaning if 'law as it should be'

is not allowed to influence positive law at all. Similarly, Fuller's

notion of 'inner morality of law' would become infructuous if it

has no relation to either positive or critical morality. Res-

ponsiveness to both positive and critical morality is the essence

of a law that is living and alive.

Responsiveness, of course, may and ought to be creative in

character. Also, in a sense, it is inescapable, for whether the

judge wishes it or not he has to interpret and apply the law to

situations for which it was never intended. It is intrinsic to the

very nature of law that it can never, in principle, anticipate all

the situations to which and in which it may have to be applied.

Hart has felicitously called this the area of 'penumbral deci-

sions', and though he disputes that this leads to what has come

to be called, following Cardozo 114, 'judicial legislation', still

there can be little doubt that the distinction between 'clear

cases' and 'penumbras decisions' is, at best, a tenuous one. To

suggest that'thejudges are only "drawing out" of the rule what,

if it is properly understood, is "latent" within it', 115 is obviously

to stretch the notion of what is 'latent' a little too far. On the

other hand, as Fuller has shown, a judicial interpretation even

in the so-called clear cases cannot be made unless the judge

asks himself the question, 'What can this rule be for? What evil

does it seek to avert? What good is it intended to promotc?,911

Yet, even if we accept Fuller's point, it would not follow that

the distinction between 'law as it is' and 'law as it ought to be'

would cease to operate, for our notions of good and evil them-

146 Politkal Development

selves may change. And though, following Hart, one may try to

provide continuity between the old and the new notion, it may

only be a fiction postulated to provide the- illusion that things

have not changed much. Conversely, after a revolution, one

may emphasize the, break and the novelty, even when not much

might have changed.

This is not exactly the place to pursue either the Hart-Fuller

controversy or the Hart-Devlin controversy any further.97 Our

only contention is that the criterion of rule-adjudication for the

ascertainment of political development must first sort out some

of these problems before it can even stake its claim as a relevant

idea in the field. The controversy regarding the Nazi legal

system illustrates this pre-eminently. But the same could be

said of most dictatorships which make a mockery of the so-

called 'inner morality of law'. Fuller seems to have assumed

too easily that 'Coherence and goodness have more affinity than

coherence and evil'."8 It would have been difficult for him

perhaps to say this had he not confined his attention to un-

successful tyrannies like that of the Nazis, but also included the

lasting and successful tyrannies such as those of the Soviet or

Chinese dictatorships. He might then perhaps have accepted

the possibility that 'evil aims may have as much coherence and

inner logic as good ones'. 99

It is strange that these issues have hardly received an atten-

1 y

tion in the literature on political development. One can only

conclude that rule-adjudication has been included in the list

only to accommodate the traditional tripartite division of

political structures and functions into the legislative, executive

and judiciary. Basically the interest of thinkers on political

development had shifted long back from giving much weight

to formal-legal considerations in comparisons between different

politics. This perhaps was a result of the fact that formal-legal

structures had begun increasingly to be viewed as instruments

for the achievements of social ends or as the product of social

forces which lay behind them. Both the Marxist and the

structural-functional approaches tended to strengthen this way

of looking at legal reality, and those who regarded law in any

other light except as masking the real interests and forces

behind the fagade presented by the legal structure came to be

considered innocent fools, if not as agents of reactionary

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 147

forces. The concepts of civil and political liberty around which

much liberal political thought of the previou!? era revolved fell

into disuse and thus the problem of creating legal structures

which would foster and safeguard them tended to be completely

forgotten. In fact, the concept of political liberty has ceased to

be in the centre of political thought, and thus the problem of

providing legal safeguards for its preservation and growth has

also tended to fall into the background.

But, whatever be the reasons for the neglect of the criteria

in terms of which different legal structures may be compared

and adjudged, it is clear that unless this preliminary exercise

is done, there is no point in looking for the criteria of political

development in this domain. Not only this, we should be able

to offer justification for the criteria chosen and, at a deeper

level, be able to answer the question why political devel

opment is identified with legal development or whether any

distinction between them has also to be accepted. Perhaps the

latter may be accepted as a necessary condition of the former,

assuming of course that the notion of legal development is free

from the difficulties we have been countering in connection

with that of political development.

Under the circumstances, it is difficult to believe that the

recourse to rule-adjudication would be of any substantial help

in solving difficulties clustering around the concept of political

development. Law, in any case, has ramifications far beyond

the sphere of what may be considered the domain of the

political. It concerns itself with almost all aspects of society and

economy, including even those which may be regarded as

predominantly personal and private. Positive law would then

have to be treated, specially in the way as it is actually operated,

as an indicator of the positive morality of a society which, if it

is to be judged, may only be done by an appeal to some ideal

morality which would have to be justified on other grounds. On

the other hand, it has to be remembered that even the sphere

of positive morality is far, far wider than that of positive law,

and that it would hardly be desirable if the two were to coincide

or even if the distance between the two were to lessen to any

significant extent in any society or polity' The concept of

society is far more deeply related to that of culture, and culture,

as everybody knows, is far wider than law. The clue to political

148 Political Development

development then may he sought not in positive law or even in

the actual proce@s of rule-adjudication as found in a particular

society, but rather in the civil or political culture in which all

the political processes are embedded and which may be said to

give them meaning or significance.

To turn to a discussion of political or civic culture as an

indicator of political development is to leave the so-called

'conversion-functions' behind and to move on into a different

domain. Yet, our detailed discussion of each of the conversion-

functions has revealed their inadequacy for providing satis-

factory criteria for political development. It may, however,

still be objected'that in discussing each of them separately in

an isolated manner we have done violence to the, whole spirit of

the discussion on political development. For, it may be said

that it was never the intention of the proponents to offer them

in such an isolated manner for consideration as a criterion of

political development. Rather, they should be treated in their

complex interrelationship which alone could serve in a unified

manner as an indicator of political development.

The objection need not be dismissed lightly by saying that if

each criterion offered has been found to be inadequate singly,

it is highly unlikely that the same criteria when considered in

some sort of interactive unity would reveal a positive adequacy

instead of a compounding of their inadequacies into a whole,

which would be even more inadequate in character. G. E.

Moore in his Principia Ethica has warned us that the value of a

complex whole need not be a sum of the values of its parts,

and as the notion of 'adequacy' is perhaps a valuational notion

we should be well advised to take the objection seriously and

find out whether the inadequacies get compounded or cancelled

when the criteria are considered not in their isolation but

togetherness. But before embarking on this examination it

would be well if we briefly consider the claims of political cul-

ture, political communication and the System Maintenance and

Adaptation Functions as indicators of political development.

(6) Political Culture as an Indicator of Development

The concept of political culture is obviously borrowed from

anthropological studies on the one hand, and the study of

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 149

civilizations on the other. The anthropologists have tended to

view culture as the structure of meanings in terms of which the

actual observed behaviour of the people of an alien society

is interpreted in such a way as to accord with those people's

interpretation of their own actions. The student of civilizations,

on the other hand, cannot observe the behaviour of people as

they have long ceased to exist. The only things he, has to work

upon are the remnants of what has been left behind and

survived the accidents of time. These he has to interpret and,

through them, to intuit the meanings, ideals and values in

terms of which they gave sense and significance to their lives in

their brief mortal sojourn on this earth. The term 'political

culture' has perhaps more aflinity with the first orientation

than with the second. But even there it has more of a valua-

tional orientation in the sense that thinkers who undertake this

approach are not interested in interpreting the behaviour of

the participants in the political process in those terms which

make it meaningful to them but rather as it facilitates or

obstructs the realization of what they regard as 'political devel-

opment'. Thus, in a sense, political scientists who think in

terms of 'political culture' are interested in the phenomenon

neither as anthropologists nor as students of civilizations, but

rather as those who are interested primarily in the study of

comparative cultures. As the evolutionary perspective gradually

slides into the developmental perspective, cultural relativism

and pluralism give way to the notion of cultural development

conceived mostly in what may be called an 'ethnocentric' or

Cculture-centrie' manner.

This 'culture-centricism', however, has itself given way to a

thought which treats the whole of culture in an instrumental

manner. Since Marx termed the whole of culture a 'super-

structure', and Weber propounded the thesis of the protestant

ethic in the rise of capitalism, culture has come to be regarded

as an instrument for the realization of ends other than its own.

It has been treated both as a fagade that hides reality from the

consciousness of observers and participants alike, as well as that

which makes reality tolerable or liveable for man. Seen either

as a lubricating oil for the creakingjoints of the social machine

or as a compensatory dream which makes the oppressive re-

F@ression of social reality bearable or as a beautiful mask which

11

150 Political Development

hides hideous reality, it is always treated in relation to some-

thing other than itself, and an instrument therco£ The talk of

Cpolitic,al culture' is no different, and it is primarily seen in

terms of Political development'. Following Webedan studies

on the one. hand, and the failure of many new nations of Asia

and Africa to make good in the economic domain on the other,

the question began to be asked whether the traditional cultures

of these societies stood in the way of their econonuc develop-

ment. M many of these new nations failed not only in the

economic field but also in the, political in the sense th@it.they

achieved neither stability nor growth, the same questions began

to be raised with respect to the political domain also. But once something is seen instrumentally, it cannot serve as a criterion of.that in relation to which it is treated as an

instrument, except in the indirect sense that its presence or

absence would also be treated as an, indicator of the presence

or absence of the other. But, even for this, it is necessary that

independent criteria be first available for determining whether the so-called effect@ or rather that which is supposed to be

hieved by some other instrumentality, is itself developed or

not. The talk of political culture, therefore, is no substitute for

the task of determining viable criteria of development with

respect to the political domain.

It may, of course, be argued that as culture usually

the pattern of interactive behaviour in any parti

and the values that are implicit therein and gst different

;p 4,1@cen the ruling

being intuited through its continuous and prolo@ @-Ation would arise as

tion, a discussion of culture with respect to an

be considered more

domain is about the domain itself. Viewed in. this i@, 0

would be little difference between political cultu c a single uniform politi

realm which is designated as 'political'. Political de

fundamental distinction

thus, would become identical with the development ; kb' of the rulers or power holders and that of

culture itself. The discussion would, however, then 4 r.' it is obvious that the relation of political

nature of cultural development in general and of cal development, howsoever conceived, would

pertains to the realm of political culture in particul ceived in a far more complex and differentiated other hand, there would be the elated question er, if the so-called masses themselves do not have

two are.related and how developments in the one fiel homogeneous political culture of their own, as is very likely

or obstruct developments in the other. be the case, there would be little point in making the broad

The notion of 'cultural development', however, is itself otomous division between the culture of the rulers and the

problematic, and stands in need of at least as much analysis as ruled. Perhaps even the political culture of the ruling 6lite may

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 151

that of 'political development'. It has been contended that no

matter how political development is conceived of or what

particular aspect of it is emphasized, the prevalent political

culture of a society cannot but be relevant to it, as it would

facilitate or obstruct the realization of political development in

that sense in the society concerned. As Lucian Pye has written,

gclearly no matter what particular aspect is emphasized political

development strikes at the roots of people's beliefs and senti-

ments about politics, and hence the proceq. ,\development

must be profoundly affected by the cb -

t_\the -politi

cal culture of a society."00 This is

modernity syndrome transposed

if we forget the gratuitous

concept of political de,,,

roots of people's b,'

people's beliefs

such a nat,-

cal dc:,

'@l-

tb >"

1 '

0. g'

il 4@ j@

:,,, , @e,,

o, , e

~

@r-

152 Political Development

not be as homogeneous as Pye seems to think, and the relevant

distinction may lie between those who share a homogeneous

political culture, whether they belong to the ruling elite or not,

and those who do not, or rather those who share a different

culture.

The problem, in fact, is further compounded as political

culture itself is a sub-system of culture in general. Or, if it be

objected that there is no such thing as culture in general but

rather cultures as differentiated with respect to particular

domains, the problem may be reformulated and articulated in

terms of the homogeneity or heterogeneity of the culture

obtaining in the political domain with those obtaining in other

domains. Sidney Verba has suggested that 'the distinction

between political culture and the more general cultural system

of a society is an analytical one."02But if the distinction were to

be merely analytical, it would be difficult to postulate the

possibility of heterogeneity between different segments or sub-

systems of a culture. Verba is of the opinion that 'the basic

belief and value patterns of a culture-those general values that

have no reference to specific political objects-usually play a

major role in the structuring of political culture'."')3 But if this

is so, the notion of an independent political culture would

become meaningless and, in any case, whether it is so or not, is

to he established empirically for every case and not assumed

a priori. Otherwise, the relationship that would have to be

investigated would be that between culture and political devel-

opment, and not between political culture and political devel-

opment.

The distinctiveness of political culture has been emphasized

by Lucian Pye and he has suggested that there are 'four specific

values which ... are apparently related to fundamental issues

that arise in the developmental process' .104 These, according to

him, relate to the dichotomies of trust-distrust, hierarchy-

equality, liberty-coercion, and the level of loyalty and com-

mitments relating to the primary political identifications of a

people. It is obvious that attitudes of trust, equality, liberty and

a generalized level of non-parochial identification would he

conducive to a polity of a certain kind which may be called

'developed', if these are the values that are taken to characterize

er constitute political development. But even amongst these, the

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 153

liberty-coercion dimension is distinctive in the sense that very

few people would like themselves to he coerced, though they

may not mind if others are coerced for the achievement of

certain ends. In fact, the attitudes towards the desirability or

undesirability of coercion may be expected to vary significantly

between the rulers and the ruled. Yet, the amount of actual

coercion would be an indication of the gulf between the values

of the rulers and the people, and of the extent of the people's

resistance to the imposition of values by the rulers. @

The other dimensions in terms of which the value-dicho-

toniies have been spelled out seem even far less clear-cut than

the coercion-liberty dimension. Trust-distrust, for example,

depends primarily on the performance of political rulers, and if

they not only have values which are different from those over

whom they rule but also dissimulate in their articulation and

profess those which they do not even mean to realize, then it is

inevitable that the masses would have a feeling of distrust

towards all those who rule them. After all, the history of the

behaviour of the ruling @lite down the ages is not such as to

inspire trust in those who have been ruled. The betrayal of

trust is such a constant feature of human history that it would

be amazing if trusting confidence were still to be found amongst

people. But even supposing such an innocence is found amongst

a people, would it be really helpful to political development, as

Verba seems to think? Or, would it not be playing into the

hands of the ruling 6lite and making their task of political decep-

tion easier ? The trusting populace is the dream of every ruler,

so that he may take them like docile sheep wherever he wants to

lead them. Would not a discriminatingly critical populace he

better than one that blindly trusts in its rulers?

The same may be said of the hierarchy-equality and the

extent and level-of-commitment dimensions of the value-

dichotomies pertaining to political culture. The relations of

power being essentially asymmetrical, it is difficult to see how

equality can ever characterize a political or even an administra-

tive system. But even if it were to be so characterized, it is not

easy to see how or why it should give better results than a

hierarchical structure. It should be remembered in this con-

nection that the openness of access to various positions in the

structure is a different issue from the egalitarian or hierarchical

154 Political Development

nature of the structure itself. As for the extent and depth of

commitment in terms of identification, it is not easy to see the

advantages of national identifications for political development,

rather than the so-called regional identifications on the one

hand, and the global identifications on the other. If equality

and participation are the directions which political develop-

rnent should take, then it is obvious that the political units of

which one is a member should not be too large. If human

beings are not to be divided into antagonistic and warring

groups, it is obvious that too much identification with the

nation-state would only lead to a condition of permanent

belligerency where each is preparing to fight the other.

@ The four values in terms of which Pye articulates political

culture do not thus seem to be related in any determinate,

unique way to the so-called processes of political development

even at the first level of analysis. Verba, on the other hand,

focuses 'on those basic political values that represent the most

general beliefs about the ends of political activity, about the

nature of the political process. and about the place of the

individual within it'."05 Besides the fourfold values emphasized

by Lucian Pye, Verba suggests that there are 'important

political beliefs about how the polity operates-not what it is,

but what it does',"06 'in particular it is the expectations the

members of a system have as to the output of the government-

what they believe it will and ought to do for and to them-that

are relevant here'.107But, as in the case of Pye's list, Verba's

delimitation of the contents of those beliefs which may be

relevant for political development does not help in telling us

what particular types of belief would help or hinder the pro-

cess. Also, there seems to be an implicit assumption that the

beliefs are an independent variable in the situation. But this

usually is not the case. The beliefs in most cases are themselves

the result of the past political experience of a people, can

only be changed by a change in the political practice of the

ruling 6lite itself. It is, of course, true that the political elite

themselves may arouse expectancies which they may not ' be

able to fulfil. One.may think of some sort of a dialectic between

the political apathy and political over-involvement of the

masses with the political elite playing an arousing and dampen-

ing role in the process.

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 155

Yet, however interesting such speculations may be, the' do y

not answer the basic question as to how political culture can

provide a criterion or criteria of political development. In fact,

if political cultures are different, and the term 'culture' in-

cludes the values that are considered worth realizing by the

culture, it would follow that each political culture would have

its own ideas or. rather@ ideal of political development. The

multiplicity of cultures is, in fact, merely another name for the

multiplicity of ideal ways in-whicii societiesconceive of them-

selves, and if political culture is merely an aspect of culture in

general, then it is@ obvious that the diversity of political cultures

would be merely another 'name for the diversity of political

ideals.

The idea of a plurality of political ideals, however, seems

anathema to political thinkers, so much so that' they hardly

dare give it a place in their scheme of thought about political

development. And this remains true even when they use the

notion of Culture, which in its anthropological context in@

evitably,implies plurality @nd multiplicity. Basically,- the .em@

phasis in most such literature'seems to be on those aspects of

culture which are conducive to secularization and ditterentia@

tion which themselves are treated as criteria of development in

general. As Almond and Powell write, 'we have,suggested,that

there is, in general an association between structural 'dif-

ferentiation, cultural secularization, and an expansion of the

capabilities of the political system. These associated attributes

are involved in the develo S .pment of political system , although of

course, such development is neither inevitable nor irrever-

sible."("' 'Differentiation' and 'capabilities' have already

been discussed at length as criteria of political development.

As for secularization, it appears to be too conveniently identi-

fied with a pragmatic-bargaining attitude prevalent primarily

in the U 'S.A. and secondarily in England than with what it

strictly means, that is, the denial of any transcendent or other-.

worldly dimension or allowing it to have any say in man"s

spatio-temporal affairs. In@the second sense, almost all modern

politics may be regarded as secular, while in the former sense

perhaps only the U 'S.A.. and perhaps U.K. would be regarded

as secular. Perhaps even in earlier times the states were not so

non-secular as they are now usually supposed to have been.

156 Political Development Religions in the past appear to have provided the same function as the ideologies of today. In other words, they prescribed the verbal rhetoric in terms of which the states justified their policies and with whose values they had to come to terms at least to some minimal extent. - The classification of political cultures 'according to the com- bination of parochials, subjects, and participants"09 can he of little help as the distinction between these in terms of the level of awareness about, and participation in, politics relates to the criterion as participation, which we have already examined at length, and does not add anything new to the discussion. The, detour to a discussion of political culture thus does not seem to raise any new issues with respect to the problem of political development. The same may be expected to be true of political socialization and political communica- tion which are also associated with the, discussion on political development. Yet, before discussing the conversion-functions in their totality as criteria for political development, we might tarry awhile and consider the possible help, if any, which political socialization and political communication may offer in a discussion on political development. (7) Political Socialization and Political Communication as Indicators of Political Development The term 'socialization' refers to the whole range of processes through which a newborn baby gradually grows into a full- grown adult member of his society. The process depends on a subtle use of approval and disapproval, of reward and punish- ment and is based on the involuntary impulse to imitate which is found in all living beings. The imitation extends to patterns of behaviour, ways of feeling, building of attitudes, organization of perception, norms of action, etc. It is, in a sense, a 'com- munication' from one generation to the next of its specific ways of living in all realms, including those pertaining to knowing, feeling or willing. The specificity of the so-called 'socialization' process with respect to the political realm is no differnet from the way it obtains with respect to other domains. The formal and informal agencies such as the family, the school, the peer group, the mass media, along with the actual experience of the

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 157 individual of those sectors of the political system with which he comes into contact, sha c both his perception of the political system and his attitude towards it. Under the circumstances, it is obvious that one would need a prior decision with respect to the question 'what does political development consist in?' in order to be able to determine what forms of socialization may be considered conducive to it. In a sense, the issue would become relevant only when the prevalent political system in a society is judged to be 'undeveloped' or 'underdeveloped'. The reason for this is that all 'socialization' basically tends to be conservative in character, as it is con- cerned with conserving through replication and perpetuation what has been achieved in the past. There may, of course, be a form of 'socialization' which tends to institutionalize innovation and experimentation, but even in such situations there is bound to be a heavy emphasis, though unstated and unacknowledged, on'the perpetuation of a stable background in the presence of which innovation and experimentation is permitted and en- couraged. The choice with respect to forms of 'socialization' is very limited, particularly as the most fundamental agency of social- ization, the family, is not particularly amenable to voluntary control. On the other hand, it does not play a very significant role in 'political socialization', though it does inculcate attitudes which may help or hinder values which are regarded as desirable for the political system. The school, the mass media and the formal and informal peer groups, specially those con" cerned with politics, may and do play a more active role in the shaping of those explicitly political attitudes which are regarded as desirable by the e'lites in charge of the political system. Yet in both cases what is desirable for the political system has to be first determined. The resort to the notion of 'political socialization' is thus of little help in throwing any independent light on the idea of political development or in providing any criterion for it. The continuity-discontinuity criterion or the homogeneity-heterogeneity criterion may be offered as indica- tors of political development, but even then it would be difficult to determine Which is to he taken as indicating development. For discontinuity clan be taken care of by the usual mechanism of role-differentiation which provides for different norms to be

158 Political Development 3

practised in different situations and heterogeneity welcomed by

seeing it as providing that healthy tension which is the har-

binger of beneficial change. Similarly.. if it be contended that

non-hierarchical, non-authoritarian practices of socialization

in the famil would be conducive to a participate ' democratic

y ry-

way of functioning of the polity, then it would not only prejudge

participatory-democratic functioning as a criterion of political

development but also entail that citizens reared in such a way

would be unfit to work in all those organizations which cannot

but be organized on the principle of hierarchical-authoritarian

control, such as the army, etc. If it be argued, on the other

hand, that the experience with respect to the, armies of demo-

cratic politics from the Athenian republic to those of the Allies

in the Second World War is a sufficient refutation of the con-

tention, then it has to be accepted also that the whole thesis

regarding socialization has to be rejected or at least drastically

revised.

The claim of 'political communication' to provide a signi-

ficant indicator of political development is perhaps even more

untenable than that of 'political socialization'. And this for the

simple reason that.it is only an instrument for the realization

of functions which may be distinctly political, but which need

not necessarily be so. As a generalized instrumentality, it is

presupposed by all activity and thus may be regarded as a

necessary condition of political development, as of any other.

Unless, therefore, some specific forms of communication are

regarded as themselves political in character, there would not

be much meaning in searching for the criterion of political

development in the field of communication. It may be con-

tended that the larger the network of communication and the

more efficiently it functions, the greater the likelihood of

the political system covering a larger area and being more

efficiently organized in the sense of being responsive to the

people whose needs it could then more easily decipher. But,

first, it is not clear why the size of a polity should be taken as a

sign of its development and, secondly, the so-called efficiency

in communication may result as much in increase of effective

tyranny as in responsiveness to the needs and wishes of the

people.

. 1 It may be suggested, however, that certain types of com-

1

1

1

1

~

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 159

munication structures can facilitate or obstruct certain types of

political development and, if so, they could serve as indirect

indicators of the possibility of finding a particular type of

political development in a society. Almond and Powell have

distinguished five types of such structures. They are: '(1) in@-

formal face-to-face contacts, which spring up more or less

independently of other social structures; (2) traditional social

structures, such as family or religious-group relationships;

(3) political "output" structures, such as legislatures and

bureaucracies; (4) political "input'@ structures, including trade

unions and similar interest groups, and political parties. and

(5) mass media.'no The list seems to consist of disparate items,

some quite heterogeneous in nature. Most refer to structures

whose primary task is other than communication per se, though

obviously no function can be exercised without involving com-

munication as well. The structures primarily concerned with

communication are those of the mass media and the crucial

question with respect to them is whether they are autonomous

or not. And in case they are formally autonomous, do they enjoy

substantive autonomy not only with respect to political interests,

but economic interests as well ?

The specifically political structures involved in the com-

munication-function mentioned by the authors relate to puliti.@

cal 'input-output' structures which we have already discussed.

There seems little point in discussing them once again in the

context of communication. The idea, however, that develop-

ments or changes in political communication in one area tend

to influence or affect political functioning in other areas is

interesting, but unless we have a clear idea as to the type of

changes that we can regard as 'developmental', little would be

gained in terms of the elucidation of the notion of 'political

development'. The authors have written that 'the performance

of political communication in a system may lead to changes in

the performance of other political functions, or may limit and

inhibit the development of certain types and levels,of system

capability."". The statement, however, is not only too general

to be of much help but also tends to suggest that it is in terms

of their'effect on a political system's capabilities that the

changes in the communication system ought to be assessed. But

as we have already seen in our detailed discussion on capabil-

160 Political Development

ities as the criterion of political development, it can hardly

provide the pivotal point in terms of which political com-

munication can function as a safe indicator of political develop-

ment. It may be urged that, depending on one's own pre-

ferences with respect to the notion of capabilities, one could

treat the extent and efficiency of political communication as @t

positive or negative indicator of the same. But indirect indica-

tors are only required where direct indicators are not available,

and this certainly is not the case with any of the criteria of

political development that have been offered, including that of

capabilities. In fact, political communication suffers from the

same defect as many other criteria discussed earlier in that one

can have too much or too little of it, implying thereby that it

is not itself an indication of political development but functions

as such only in some particular context and relationship. This

is to suggest that the criteria cannot be understood in isolation

but only in interrelationship, and this is what we propose to

discuss next.

(8) The Criteria in Interrelationship

Any such complex phenomenon as political development is

unlikely to be understood in terms of a single variable alone. It

may he contended, therefore, that our attempt to consider each

of the criteria that have been offered singly as constituting

political development has been doomed to failure from the very

start and we should not he surprised if our detailed examination

has failed to find any of them fully satisfactory. It is time, there-

fore, to examine the criteria in their interrelationship and find

if such an approach proves more helpful. In a sense, the

approach through interrelationships has not remained com-

pletely unexamined as the notion of 'capabilities' may be

deemed to be primarily interrelational in character. In fact,

the whole notion of input-output ratios mediated by conversion-

functions is interrelational in character and has been examined

and discussed in that perspective. Still, a focussed discussion on

political development in terms of an explicit relationship between

the different variables discussed in the literature is not as

superfluous as it may appear at first sight. For, even if there be

an element of repetition in the points made, the shift in the

~

~

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 161

focus may result in some new insights regarding the problem.

The criteria we have discussed uptil now in great detail

relate to those of (1) participation, (2) differentiation and

(3) capabilities. The latter has been discussed in terms of

the relation between input and output functions as explicated

by Almond and Powell in their classic formulation on the

subject. Besides these, we have also discussed in great detail

each of the conversion-functions, such as (1) Interest articula-

tion, (2) Interest aggregation, (3) Rule-making, (4) Rule-

application, and (5) Rule-adjudication. Political communica-

tion is also sometimes treated as a part of conversion-functions,

but we have discussed it separately along with political social-

ization. The relationship between participation, differentiation

and capabilities has seldom been directly discussed in the

literature. There is a generalized assumption that differentia-

tion per se leads to an increase in capability, and that participa-

tion leads to greater system-responsiveness which may be

taken as an indicator of its increased capabilities. There is,

however, a slight difference in the assumptions, in that the

latter tends to be made primarily by those who have some sort

of commitment to democracy as a political value, while the

former is unreservedly accepted by almost everyone who has

written on the subject. In fact, there are thinkers like Hunting-

ton who consider participation an adverse indicator, specially

in the case of developing politics. As the concept of political

order or political stability is more central to his thought than

that of political development, he assesses the value of political

participation in terms of its effect on political stability or order.

An increase in political participation makes increasing demands

on the political system which it finds increasingly difficult to

fulfil, thus leading to political decay rather than political devel-

opment. In his own words, 'as political participation increases,

the complexity, autonomy, adaptability, and coherence of the

society's political institutions must also increase if political

stability is to be maintained."'? But it is obvious that it is far

easier for political participation to increase than for political

institutions to increase in autonomy, adaptability and co-

herence, thus making it increasingly impossible to maintain

political order in face of increasing political participation. As

Huntington argues, 'the stability of any given polity depends

162 Political Development

upon the relationship between the level of political participa-

tion and the level of political institutionalization.1113 And

Apolitical stability, as we have argued, depends upon the ratio

of institutionalization to participation.1114 By 'political institu-

tionalization', Huntington means 'limitations on the resources

that may be employed in politics, the procedures through

which power may be acquired, and the attitudes that power

wielders may hold'."5 But as such restraints are difficult to

establish with a sudden increase in participation, the likelihood

of the emergence of what he calls 'practorian' societies is greater

in most developing societies than those he calls 'civic'.

We are not interested here in discussing Huntington's posi-

tion in detail, but it may be pointed out that he uses the term

participation' in a somewhat unclear sense. For all 'participa-

tion' does not necessarily imply making increasing demands on

the system, or making them in such a way as to lead to a break-

down of the system. Once a polity has opted for adult franchise

and free and fair elections, it has provided the sufficient condi-

tions for 'political participation'. This, however, by no means

entails that there would be such an overloading of demands on

the system that it is more likely than not to result in its break-

down. Such an eventuality is more likely to occur if 'participa-

tilon' takes the form of 'populism'. The situation might get

further aggravated if 'participation' is conceived of in terms, of

'interest articulation'. It may, of course, be argued that even in

a situation where 'populism' does not obtain, the mere com-

petition between parties for the support of the electorate would

tend to their making tall promises which would drive the polity

to disorder and ruin. But this assumes that those who are elected

try to fulfil all the promises made during elections or that the

electorate takes all the promises that are made seriously, or that

it even remembers the promises that the ruling party made at

the last election. In normal circumstances it is the overall

performance of the party in power that is judged by the elec-

torate and not the detailed, specific promises made at the last

election.

On the other hand, it might equally be contended that a too

successful institutionalization may hamper development instead

of fostering it, for the simple reason that it may purchase

stability and order at the price of growth and change. The

g@

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 163

institution of caste in Hindu society is a classic example of such

a situation. It has become so successful as a principle of social

ordering that all attempts at radical innovation based on its

denial have been doomed to failure in Indian society. In fact,

even non-Hindus in the Indian subcontinent have had to

subn.iit to this ordering principle in their soci structure, even

though it was at variance with the basic tenets of their religion.

Islarnic and Christian communities in India have found it

difficult not to come under the influence of this ordering

principle in their social structuring. A successful institutional-

ization, then, can he as inimical to development as the lack of

it, depending on the situation and the,context we are talking

about.

The relation between 'institutionalization' and 'participa-

tion' may, of course, be seen in a more dialectical manner so

that it is the tension between the two that provides the condi-

tion for development to occur. The dialectical view, of course,

may take many forms, depending upon the conception one has

of the basic forces whose antagonism and interplay is supposed

to determine the system. The Marxian version of the dialectical

approach is too well known to be, discussed here. However,

amongst non-Marxist political thinkers, Fred Riggs may be

singled out for his dialectical view of political development. In

his well-known article 'The Dialectics of Developmental Con-

flict',"6 he sees political development as a dynamic resultant of

the dialectical conflict between differentiation and integration

on the one hand, and between capacity and equality on the other.

His notion of 'capacity', however, is different from that which

is conveyed by the term Ccapabilities' in Almond and Powell's

system, though perhaps by stretching the sense, it might be

made to coincide with it to a greater extent than may appear

primafacie to be the case. For Riggs, the notion of 'capacity' is

primarily related to the desire of the rulers to preserve their

power and perhaps increase and enhance it as well. In Pact, the

'capacity-equality dichotomy'for Riggs is merely a consequence

of the 'dlite-mass dichotomy' which itself is a result of the fact

that power is not only asymmetrical in character, but also that,

by definition, 6lites cannot but be few in number and that many

of those who are not amongst the @lites would like to join and

be counted as such. As Riggs points out, 'the !bite are defined as

164 Political Development

those who exercise power, the mass as those over whom power

is exercised'. and that the so-called pressures 'manifest them-

selves through government, in the desire of rulers to preserve

their power and in the demand of the ruled to be heard and

considered . . . the typical rationalization for preserving power

by ruling @lites takes the form of capacity, and the demands of

the ruled are expressed as a quest for more equali@y.""' It is

obvious that Riggs has not expressed himself clearly, for there

does not seem any intrinsic conflict between the demand of the

ruled 'to be heard and considered' and the desire of the rulers

'to preserve their power'. The conflict would become inevitable

only if those who are ruled want themselves to become the

rulers or share in their power. The situation is insoluble in

principle if it is conceived in terms of the dichotomy of 6lite

and mass, as Riggs has done; for, by definition, the elite cannot

but be in a minority, and that too a microscopic minority in

most cases.

The impasse is sought to be bridged by Riggs through what

he calls 'differentiation', as he argues that 'this conceptualiza-

tion ... postulates a narrowing of the zone of conflict (acute

tensions) as the degree of "differentiation" rises-at least

beyond some developmental threshold'."" The term 'dif-

ferentiation' includes in itself three concepts for which, accord-

ing to Riggs, we need different terms for purposes of clarity.

They are 'role specialization within a system, effective co-

ordination of roles, and the two combined'.ng As everyone who

is familiar with Riggs's thought can guess, we are safely on our

way to a fused-prismatic-diffracted trichotomy in terms of

which the process of development is to be understood. But it

is not clear at all how 'differentiation' solves the dilemma of

'61ite-mass dichotomy' with which Riggs started his analysis.

Riggs has many interesting things to say regarding the identi-

fication of the. relationship between 'the structure, the goals of

equality and capacity, typical forms of conflict, and degrees of

,diffraction',12( but it is difficult to see how this relates to the

other, and politically more fundamental, dichotomy between

mass and 6lite, understood in terms of the ruled and the ruler

respectively.

It is necessary, therefore, to distinguish between the dialectic

imposed by the fact of differential distribution of political power

~

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 165

amongst the members of a polity and the dialectic created by

'differentiation', meaning thereby the increasing specialization

of roles within a system and the demand for some sort of

integration between them so that the system may work effi-

ciently and harmoniously to some extent and not break

asunder.

We need not pursue our discussion of Riggs' twofold

dialectic any further, particularly as we will have occasion to

revert to it later in our concluding discussion on the concept of

development and its relevance for different domains of human

endeavour. However, it may he pointed out in passing that the

basic weakness of the first dialectic relating to mass and @lite

is the assumption that political @lites are the only 6lites, and

that political power is the only power. Unfortunately for Riggs'

model, this does not happen to he the case, and though he has

theoretically conceded the possibility that power, presumably

political, may itself be the consequence of the possession of

other valued conditions,121 he has failed to draw the con-

sequences-,pf such an admission. The deeper problem, however,

relates not only to the relations between different forms and

types of power, but of their relative autonomy and indepen-

dence as well. Otherwise, one would see all values as instru-

mental to the value one holds as primary and fundamental. The

history of sociopolitical thought is replete with such examples,

and one may choose the value one happens to like or the form

of power that in one's opinion happens to possess causal

primacy over all the others.

The dialectical notion of political development is not entirely

absent from Huntington's thought either. Only, in his case

the dialectic is more between the conflicting claims of rural

and urban centres in the process of development. The crucial

factors in the drama of political development, according to him,

are the twin conditions of what he calls 'rural majority and

urban growth'. The countryside continues to be traditional

while the city becomes the centre of modernizing activity.Thus

develops what he calls the gap between the political attitudes

and behaviour of the cities and those of the countryside. The

city, however, remains constant in its function. The variable

factor in his analysis is provided only by the countryside on

whose behaviour depends whether there would be stability or

12

166 Political Develo .pment

revolution. As Huntington says, 'the role of the city is constant:

it is the permanent source of revolution'.122 However, though

the role of the countryside is crucial for political modernization,

which, for Huntington, is identical with political development,

the source for political mobilization and differential behaviour

may be said to rest primarily with the urban political 6lite,

whether they belong to the ruling group or to the opposition.

'The basic political competition', Huntington argues, 'becomes

the competition between the government and the urban re-

volutionary intelligentsia for the support of the peasantry. If

the peasantry acquiesces in and identifies with the existing

system, it furnishes that system with a stable foundation. If

it actively opposes the system, it becomes the carrier of revolu-

tion.1123

The relationship between urban and rural areas is supposed

to show four phases according to Huntington's system. In the

first phase, the countryside dominates the city socially, eco-

nomically and politically. Both, however, enjoy stability, each

at its own level. In the second phase, urban groups develop

strength and begin to challenge the rural 6lite, thus bringing,

instability into the system. In the third phase, the urban groups

overthrow the ruling rural 6lite. @ The fourth phase consists of

the induction of the rural masses into politics, which itself can

occur in four ways depending on whether the sponsors of the

'Green uprising' are (i) nationalist intellectuals,,or (ii) a section

of the urban @lite trying to overwhelm the more narrowly based

political opponents, or (iii) a rurallyorio-nted militaryjunta, or

(iv) a clique of revolutionary urban intellectuals.'124

We are not interested here in discussing in detail the ade-

quacy of Huntington's dialectical model of political develop-

ment. It should, however, be pointed out that the very terms

of the dialectic confine the theory to primarily agrarian societies

which'are being urbanized under the impact of industrializa-

tion. The unquestioned assumptions of the theory, thus, are

twofold. First, it uncritically assumes that the process of

modernization necessarily involves a continuous decrease in the

proportion of the rural sector, both in terms of the manpower

engaged in it and its relative share in the national income. And,

seconaly, there seems to be an unconscious assumption that

once the problem of rural-urban dichotomy is solved by the

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 167

swallowing up of the rural sector, political development would

finally have been achieved, as there would be no further

significant problems for the polity to solve.

Both the assumptions are naive in the extreme. The first,

though buttressed by large incontrovertible data from the

history of industrialization uptil now, runs against the increds-

ing evidence that the pattern of economic development of

large agrarian countries such as India or China cannot take

the form followed by industrialized countries in the past. Not

only this, the increasing evidence indicates that the large-scale,

capital-intensive, centralized pattern of industrialization based

on the use of non-ren@wable resources is ultimately suicidal in

nature. In plain terms, it is alleged that there are just not

enough resources to sustain a per capita world consumption at

the level which now obtains in the U.S.A. The question

obviously is not whether or not such a possibility is attainable

in the near future, but whether, given the resource estimates of

the earth, it is logically conceivable as a problem in simple

arithmetic to think that it could ever be achieved at all. There

is, of course, the on-going debate whether the notion of a finite

resource base has any meaning at all and whether we need

confine ourselves to the resources available on earth alone to

satisfy the future needs of mankind '1125 But whatever side is

taken in the debate, one cannot uncritically assume today, as

one could perhaps ten or twenty years ago, that there was

only one road to economic betterment exemplified by the

history of western nations' including that ofjapan.

Whatever one may think of the first assumption, the second

is even more fundamental and more questionable. There seems

no reason to believe that problems of political governance

cease or that political good is completely realized the moment

the rural-urban dialectic ceases to operate because of the

practical abolition of the rural sector in the economy and

society. The development of industrial and post-industrial

societies does not lessen the tasks of political management or

make the political antagonism between different classes and

groups disappear, as is known to all the political leaders of

these societies. It is therefore surprising to find Huntington

writing as if the problem of political development were pri-

marily a problem of underdeveloped countries alone, and has

168 Political Development

little to do with the so-called 'developed' societies. He may, of

course, plead in his defence that he is only concerned with the

problem of political order in changing societies and not devel-

,x)ping a generalized theory of political processes which would

be applicable to all societies at all levels of their development.

But this would be to assume that the so-called 'developed'

societies have stopped changing or that there is no problem of

political order in them. This, however, is to be blind to the

social and political facts of these countries. Huntington's book

was published in 1968 and thus, presumably, was written in

the late sixties. Yet it shows little awareness of all the social and

political turmoil prevalent in the U.S.A. during that period.

At the social plane, the period 1958-68 had seen a hundred

per cent increase in the crime rate. The comparisons with other

nations were even more alarming.1211 The Final Report of the

National Commission on the Causes and Prevention of Vio-

lence gives not only these staggering figures, but breathes an

atmosphere of hopelessness regarding the situation and wonders

if anything could really be done in the matter. The report. for

example, states, 'In the last 25 years our country has been

deluged with significant Presidential and national fact-finding

commissions, starting with President Truman's Commission to

secure these Rights in 1947.... Thus the problems of poverty,

racism and crime have been emphasized and re-emphasized,

studied and re-studied, probed and re-probed.' And, 'Surveying

the landscape littered with the unimplemented recommenda-

tions of so many previous commissions, 1 am compelled to

propose a national moratorium on any additional temporary

study commissions to probe causes of racism, or poverty. or

crime, or urban crisis. The rational response to the work of the

great commissions of recent years is not the appointment of

still more commissions to study the same problems-but rather

the prompt implementation of their many valuable recom-

mendations.11127 But even the possible hope of any such action

was remote from the minds of many persons who appeared

before the Commission. The Commission itself concluded its

Report with the following statement of Kenneth B. Clark which

may be taken as typifying the mood of the Commission: 'I

must again in candour say to you members of this commission-

it is a kind of Alice in Wonderland-with the same moving

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 169

picture reshown over and over again, the same analysis, the

same recommendations, the same inaction.11128

The political situation also was equally bad during this

period. This was the time when student protests on the cam-

puses against the Vict-Nam war increased both in intensity

and violence. Starting from the Berkeley campus of the Uni-

versity of California in 1959, they continued unabated and

spread to almost all the major campuses in the United States.

The desertions from the U.S. Army reached grave proportions,

and thousands of young men turned their draft cards over to

federal officials and announced publicly that they would not

serve.

The facts are too well known to he either repeated or docu-

mented here. What is surprising is that Huntington seems

completely unaware of them or of their relevance to what he is

writing on political order or political development in changing

societies. And he is not alone in this respect. Rather, every

writer on political development seems to be guilty of the same

amnesia. One has reluctantly to agree with Hirschmann when

he writes: 'I believe that the countries of the Third World have

become fair game for the model-builders and paradigrn-

molders to an intolerable degree."29 And, that 'Having been

proved wrong by the unfolding events in almost every instance,

the law-makers then migrated to warmer climes, that is, to the

less developed countries."30

The dialectical -model of political development, whether in

the classical version of Marx, or in that of Riggs or Huntington,

sees it primarily as a dynamic relationship between two vari-

ables alone. The moment, however, we conceive of development

as a resultant of more than two variables, the relationship

would have to be conceived in a more complex manner. One

would have to specify in detail the specific interactive linkages

between the particular values of the variables as well as the

positive and the negative feedback loops connecting them.

Basically, nothing of the sort has been attempted so far.1131 As

most thinkers in this field have tended to offer multiple criteria,

it is imperative that this aspect should not have been left

unattended to. Further, as the relationship between the criteria

that have been offered has generally been viewed inversely, it

was even more incumbent on the authors to indicate the rela-

170 Political Development

tive weightage of the values involved if a viablejudgnient about

political development were to be regarded as feasible,. Lucian

Pye, for example, has remarked that 'historically the tendency

has usually been that there are acute tensions between the

demands for equality, the requirements for capacity, and the

processes of greater differentiatioil. Pressure for greater equality

can challenge the capacity of the system, and differentiation

can reduce equality by stressing the importance of quality and

specialized knowledge."32 But if there are such acute tensions

between equality, capacity and differentiation, each of which

is regarded, severally and jointly, as the criterion of political

development, then it is necessary that the problem of propor-

tions and priorities between them be faced and settled. Yet

Lucian Pye has done nothing of the kind. One is given no

indication as to how much weightage is to be given to each.and

what exactly is to be the plus-minus equation between such

incompatible criteria. The same can be said of many of the

'conversion-functions' which also display an inverse relation-

ship, between them. Take, for example, 'interest articulation'.

and "Interest aggregation'. It is obvious that the more we have

of the former, the more difficult it would be to achieve the

latter. Any increase in the quantity and diversity of interests

would make it increasingly difficult to achieve.'aggregation' in

the sense of 'reconciliation' of divergent interests.

Sirffilarly, if we take 'rule-making, 'rule-application', and

'rffle-adjudication' together into consideration, we see that an

increase in the quantity and complexity of the first leads to

increasing difficulties at the level of both 'rule-application' and

'rule-adjudication'. The more the rules enacted, the more

difficult it becomes to see that they are properly observed and

that the conflicts between them are expeditiously adjudicated.

In fact, the possible conflicts between rules, both actual and

imagined, may be expected to increase in a geometrical ratio,

making it almost impossible for the ad udicating function to be

reasonably exercised by finite human beings. In a sense, such a

situation is already being approached in many countries where

cases demanding adjudication lie for years without proper

attention on the part of adjudicating authorities.

It may be suggested that if the relationship is of such an

inverse character, the best course to ensure efficient 'rule-

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 171

application' or 'rule-adjudication' would he to go slow on 'rule-

making'. It would then be in the direction of reduction and

simplification of rules that political development will be sought

rather than otherwise. But, however seemingly sensible this

may appear in the case of 'rule-making', it may not even appear

to be so in the case of 'interest articulation'. It will be difficult

for anyone to argue that,it is best for 'interest articulation' to

he lessened so that difficulties may not arise in the way of

'interest aggregation'. Perhaps, the difficulty may be met by

thinking of a moving equilibrium between the quantities on

the inverse side of the relationship in such a way that the

opportunities for an increase in 'interest articulation', or in

'rule-making' are only provided when there is a chance of

their being 'aggregated', or 'applied' and 'adjudicated'.

Theoretically, the idea may seem logically impeccable even

if it be conceded that in practice it is almost impossible to

realize. But besides the issue of empirical unrealizability there

is the ethical problem of the desirability of doing so. just as it

is ethically unacceptable that the opportunities for 'interest

articulation' be reduced only because the polity is not able to

aggregate the interests articulated, so also it may appear ethic-

ally unacceptable that an increase in such opportunities be

withheld just because the polity is not able to increase its

capacity to aggregate them. There may perhaps be an asym-

metry in the two situations, as a restriction of opportunities

which already exist may seem morally more reprehensible than

a failure to provide more opportunities for expression of

'interest articulation'.

The difficulties, however, may be regarded as confined not

merely to the empirical and the moral levels, but to extend to

the theoretical dimension also. The equilibrium ratio, whether

moving or not, is expected to be unity if it is to count as

indicating political development. But in such a situation there

can hardly be any development, for the indicator would always

stand at unity, provided the situation is satisfactory. The

difficulty may be avoided by treating unity as an ideal limit

which is never actualized in practice because of the empirical

limitations inherent in the situation. and treating development

as a movement towards it. Any two ratios at different moments

of time would then be compared in terms of their approxima-

172 Political Development

tiori to the ideal ratio given by unity and judged as political

decline- or development according to whether it is farther from

or nearer it. One may also think of the logical possibility that

'interest aggregation' may exceed 'interest articulation' and

that 'rule-application' and 'rule-ad udication' may exceed

'rule-making'. Such a situation may be described as 'over-

development', in case there are no intrinsic incom,patibilities'iin

the concepts of such a nature that any ratio indicating more

than unity is ruled out by the very nature of the concepts con-

cerned.

A primafacie analysis does appear to suggest this in the case

of 'interest aggregation' and 'interest articulation', for it seems

meaningless to talk about aggregating interests which have not

been articulated by any group or class of persons. The only

way out of the difficulty would perhaps be to formulate the

concept of 'anticipated interest' which, then, could allow being

aggregated even in the absence of any explicit articulation. But,

in that case, the problem would arise whether the so-called

'anticipated interest' coincides with the interest of the person

or groups if they were to articulate their interests. The notion

of 'anticipated interest' has, in fact, occurred in the classical

literature of political science under the guise of what is called

great interests', The distinction between 'real' and 'apparent'

interests, however, undercuts the notion of 'articulated interests'

as it implies that people are not the best judges of what they

really want. It is only the @lite which knows what is best for

everybody. And, in most cases, the @lite is supposed to be the

political 6ite only. The history of this notion is well known

from Plato onwards, and has been helpful to dictators of all

hues injustifying their authority which, according to them, has

always been exercised for the achievement of the public good.

Whatever the difficulties with respect to the possibility of

'interest aggregation' exceeding 'interest articulation', there

seem hardly any regarding the possibility of 'rule-adjudication'

exceeding 'rule-making', as the possible disputes that may arise

with respect to the rules made is always larger than the rules

themselves. Even here, however, both the number and the

wording of the rules would have a direct relationship with the

number of disputes that may arise requiring adjudication. The

larger the number of rules, the greater the possibility of the

The Criterion as Conversion Functions 173

disputes arising with respect to them. On the other hand, the

wording of the rules may be such as either to encourage or

discourage disputes about them, depending on the ambiguity

inherent in the formulation itself. But even when the rules are

formulated in as clear and precise a manner as possible, what

Hart has called 'the open texture of law' would ensure the

necessity of adjudication, as no law, in principle, can anticipate

or provide for all the complex situations that may actually

arise in life. There is, therefore,-always a likelihood of rule-

adjudication cases being larger than the rules that are made,

though it cannot be denied that the larger the number of rules

that are enacted, the more will be the occasions that would

arise requiring adjudication with respect to them.

We may conclude, therefore, that the interrelationship

between the criteria has hardly been the subject of any serious

consideration or discussion by the authors who have offered

them. Even the awareness that the relation between criteria

may be antagonistic in character has hardly resulted in any

attempt at answering the question as to how, in such a situation,

we could possibly determine whether any such thing as political

development has actually occurred or not. Whenever, for ex-

ample, a plurality of criteria are offered in any field, the first

question that has to be raised is whether they are to be treated

as independent of one another or not. Yet, even this preliminary

question has not been raised in the literature in any focal

manner, for it is obvious that in case they are not to be treated

as independent, then not only has it to be specified which of

the criteria offered are independent and which are not, but

it also has to he explained why, if some are not independent,

they have to be included in the list at all. Further, in case

more than one criteria is offered and each held as independent,

it is incumbent on the thinker who is proposing the criteria to

indicate what weightage has to be given to the various criteria

in order to reach a total assessment of the situation. For, unless

some such summation is done, no judgement will be achieved

regarding the polity as to whether development has occurred or

not. Yet, this problem of weightage has hardly been touched

upon in the literature on the subject. It could perhaps be con-

tended that no fixed weightage can be given to the criteria, as

it varies with varying situations. There are situations when

174 . Political Development

participation' may be given a greater weight as an indicator of

'political development', while in some other set of circumstances

it is 'capabilities' that may have to be given greater weight' But

then, one has to indicate the sort of circumstances which made

a difference to the weightage to be given to a. particular

criterion and the reason or reasons why it has to be so. Yet

there is little in the literature that is helpful towards answering

such questions, or which even indicates the awareness that they

have to be answered if the quest for the criteria of 'political

development' is to have any meaning at all.

The search for the understanding of 'political development'

in terms of the interrelationships between the criteria seems to

have ended as much in a blind alley as the search for the indi-

vidual criteria in earlier chapters. There seems to be something

fundamentally wrong with the whole enterprise if none of the

criteria offered, either singly or in interrelationship, can with-

stand a sustained exarm'nation of their adequacy. Perhaps some-

thing is radically wrong with the notion of 'development' itself

or with the notion as applied to the field of 'politics'. In the

former case, the troubles will lie- at the very root and make the

whole enterprise untenable in any domain whatsoever. On the

other hand, if difficulties arise from the domain of the 'political',

it would indicate limitations for the applicability of the concept

and suggest its irrelevance for all domains which shared the

characteristics of the realm of the 'political'. We will try to

explore this issue in the next chapter.

NOTES

1. Almond and Powell, Comparative Politics, p. 73

2. Ibid." p. 73.

3. Ibid., p. 74.

4. Ibid.

5. Ibid. Italics author's.

@6. Ibid., p. 75.

7. Ibid.

8. Ibid., p. 76.

9. Ibid., p. 77.

10. Ibid., p. 76.

11. Ibid., p. 81. Italics author's.

The Criterion as Conversion Functions

175

12. Ibid., p. 81.

13. Ibid.

14. Ibid., p. 82.

15. Ibid., p. 80.

16. Ibid., p. 167

17. Ibid., p. 82.

18. Ibid., P. 86.

19. Ibid., p. 87.

20. Suzanne and Lloyd Rudolph, The Modetni@y of Tradition (Chicago: University

of Chicago Press, 1967).

21. Almond and Powell, p. 89.

22. Ibid.

23. Ibid., p. 98. Italics mine.

24. Ibid., p. 99.

25. Ibid.

26. Ibid., p. 100. Italics mine.

27. Ibid., p. 105 '

28. Ibid., p. 98. Italics mine.

29. Daniel Bell, The Coming of Post-Industrial Sock@y (New Delhi: Arnold Heine-

inann, 1974).

30. Almond and Powell, p. 100. Italics mine.

31. Ibid'., p. 101.

32. Ibid., p. 1 1 1. -

33. Ibid., p. 108.

34. Ibid.

35. Ibid.

36. Ibid.

37. Ibid., p. 109. Italics mine.

38. Ibid. Italics mine.

39. Ibid.

40. Ibid., p. 112. Italics mine.

41. Ibid., p. 113.

.42. Ibid., p. 114.

43. Ibid., p. 1 10.

44. Ibid., p. 107.

45. Ibid., p. 114.

46. Ibid., p. 100.

47. Ibid., p. 98.

48. Ibid., p. 134.

49. Ibid., p. 136.

50. Ibid., p. 132. Italics mine.

51. Ibid., p. 138. Italics mine.

52. Ibid., p. 140. Italics mine.

53. Ibid., p. 105.

54. Ibid.

55. Benjamin N. Cardozo, The ivature of Me Judidal Process (New Haven: Yale

University Press, 192 1).

56. Ibid., p. 142.

176 Political Development

57. Ibid., pp. 143-4.

58. Ibid., p. 144.

59. Ibid., p. 86.

60. Ibid., p. 108.

61. Louis Dumont, Homo Hierarchinu (London: Weiderfeld & Nicholson Ltd.,

1970).

62. Herbert A. Simon, Administrative Behaviour (New York: Maemillan, 1957).

63. Talcott Panons, Structure and Process in Modern Societies (Glencoe, Illinois.. Free

Press, 1960).

64. Lloyd 1. Rudolph and Susanne Hoeber Rudolph, Modern and Traditional

Administration Reexamined: A Revisionist Interpretation of Weber on Bureaucracy.

International Political Science Association IX World Congress, 31 Aug.

1973. Mirneographed copy, p. 46.

65. Almond and Powell, p. 153. Italics mine.

66. Ibid., p. 156.

67. Ibid., p. 158.

68. Ibid., p. 154.

69. Ibid., p. 155.

70. Ibid., p. 153.

71. Ibid., p. 157.

72. Ibid., p. 155.

73. Ibid., p. 158. Italics mine.

74. Ibid., p. 156. Italics mine.

75. Ibid., p. 149.

76. Ibid. I Wics mine.

77. Merle Fainsod, quoted in Almond and PowcH, P. 150

78. Almond and Powell, p. 150.

79. Ibid., p. 151.

80. Ibid., p. 152.

81. Ibid.

82. Ibid., p. 150.

83. Ibid., p. 151.

84. Lucian Pye, Aspects of Political Development (Boston: Little, Brown & Co.),

P. 118.

85. Ibid.

86. Ibid.

87. Ibid., p. 121.

88. Ibid.

89. Harvard Law Review, vol. 7 1, no. 4, Feb. 1958.

90. Lon L. Fuller, 'Positivism and Fidelity to Law. A Reply to Professor Hart',

Harvard Law Review, vol. 7 1, no. 4, Feb. 1958, p. 644.

91. H. L. A. Hart, Law, Liberty and Morality (London: Oxford University Press,

1963), and Patrick Devlin, The Enforcemmt of Morals (Oxford University

Press, 1965).

92. Hart, p. 1 1.

93. Ibid., p. 16.

94. Benjamin N. Cardozo, 7-he ivature of the _7udicial Process (New Haven . Yale

University Press, 1964).

95. Hart, p. 61 1.

96. Fuller, p. 664.

97. For Hart-Fuller controversy, see also Hart, The Concept of Law (London:

Oxford University Press, 1961), and Fuller, T7te Morality of Law (New

Haven. Yale University Press, 1964).

98. Fuller, P. 635.

99. Fuller, P. 635.

100. Lucian W. Pye and Sidney Verba (eds.), Political Culture and Political Develop-

ment (Prinecton. Prinecton University Pren, 1969), p. 13.

101. Ibid., p. 15.

102. Ibid., p. 521. Italics mine.

,103. Ibid.

104. Ibid., p. 22.

105. Sidney Verba, p. 527.

106. Ibid., p. 537. Italics author's.

107. Ibid.

108. Almond and Powell, p. 62. Italics author's.

109. Ibid., p. 53.

110. Ibid., p. 167.

Ill. Ibid., p. 172.

112. Samuel P. Huntington, Political Order In Changing Societies (New Haven - Yale

University Press, 1968), p. 79.

113. Ibid., p. 79.

114. Ibid.

115. Ibid., p. 83.

116. Fred W. Riggs, 'The Dialectics of Developmental Conflict', Comparative.

Political Studies, 1 (July 1968).

117. Ibid., pp. 202-3.

118. Ibid., p. 205

1 19. Ibid., p. 206

120. Ibid., p. 208

121. Fred W. Riggs, 'Power plays a critical role in relation to all such values, as

a possible consequence of, and as a possible means for securing, the valued

conditions', ibid., p. 203.

122. Ibid., p. 292.

123. Ibid., p. 293.

124. Lester M. Salmon, 'Comparative History and the Theory of Modernization',

World Politics, vol. XXIII, no. 1 (Oct. 1970), pp. 83-103. Contains a good

summary and discussion of the views of Black, Huntington and Moore.

125. Donella H. Meadows, Denis L. Meadows, jorgen Randers and Williain

W. Behrens Ill, The Limits to Growth (New York. Universe Books, 1972).

Also see Mesarovicetal., Mankindat the TumingPoint (New York.. E. P. Dutton

and Reader's Digest Press, 1974). See the debate in Forum (University of

Houston), vol. XIII, nos. 1 and 2, 1975. Also Hernian Kahn, Williain

Brown and Loon Martel, The ivext 200 k'ears (New York.. William Morrow

& Co., 1976).

126. The Final Report of the National Committee on the Causes and Prevention

of Violence (Bantam, U.S.A., 1970). The comparative figures for 1966 in

The Criterion as Conversion Functions

177

178 . Political Development

respect of some other countries as given in the report per 100,000 of the

population are:

1. Australia 1.5

2. Canada 1.3

3. England & Wales 0.7

4. Finland 2.3

5. Austria 1.1

6. Hungary 1.9

As against these the crime rate in U.S.A. per 100,000 of population happened

to be 3.0 in 1966.

127. Ibid., p. 99.

128. Ibid., pp. 99-100.

129. Albert 0. Hirschmann,'The Search for Paradigms as a Hindrance to Under-

standing', World Politics, April 1970, p. 335.

130. Ibid.

131. An interesting attempt in this regard is that of Ronald D. Brunner and Gary

D. Brewer, Organised Coinplexi@y (The Free Press, 197 1). But it tends to accept

the rural-urban paradigm of Huntington as the only framework of analysis

relevant for the study of political phenomena.

132. Pye, p. 147.

179

5

The Concept of Development

In the detailed examination that we have undertaken, the

failure of the criteria, both individually and in interrelation-

ship, suggests that there might he something wrong either with

the notion of 'development' itself or the field ofpolities to which

it may not be relevantly applicable. The feeling of failure, it

might be added, is not confined just to us. After more than a

decade-and-a-half of discussion by the best brains in political

science we find Charles Tilly asking in the latest volume of the

Prinecton series on the subject, 'Are these difficulties sur-

mountable?'and answering, 'For my part, 1 do not think the

difficulties are surmountable." But if the difficulties are not

surmountable, it can only be so because in principle it is

impossible to do so. But if it is impossible in principle, then the

whole enterprise is doomed to failure from the very start, and

it is no wonder that we have not been able to bind any sure

footing amongst any of the criteria 'that have been offered by

many thinkers. Yet even so, it is incumbent on someone who

argues for the impossibility to show from where the impossibi-

lity arises. And as we have observed earlier, the impossibility

may arise from two very different sources, the one relating to

the concept of development itself, the other relating to the

nature of political reality, to which the concept of development

may not be applicable.

But whatever the alternative source from which the im-

possibility may be said to arise, the primary task would require

an analysis of the concept of development without which neither

the first nor the second alternative would make any sense. The

concept of development, thus, may be said to be crucial to the

whole enterprise and unless we are clear about it, we would not

be able to know the cause of our failure in finding a viable

criterion of 'political development'.

NT

180 Political Development

'Development', it would be agreed, is essentially an evalua-

tive concept. In most contexts, its use expresses a positive

evaluation, and thus, unless otherwise stated, it should he

interpreted as such. Also, it is comparative in character. To talk

of development is to compare two stages of the same entity at

diff@rent moments of time or to compare two different entities

in respect of some characteristic which is regarded not only as

common to both but also as characterizing them in the same

essential manner. Besides t@ese, it may also be said that the

notion of 'development', to be relevantly applicable, must also

contain the possibility of indefinite extension in the sense that

there should, in principle, be no last term beyond which it is

not possible of being conceived any further. In other words,

there should be no terniinus to 'development', in the sense that

the very possibility of all further development be impossible in

principle.

Besides this, what is perhaps even more necessary is that

there should be some unambiguous way of adding the positive

indicators and subtracting the negative so that it may be clear

whether development has actually occurred or not. For this, it

is necessary that some common measure be possible in terms of

which the various indicators may he compared and evaluated.

This, however, itself requires as a logical prerequisite that there

be a clarity about the value or values that are immanent to the

domain, and in terms of which the question of development or

decay is said to arise. In case there is only a single value which

defines the realm, the situation may not give rise to any specific

difficulty. But in case there is more than one value inherent to

the domain, they may not be necessarily harmonious in them-

selves, or the means for their realization may be such as to be

antagonistic in character in the sense that the very adoption of

the means for the realization of one value makes it difficult to

adopt the means for the realization of the other value, or even

works directly against its realization.

The issues with respect to'the identity of the unit or units

which are being compared have been pointed out by Tilly in

his remarks on the formation of nation-states in Western Europe

in the book referred to above. Most writers on development

choose as their units of comparison the contemporary nation-

states as they exist at present. But, as is well known, most of the

The Concept of Development 181

present nation-states did not exist in the past or had different

boundaries from their present ones. The history of nineteenth-

century Europe is well known in this regard and the effect of

the two World Wars on the political map of the world is too

familiar to he repeated here. As Tilly remarks, 'the choice of

contemporary states as units for the long-run comparison of

"political development" causes grave difficulties'.2 He takes

Germany as a typical example, whose frontiers have been fluid

since, say, 1550 to 1950. But if the fact of changing frontiers over

periods of time is taken seriously, then Tilly suggests that 'such

a literature seems unlikely to yield statements about the condi-

tions under which a given political structure will disintegrate,

stagnate, combine with others, or transform itself into a variety

which has never been seen before'.3

Tilly's remarks have been made in the context of political

development, but it is obvious that as 'development' is a com-

parative term, the problem of the constancy of the unit of com-

parison would arise with respect to its application to any field

whatsoever. And that where the unit is primarily defined in

spatial or geographical terms which are liable to change over

a period of time, the difficulties of making a comparative

judgement may he remedied, if at all, by taking into account or

making allowances for this factor. Some may go even so far as

to treat territorial expansion as a sign of development in realms

where it is relevant, and its contraction as a sign of degeneration

or decay. The imperial expansions of states in the past through

diplomacy, conquest or matrimony were always treated as

times of growth and glory by historians of various persuasions.

There have, of course, been exceptions like Marx or Toynbee

who, in their different ways, have refused to accept the age of

expansions as a sign of development. Rather, they see it as a

sign of inherent weakness at the centre which tries to mask its

failures by aggrandizement abroad.

Yet, whether territorial expansion is treated as a sign of

development or not, it is obvious that the notion will be relevant

only in those cases to which spatial categories apply and where

they are regarded as the essence of the matter. Many realms

with respect to which questions of development arise may have

nothing to do with questions of space, and even when they

must have a location, it is not taken to define their identity.

13

182 Political Development

The problem of identity in relation to the unity of units with

reference to which comparison is made has been extensively

discussed by Toynbee and Sorokin. Toynbee has.raised the

issue in relation to the study of history and Sorokin in relation

to his study of social and cultural dynamics. Toynbee finds his

unit of comparison in what he calls a 'civilization' which has

both a spatio-temporal spread and an identity of style in its

various cultural manifestations which attempted to embody a

distinctive vision of values, rooted generally in the successful

response of a society to some supreme challenge ,,vhich meets

with such notable success that it seeks to repeat it again and

again, even when it ceases to be adequate and leads to break-

down and disintegration.

Toynbee has wavered in his conception of the criterion of

unity in terms of which one civilization may be distinguished

and demarcated from another for purposes of comparison. On

the one hand, he tries to find them in those empirical 'cut-off

points' where that which is responsible for the birth of a

civilization is simultaneously the cause of the death of some

other civilization. The relation, lie calls, 'apparentation-alnd-

affiliation'. And, its clearest example he finds in Christianity,

which simultaneously lies at the root of modern western civiliza-

tion and is one of the most important causes of the break-up of

the Greco-Roman civilization of earlier times. Christianity,

however, is not only the cause of the death of one civilization,

and the birth of another, but also one of the higher religions

which give meaning and significance not, only to human life

and history but to the world of temporality itself. In this sense,

the unity provided by Toynbee would have to be conceived in

terms of meaning, significance or value whose basic' exempli-

fications are found in the higher religions.

However, neither the relation of 'apparentation-and-affilia-

tion' nor the valuational vision embodied in the higher religions

can provide that 'cut-off' point in all cases for the simple reaso 1n

that according to Toynbee himself, there are civilizations which

are not 'apparented' or 'affiliated' or both to any other civiliza-

tion and that 'higher religions' are not found in all civilizations.

One will, therefore, have to go beyond the specificities singled

out and emphasized by, Toynbee and seek the demar@atine

principle of unity in some other causal-fanctional or valuational

The Concept of Development 183

principle in the case of those civilizations where the specificities

mentioned by him do not obtain. Sorokin, in fact, has enum-

crated the principles in terms of which different forms of

unities may be treated either as given or constructed. Besides

the unities provided by such natural demareators as space and

time which provide, so to say, only external unities, there are.

according to Sorokin, unities provided by causal-functional

and logico-mcaningful factors. The latter are obviously more

internal and intrinsic, as the principles providing them are more

integral to the objects concerned. The causal-function'al unities

are relative. to the scientific knowledge of a period, while the-

logico-mcaningful unities may be regarded as relative to the

value-apprehension of an observer. The objectivity, therefore,

An their case' is relative to the shared knowledge of a period or

@the shared value-apprehension of a people. However, the

s as we approach individual works

ophy which are regarded by Sorokin

les of logico-mcanin-eful unities, or

relatively segregated, quantitatively measurable, indefinitely

repeatable, individual causal sequences which are well known

in so many areas of science. The functional unities,in the same

way, are more clearly and unambiguously exhibited in indivi-

dual organisms which may be taken as their paradigmatic

examples. But the moment we move to larger and larger units,

the so-called unities become increasingly problematic and

relative in character. The unities of whole civilizations as

apprehended by a Toynbee, a Spengler or a Sorokin have been

the subject of great controversy, as is well known to students of

the subject.4

However, it would hardly be denied that the criteria for

unity have to be specified first so that relevant conipargtive

judgement about development could be possible. After all, the

first question is: what is it to which the characteristic of 'devel-

opment' is being predicated or applied? Similarly, though

'development' is not just 'change', it presupposes it in an

essential manner. 'To develop' is 'to have changed', though 'to

change' does not necessarily mean 'to have developed'. Hence,

it is equally necessary that we determine not only that to which

'change' is being ascribed but also the respect in which it is

supposed to have changed. 1 have discussed at length in my

184 Political Development

earlier work, Considerations Towards a Theo7 of Social Change,,5

many theoretical and conceptual issues relating to 'unity' and

'change', and hence need not repeat theni here. Suffice, it to

say that, whatever be the criterion adopted for demarcation of

the units for purposes of comparison, they should not only be

explicitly indicated, but also held constant for the duration of

the discourse. The requirement may appear elementary and even

a prerequisite for intellectual integrity and honesty, but even

a cursory glance at the literature reveals that it is conspicuous

by its absence. The complaint of Charles Tilly quoted earlier

makes sense only in such a background. He writes, 'the Europe

of 1500 included sonic five hundred more or less independent

political units, the Europe of 1900 about twenty-five. The

Gernian State did not exist in 1500, or even 1800."' If such is

the situation, there can be little surprise that 'the choice of

contemporary states as units for the long run comparison of

"political development" causes grave difficulties.'7 This is, of

course, an understatement, or rather a polite way of saying that

the whole exercise does not make any selise, as the units chosen

for comparison cannot be compared in principle.

What is even worse, however, is the persistent attempt to

compare. the performance of the newly emergent states of Asia

and Africa with those of western countries, not with what they

did at comparative stages of their emergence and growth but as

they are now in contemporary times. Further, the growth-

performance of the newly emergent nations is usually treated

as a purely autonomous function of their ruling 6lites, and not

as a complex resultant of their past colonial history combined

with the realities of the power situation in the international

world around them. The exception to this are, of course, the

so-called leftist thinkers who derive their inspiration from

Lenin's extension of Marxist thought to cover the imperialist

phase in the development of capitalism. They are quick to

point out that the political and economic development of the

new nations is both hampered and distorted by the inter-

national structures of domination and exploitation built by the

advanced capitalist countries of the world. But they. con-

veniently forget the fact that the nation-states of eastern Europe

are as much, if not more, under the thraldom of Soviet domina-

tion as the so-called direct or indirect client-states of the

The Conce .pt of Development 185

western superpowers. As Tilly specifically states in answer to

the question he himself raises, 'what, then, do we have to learn

from the literature of dependency and exploitation? First, the

recognition that the nature of the international structure of

power, and the relations of particular countries to that struc-

iure, account for a major part of the form, change, and varia-

tion of the national economic lives of poor countries; there is

no obvious reason why that should be less true of political

Besides the problems relating to the unity of the units being

compared, there is the deeper problem relating to the units

themselves. In case the comparison is merely quantitative, few

problems arise. But the moment questions of quality arise,

difficulties begin to' pile up. The usual way out. is to correlate

quality to that which can be quantitatively measured, and

thus to avoid the dilemma of making direct qualitative judge-

ments and justifying them. But where such a quantitative cor-

relation is not possible for some reason or other, one is reduced

to making comparisons based on long familiarity with the

field, the training of taste under those who have cultivated

judgement in the matter and developing a sensitive openness

to that which may emerge with creative novelty in the domain.

The history of art criticism is a standing example of this situa-

tion where all attempts to do away with the direct qualitative

judgement of the connoisseur have failed.

The notion of 'development', however, does not merely

involve a comparative judgement in terms of quality, but also

what might be called a direction of growth. Interpreted in

terms of quality, this can only mean approximation towards an

ideal which is more and more visible in its successive embodi-

ments. The ideal, of course, is itself apprehended only through

,its concrete embodiments and is, so to say, a construct out of

them. Yet, as it is never exhausted by its concrete embodi-

ments, it is difficult to understand it completely in terms of the

notion of 'logical. construction', unless logical constructions

themselves begin to be seen as acquiring independence from

those examples out of which they have been constructed. The

dilemma whether to conceive of that which has been ap@-

prel-iended through, or abstracted from, experience, as indepen-

dent of or unexhausted by it, is ia,ell known to students of

186 Political Development

philosophy since the days of Plato and Aristotle. The dilemma

was solved by Plato through formulating his famous theory of

remembrance which asserted that experience was merely the

occasion of reminding one of that of which one was already

aware in the past, when one was presumed to be directly aware

of the world of Ideas themselves. Such a way out is obviously

closed to the scientific student of phenomena, though he may

perhaps get some leeway by using the Kantlan notion of a

transcendental presupposition, or of Weber's notion of an Ideal

Type, or even the generalized idea of a heuristic device to use

it effectively for his own purposes.

The problem, however, gets a little more complicated by the

fact that we do not merely talk of the growth of a style, but of

its exhaustion also. It has repeatedly been asserted, specially

by historians of art and literature, that any particular style,

say, the renaissance, the baroque or the rococo emerges, grows

and reaches its maturity after which there is only repetition,

stagnation and decay. A master is supposed to exhaust the

potentialities of a language or the medium in at least one

dimension of its development, and after that there are only the

epigoni or the epigoni of the epigoni, till a new master arises

and blazes the trail in a fresh direction, when the same story

repeats itself once again. The@ idea has been extended to the

field of civilizations and cultures, and it has been contended

thatjust as there is a genesis and growth of civilization, so also

there is a decline and decay which can hardly'be arrested for

the simple reason that they have exhausted their potentialities

by actualizing what they were ca pable of actualizing in the

course of their history. Spengler's name is most associated with

this view, but no one who has reflected on the history of any

people has been able to escape the impression that creative

heights are achieved in only very brief periods and that too in

certain select directions. After that, there seem to be only the

valleys, stretching out in space and time, where men remember

and repeat that which was achieved for once and all by the old

masters.

The history of creativity in cultures and civilizations, thus,

shows a double facet. On the one hand, it reveals the exhaustion.

of possibilities in a particular direction after Ns@hich there is only

repetition, perhaps refinement, but no further gros@,th or devel-

The Concept of Development 187

oprnent. On the other hand, there seem breakthroughs in new

directions which achieve a different kind of perfection or ex-

cellence than the one achieved before. This may be achieved in

the same culture when there is an awareness of past achieve-

nient and of the break with it, or in a different culture at a

different place or time where no such awareness may exist, or,

even where it exists, there is no feeling of break with it as it does

not form part of the consciousness of the tradition within which

one works.

The concepts of growth and development, thus, appear to

find their natural application in the case of the former, though

they tend to be extended to apply to the latter also. Only, the

extension always appears forced and seems to demand a

justification which seldom is forthcoming and, even when

forthcoming, appears to be rarely satisfactory. The history of

art provides a classic example of such dilemmas. One may, for

example, reasonably maintain that the Parthenon is the cul-

mination of Greek architecture and its greatest achievement,

but how should it be judged in relation to the masterpieces of

renaissance architecture which were built with a feeling of

self-conscious continuity with the Greek past, however mistaken

it might have been? This remains a difficult and debated

question. The comparison of Greek or renaissance master-

pieces with those that are known as Gothic raises problems of

even a more perplexing kind. The two seem so different in

form, spirit and composition that one wonders if anything is

gained by the comparison, except the awareness of a difference

in achieved excellence or greatness. But, whatever the diffi-

culties, they still belong to a tradition whose historic continuity

with each other can be documented and traced. On the other

hand, any attempt at comparison with the masterpieces- of a

historically different tradition, say, that of India or China,

would create even greater difficulties. How shall we determine

which is greater or more developed, and in terms of what? The

simultaneous awareness of the achievements of different times

and cultures seems simultaneously to challenge one to compare

and also frustrate the attempt to do so.

The same situation obtains in the realm of religion also. How

shall t one compare , he great religions, each of which claims

both absoluteness and finality, es@en in terms of history? Who

188 - Political Developme@it

shall determine which is better or more developed, and on

what grounds? The attempt at intercultural comparison leads

to the search for transcultural criteria in terms of which a con,-

parative evaluation may be made. But to talk of transcultural

criteria is to talk of universal standards in terms of which not

only may everything be judged, but which may also be treated

as an ideal which everything is trying to approximate and

realize to some extent or other. The radical difference in the

case of historical religions in this respect is that they make the.

claim that the ideal has already been completely and finally

realized and that every religion before and after it can be

judged in terms of it. Yet, the very fact that the dream of an

oecumenical religion acceptable to all has vanished from the

minds of the most optimistic votaries of any religion has resulted

in a situation where, however deeply one might be convinced

of the superiority of one's own religion, one cannot but be

aware that others think differently and that one has to live

with these differences.

The situation is found in the field of art also, though not

perhaps to the same extent. There are persons who think that

the art they are familiar with is the only art worthy of being

called by that name, and that the art of all other civilizations

and cultures should be judged in terms of it. Greek and re-

naissance art were put on that pedestal by western art critics

at one ti,.,ne, though the parochialness of that view has long

been exposed by now. Yet, this exposure has been brought

about by that very encounter with the arts of diverse cultures

and civilizations which, in the first instance, had resulted in the

almost total rejection of everything alien as 'barbaric', 'un-

civilized', "underdeveloped'. The first impulse at. rejection

gradually gave way to the feeling of 'alternative validity', and

still later to a search for those universal excellences of form

which are the creators of real aesthetic value, apart from the

specific content which may be said to vary from one civilization

to another.

The practitioners of art, on the other hand, have perhaps

always been less parochial than the so-called connoisseurs

and critics. They have always tended to incorporate from an

alien tradition what they thought could successfully be blended

with their, own. There may appear here a certain'difference

The Concept of Development 189

with the religious practitioner who usually tends to be more

Drthodox and dogmatic in his preferences. All religions have

had the notions of 'heresy' and 'heretics, but it will be difficult

to find their counterpart amongst practitioners of art, where

creative novelty has always been prized over dull repetition.

Still, the encounter between different religions, specially those

that are regarded as 'major' or 'great', has not been without

influence because of the awareness of each on the part of the

others. The mutual interaction in India between Islam and

Hinduism on the one hand, and Hinduism and Christianity on

the other, may be seen as examples of the truth of this assertion.

The emergence of e notion of Christian Sanyasa in such

Jesuit Fathers in southern India as Father Mochanin and Le

Saux, as well as the various reforniist movements in Hinduism

under the influence of Christianity in the late eighteenth and

early nineteenth centuries, starting with Ram Mohun Roy, are

all evidence of such interaction. Earlier, the interaction between

Islam and Hinduism in India had given rise to many sects in

both the religions which were frankly syncretistic in character.

Similar examples could easily be found from encounters

between other religions also. Yet, though examples can be

found of mutual modification and influence in the field of

religion, tl-iey certainly seem less numerous than in other fields

such as art or philosophy or science. And this may perhaps be

because the deepest identification of man uptil now in history

has been with his religion rather than with anything else.

However it be, it is clear that the concept of developn-ient

does not seem to be equally relevant to all domaiiis in which it

may be sought to be applied. The cases of art and religion we

have already examined to some extent. They may. however, be

regarded as relating to realms of feeling and emotion where

ultimately everything may be considered a matter of taste. But

the situation in philosophy, which at leastprimafacie is supposed

to be the rational cognitive enterprise par excellence, seems no

different. If one were, to ask oneself the question whether there

has been any development in philosophy or not, one would be

hard put to answer it either way. Whitchead's well-known

remark about all philosophy being footnotes to Plato epitomizes

this feeling. Similar is the feeling expressed by the equally well-

knowledge that in philosophy one is either a Platonist or an

190 Political Development

Aristotelian. Yet, there is also the repeated spectacle of 1

philosopher starting de novo on foundations which appear to him

not only firmer and surer,' but unassailable in principle. Also,

there have been recent. claims for showing the 'nonsensical'

character of most previous philosophy as the cognitive claims

it made were unverifiable in principle. On the other hand,

there are even more recent claims of the inalienability of

metaphysics and a revival of interest in on 'tology. But, however

different these claims and counter-claims may b.e, they all add

up to the same thing. And that is the denial' of cumulative

growth or development in philosophical knowledge. The

repeated search for absolute beginnings shows this as clearly as

anything could. Also, how could one take seriously the claims

to growth and development in a subject whose practitioners

seriously state the literally 'nonsensical' character of almost all

its achievement in the past?

.Philosophical knowledge, then, seems to share with art and

religion the dubious distinction of being resistant to the facile

application of the notion of development to its domain. The

answer to the simple question, 'what is the status of a past

achievement in the face of the present one?', may be taken as a

rough indication of the applicability ofthe notion of 'develop-

ment' relevantly to a domain. But philosophy is a domain

where, like art or religion, the latter does not necessarily sup-

plant the former. A Plato or a Kant remains as relevant to

philosophical thought as a Russell or a Wittgenstein. True, no

problem in philosophy remains the same after the shock

administered by a great thinker, but the latter never replaces

the former. The contrast with natural sciences in this context is

revealing in the extreme. A student of physics is not only not

bothered about the physics of Aristotle or even that of Newton

today, but he knows that he shall not gain anything worthwhile

with respect to the knowledge of physical phenomena by any

such knowledge. A philosopher, on the other -hand, could never

say such a thing. The history of philosophy is not an accidental

adjunct to the teaching or understanding of philosophy. Rather,

it is central to it, as was so well understood by Hegel and per-

haps, in d sense, by Aristotle also. The tradition of developing

philosophical thought by the method of writing commentaries

on an older text in India evinces perhaps the same situation.

The Concept of DeveloPment 191

The contrast between philosophy and the natural sciences in

respect of the development of knowledge is too glaring to be

missed by anybody. In fact, it has led many to doubt if philo-

sophy could legitimately be regarded as an instance of know-

ledge at all. But what about the social sciences? A nagging

doubt seems to haunt the social sciences that however much

they try to be 'scientific', they do not become 'sciences' at all.

There seems to be no feeling of cumulative growth of know-

ledge, which is a feature of the natural sciences. There are, of

course, radical differences between the various social sciences in

this regard. Economies, demography and linguistics appear to

be closer to 'the ideal of achieving some sort of cumulative

growth of knowledge in their fields. But, whatever the indivi-

dual differences in this regard between the different social

sciences, there seems little doubt that they are regarded as

belonging to the cognitive domain or as a part of the cognitive

enterprise of man.

There is a peculiarity regarding the application of the, notion

of 'development' to these fields which, unless clearly under-

stood,, may give rise to ambiguities and perplexities that are

difficult to resolve. The concept of 'development' in many

fields may be applied either to phenomena belonging to the

field itself or to the knowledge about the phenomena or both.

One may, for example, legitimately talk about economic de-vel-

opment, meaning thereby the rise in national or per capita

income, or more egalitarian distribution of income or any

other criterion or set of criteria that one may choose to adopt.

On the other hand, one may equally w@ll talk of developments

in the-field of economic theory or in the methods of collecting

economic data or in that of their interpretation. The two,

however, are independent of each other and refer to different

domains which should not be confused with each other. There

can, in fact, be advances in economic theory along with sub-

stantial retardation in economic development, judged by any

of the criteria that are usually adopted for measuring the,

phenomenon.

A similar situation obtains in almost all the social sciences

and disciplines relating to the humanities, as the phenomena

they study have themselves a qualitative aspect because of

vhich it is impossible _not to apply to. them the adjectives

192 Political bevelopment

'better' and 'worse'. Such a situation, on the other hand, does

not obtain with respect to the phenomena studied in the natural

sciences. There does not seem any sense in applying the terms

.'developed', 'undeveloped's or 'underdeveloped' to the sort of

phenomena studied in, say, physics or chemistry or astronomy.

The situation may seem a little ambiguous within the realm of

phenomena studied by the life sciences. Can the concept of

'development" be relevantly applied to the emergence of new

species, or the adjectives 'better' and 'worse'. to what we find

happening in the field of phenomena pertaining to life? The

emergence of life may be regarded as valuable in that it provides

both the precondition for the application of the value-judgment

and the actual application of its occasion as well. Still, without

the emergence of reflective self-consciousness in man, the

phenomena of life would only provide the potentiality fo@ such

occurrence, and not its actuality. And, in case the potentiality

itself is taken into account, the whole set of physical and chem-

ical preconditions necessary. for the emergence of life would

have to be treated as events to which the idea of 'development'

would be regarded as relevantly applicable. Man, in that case,

would become the measure of all things, and the process leading

to him, whether at the physical, chen-dcal or biological level,

would be treated as 'developmental'. Within humanity, one

could then choose one's own religion 'or culture or nation as

providing the measuring rod in terms of which historical devel-

opment could be traced and others placed at a suitable location

on the line of development depending on their relative distance

from that which has been taken as therneasure of development.

The ethnocentric and parochial character of the latter exer-

cise is known to most thinkers, and we have already seen its

untenability in the realm of art, religion and philosophy in our

earlier discussion of them. In the earlier discussion on evolu-

tion, we made the same point that the distinction between 'more

developed' and 'less developed' is difficult to draw amongst

different species except in terms of survival which, excluding

those that have become extinct, each species manages to

achieve. The question whether any notion of 'development'

can escape the charge of parochialism or ethnocentrism is too

difficult to be decided with finality here. But what can be said

with reasonable certainty is, (1) that.the notion of 'develop-

The Concept of Development 193

inent' is only derivatively applicable, if at all, to the, realm of

the inorganic; (2) that within the realm of 'living beings', the

application of the notion is primarily projective, in the

sense that it is the qualities regarded as desirable amongst

human beings or for the achievement of their purposes which

are projected on to the animal world in considering. them

'developed' or not; (3) that while the concepts of 'growth' and

'development' arise naturally in the context of human life in

all its myriad manifestations, it does not apply with equal

relevance to all the fields which emerge because of human

interaction and creativity. In fact, if there are to be any struc-

tural parameters of the human condition, then it may be

regarded as axiomatic that there are some constraints in the

situation in respect of which any use of the notion of develop-

ment makes no sense. But if it is so, then it becomes imperative

that such areas be clearly demarcated so that the range of

expectancy in relation to them may not go beyond bounds

and feed on impossible illusions. Even for sheer ontological

equality, it is necessary that in some respects at least not only

all individuals, but all societies be the same or rather find them-

selves in the same situation. The privilege of being the latter

should not confer advantages in all domains; just as for those

whose philosophy of history makes them see it as a continuous

decline from some golden past, it should not be seen as con-

ferring disadvantages only on those who, through no fault of

their own, happen to live in a later period. To put it in other

words, the sheer passage of time should not be treated in such

a way as to confer uniform advantages or disadvantages on all

domains of human effort and endeavour.

Robert Nisbet has discussed some of these issues in great

detail and exposes the difficulties inherent in the notion of

change when 'it is made subject to the fundamental concepts- of

developmentalism'. 9 In the last chapter entitled 'Reflections on

a Metaphor', he suggests that 'the usefulness of the metaphor

of'growth is determined by the cognitive distance of the object to

which the metaphor is applied. The larger, the more general,

abstract, and distant in experience the object of our interest,

the greater the utility of the metaphor. Conversely, the smaller,

more concrete, finite, and empirical our object, the less the

metaphor's utility."0'The relevance and utility of the metaphor

~

194 Political Development

of growth are in dire-et proportion to the cognitive distance of

the subject to which the metaphor is applied.... The less the

cognitive distance, the less the relevance and utility of the

metaphor. In other words, the more concrete, empirical, and

behavioural our subject matter, the less the applicability to

it of the theory of development and its several conceptual

elements."' And, as reality is that which is concrete and

empirical, the concepts of growth and development cannot be

applied to it. In case the attempt is made'to apply them under

the mistaken impression that they are so applicable, as many

social scientists have attempted to do, it can only lead to

disaster. Basically, it is a metaphor derived from organic pro-

cesses which, if taken seriously and applied to the social realm,

would lead to a distorted understanding of their nature. It

would be what he has called the abuse of i metaphor, for

basically it is irrelevant to the phenomena to which it is being

applied,12 In fact, even in the realm of the organic, the meta-

phor can only be relevantly applied to the individual and not

to the species, though Nisbet does not seem quite clear about it.

However, Nisbet has accepted the uses of the metaphor. He

has no doubt that it is applicable to processes in the abstract,

specially when they are supposed to cover a vast, large field

which is distant from the concerns of our immediate interests.

One wonders how Nisbet conceives of th c relation between the

abstract and the concrete in the field of knowledge. It is obvious

that he cannot bifurcate the two in such a manner as to have

absolutely no relation with each other. The purpose of the

abstract formulation is to illuminate the concrete, just as the

use of the concrete is to test the ad@'quacy or validity of the

abstract formulation. If the metaphor is irrelevant to'concrete

phenomena, it is equally irrelevant to the abstract formulation;

and if it is held to be relevantly applicable to the latter, then

it cannot be entirely irrelevant to the former. The issue is

important, for Nisbet seems to be assuming that the concrete

can be understood without the help of the abstract, which is

contrary to the history of understanding in any field. Further,

he seems to have a strange notion of the abstract, in that he

thinks that any entity that is too large to be apprehended by

some immediate intuition ether sensuous or

,@ @vh otherwise, can-

not be regarded as concrete or empirical in character. While

The Concept of Development 195

discussing Lynn Thorndike's History of Civilization, Nisbet

points out that 'we are dealing with an abstract entity given

body by attributes drawn from a score of civilizations-

technology, arts, agriculture, writing, philosophy, fine arts,

etc. and the historically concrete civilizations are used only as

periodic incarnations, as it were, of the single entity, civiliza-

tion. We are not studying, not really, despite appearances, the

Egyptians, Greeks, Chinese, Romans,' and other peoples. We

are studying Civilization in its successive and fleeting resting

places in Egypt, Greece, China and elsewhere.".' One may be

led from this to assume that Nisbet would at least grant

historical concreteness to such civilizations as the Egyptian,

the Greek, the Roman or the Chinese. But, basically, he seems

averse to such an acceptance; though, to be more accurate, it

n-iight be said that he fluctuates in his attitude and at least

positively rejects it in the sense in which an metaphor of

y '

growth or decline could be,relevantly predicated of it. He says

'we should feel lost, most of us, without the accustomed civiliza-

tion-one of Spengler's eight, one of Toynbee's twenty-one

civilizations-that came into being (genesis), that matured to

fullness (development orgrowth), that in time suffered decay

through forces endemic in Roman polity and culture, and then

withered and perished, fit consequence for Rome's never having

cured itself of the diseases to which it fell heir in middle age."4

The irony is obvious, but perhaps it is even more ironic that

the same Nisbet, who waxes so eloquent about the abuses and

irrelevance in the application of the metaphors of growth and

decay to the study of societies, himself succumbs to it in his

book Twilight of Authori@y. The adverse judgment on Spengler,

Toynbee and others for their gross misuse of metaphor is

almost reversed. It is strange to find the author asking, 'Has

the West, in each of its nations, reached by now the condition

prophesied by these and other n-tinds of the past?' and answer-

ing, 'There is much reason to believe so, and it would require

a totally closed mind to be insensitive to the increase at the

present time in forebodings of the future.".' He feels it enlighten-

ing to compare the present age with what 'Sir Gilbert.Murray

found in another of history's twilight ages, the age of social

disintegration and militarism that followed the Peloponnesian

wars in ancient Greece and the consequent breakdown of the

196 Political Development

Athe&ian Polis'.16 The 'repudiation of the political state and of

the wlhc)le Pattern of thinking that has been associated with the

state for more than two centuries' on the part of modern youth

is supposed to have an illuminating parallel in Greece where

,the , breakdown of the Ale-xendrian Empire ... was associated

with the eruption of numerous otherworldly, often frankly

irrationalist, faithsl.17 The inevitability of the use of the meta-

phors of.growtl-i, development and decay in a comparative

conte@l.t seenis thus as transparent here as it could possibly be.

Nisbef, for all his fulminations against the comparative method

and tihe abuse of the metaphor in the writings of Rostow,l"

Levy,@9 Smelser,2(1 and Parsons,21 himself appears to succumb

to the same temptations, albeit half a decade later. .

HO,@vevcr, the deeper point made by Nisbet in his earlier

book is the contention that unless some sort of an immanent

telos i@ Posited for societies or civilizations, the so-called notions

of g'ro'@ th and development or of decline and decay cannot be

applied to them. And it is his firm conviction that any impartial

look @at the evidence which history provides does not sub-

stanti@Lte any such contention. On the contrary, history, ac-

cordidg to hirn, supports just the opposite conclusion. Change

is, generally, the result of an external intrusion, something

which cannot but be treated as 'accidental' from the internal

viewpoint Of the system concerned. According to him: 'change

is, ho@vever@ not "natural," not normal, much less ubiquitous

and c(nstant. FiXity iS.122 'If we were Newtonians we could say

with lgewton that "every body continues in its state of rest, or

of uniform motion in a straight line, unless it is compelled to

change thatstate by forces impressed upon it".'2" Change is, of

course, not to be confused with 'mere motion, activity, move-

ment, interaction'.24 'These, beyond any doubt, are constant and

ubiqu@tOus.-13ut none of them, as a moment's thought tells us,

is synonymous with change.125 Any change which can be con-

sidere(i Of notable significance, 'is intermittent rather than

continuous niutational, even explosive, rather than the simple

accun@ulatioil of internal variational And, such a significant

change 'is overwhelmingly the result of non-developmental

factors; that is to say, factors inseparable from external events and

intMSi@nS'.27

Basically, the notion of change in the context of the theories

The Concept of Development 197

of development involves the related concepts of immanence,

'Continuity. directionality, necessity, and uniforrnitarianism

without which it could hardly be stated, far less developed in

any detail. But history as an account of concrete events fixedly

anchored in specific space and time does not provide any

evidence, according to Nisbet, of the meaningful applicability

of such concepts. As he argues, 'the language of history ad-

mittedly is not to be converted into the language of develop-

mentalism with its hoary concepts and premises of immanence,

continuity, directionality, necessity, and uniformitarianism.'28

And this is so,. for 'there is no historical evidence that macro-changes in

time are the cumulative results ofsmall-scale, linear micro-changes.'29

The dilemma posed by Nisbet seems too forced to be accepted

unreservedly. That the concepts of growth and development

cannot be relevantly applied to any field whatsoever, seems

an over-reaction to the unabashed claims of its unrestricted

application. True, there seems little justification for the un-

limited application of the notions of immanence, continuity,

directionality, necessity and uniforrnitarianism which go to

form what may be called 'the development syndrome'. But to

argue that the application of the constellation of these concepts

is impossible in principle would be to argue that they are self-

contradictory in nature, for without that it is difficult to see how

the contention could possibly he maintained. Yet, there is

nothing logically self-contradictory about them. At least Nisbet

has not shown that it is so. But even on the historical plane, his

argument does not appear to be as well-grounded as h c thinks.

It is not true to say that over short periods of concrete historical

time, we do not apprehend mutual interaction which is

primarily internal to the system. The development in philoso-

phical thought f@om Thales to Aristotle in -a -ncient Greece 'or

from Kant to Hegel in Germany may be given as one example

of this. Developments in science from Galileo onwards, or in

distinct domains of art in, say, the renaissance or nineteenth-

century France could be treated as other examples. And, even

if one were not to accept these as correct examples of growth or

development, one could find others in these or other domains,

for surely no one believes that all- human creations are of the

same Borders or that they have no relation@ to each other.

Simildrly, it is e-qually wrong for Nisbet to think that 'the

14

198 Political Development

larger, the more general, abstract, and distant in experience

the object of our interest,. the greater the utility of 'the meta-

phor,.30 But as we have shown in some detail, this is not true.

In the fields of religion, morality, art and philosophy there is

not much impression of growth or development when we

apprehend things in the longer, and the larger, perspective.

True, even in those short centuries of actual history when

growth is. undeniable in a particular field, it does not reveal

itself as either immanent or necessary except to.a retrospective

glance which may reconstruct the story in terms of those con-

cepts. On the other hand, there is a continuity and direction-

ality without which no notion of growth or development would

be applicable. As for uniforrrfitarianism it is applicable only in

the comparative context when it is argued that there are

similar stages in the growth or evolution of different societies or

cultures. The concepts enumerated by Nisbet have thus to he

differentiated, for while some of them may be regarded as

intrinsic to the notion of growth and development, others are

required only for a particular variety of the theory of history

which tries to interpret the diverse, multifarious phenomena

from a certain perspective only.

Whenever, therefore, we find continuity, and directionality

we may talk of growth or development, provided We have a

positive attitude towards the direction which the process is

taking.* However, even when such a situation obtains, the

prediction may take two very different forms. In one, the move-

ment is from a negative state to a positive one which itself can

be completely realized. In the other form, the positive state

functions more as an ideal which may be approximated but

never actualized. The classic example- of the former is the

movement from disease to health; there are myriad ways of

being ill, but there is only one way of being healthy. Also, one

cannot be more or less healthy, though one may say loosely

that one is more or less ill, implying thereby either the severity

The Concept of Development 199

of the illness concerned or its distance from possible fatal con-

sequences for the person concerned. The closest analogy to the

situation with respect to health may be found in 'winning',

where also one cannot win more or less, as one either wins or

fails to win. There is, of course, the radical difference that

'winning' has a finality about it which 'being healthy' does

not. A game that has been won can ndver, be lost, but one may

lose the health one has gained almost the very next moment.

On the other hand, there are ideals which one never seems

to actualize, or rather, which can never be actualized but only

more or less'approximated, though even to talk of 'approxima-

tion' in their case is unwarranted as one knows them chiefly in

the negative sense of dissatisfaction with 'what is', rather than

positively as apprehension of 'what ought to be'. In their case,

the notion of development implies a movement from positive

to positive in an unending series where the latter generally

seems to embody more of the positive than the earlier. This, of

course, need not necessarily be the case as there may be stagna-

tion or decline in the sense that either nothing new has been

added, and there is only, a repetition of what was achieved

earlier, or even a.loss through extraneous processes interfering

with the transmission to new generations of what was earlier

achieved by the culture. The latter, of course, may interfere

with transmission in all domains, for it is a characteristic of all

that is culturally acquired that, unless transmitted from one

generation to another, it may lapse into complete oblivion

incapable of being resuscitated by later generations even if

they wish to do so. 1

There is, however, a sharp difference even in this realm of

ideals which can never be completely actualized and which

thus provides the possibility of indefinite development to man

in many fields of his activities in which he engages both indi-

vidually and collectively in the course of history. There are

'lms which do not permit of the application of the notion of

rea

cumulative growth where the latter builds on the earlier and

includes it as an integral part of itself. The seeking in many of

these realms may be rather to break away from.the past, to get

rid of it and to create something new having little relation to

what has gone before, or even an express repudiation of it. Art,

religion, morality and philosophy are almost paradigmatic

* It is not being denied that there are 'non-yaluational' and even 'dis-valua-

tional' uses of the term, but they are of little relevance to the issue we are discussing.

In the former case, only the Quantitative aspect is being emphasized, while in the

latter, there is a directionality, though in the negative direction. 'Growth in POPU-

lation' may be taken as an example of the former, while the 'growth of a tumour'

or the, 'progress of a disease' exemplifies the latter.

200 Political Development

examples of such realms and we have already discussed them

in detail earlier. The poin't here is that in these doma ns what

appears later in time does not supplant the one' that was

achieved earlier. Rather, the two together reveal the infinite

inexhaustibility of the realm, instead of any unilinear growth

towards an ideal where the latter may be taken as a closer

approximation, for it contains within itself not only the"truth

of all that has gone before, but goes beyond it.also.

The oh jection may he made that the contrast we are drawing

cannot be sustained by a closer examination of the situation. To

the historian's eye, the situation is never as discontinuous as we

have tried to make it out to be. After all the techniques once

discovered or values once apprehended or the solutions once

proposed become as much a part of the patrimony of ma;ikind

which later generations are necessarily heir to, and which they

may use in any way they like. On tl-ic other hand, the so-called

incremental, cumulative model of growth where the latter

inevitably contains the truth of the earlier and is in this sense

the truer, has come in for serious questioning even in the realm

of scientific knowledge which was regarded as the paradigmatic

example of the continuous, linear, cumulative, developmental

model. Kiihn's attack on the models' may be said to have

demolished at least the so-called self-evident character of the

assumption. However, the debate that has followed Kuhn's

ideas shows that while it is true that there are predominant

paradigms of explanation at any one period in the history of

science, and that scientists are not easily willing to give up

their theories even in the-face of facts that seemingly disprove

them, the distinction between,'normal' and 'revolutionary'

science is not very tenable. Not only is there no such thing as

an exclusive paradigm of explanation at any stage in the history

of science but even after revolutionary change in the so-called

'paradigms of explanation', the facts which were explained by

the former theories are explained by the, newer ones also.3? In

other words, the theories still retain commensurate compar-

ability, and the earlier never stands alongside the latter as

demanding cognitive allegiance, except as a creation of the

human mind in which context it becomes more like a work of

an as @a 'tool for discovering the. truth about ' ific

art th a spec

domain, which all cognitive theory purports to be.

The Concept of Development 201

The question, thus, is not of continuity or discontinuity, of

sudden revolutionary breaks or of imperceptible incremental

growth, but of the status of the earlier achievement after the

latter has come into being. Has it to be necessarily superseded

or has the earlier to be subsumed under the latter, or can the

two stand side by side without involving either of the alterna-

tives? There can be little doubt that there are substantial

differences in this respect between different realms,. and that

the cognitive enterprise in the field of science is the example

par excellence of the situation where the latter necessarily claims

to supersede.the former and, if accepted, actually does so.

We need not labour any further in establishing the contention

that the concept of development is not equally applicable to

all realms of human seeking, whether cognitive or otherwise.

The crucial question which therefore remains to be answered

is whether the realm dealt with by the science of politics is of

such a nature as to permit the application of the concept of

'development' to itself. And our answer to this question is in

the negative,-for the simple reason that the only relevant dis-

tinction here is -between 'good government' and 'bad govern-

ment', and not 'between' a 'developed polity' and an 'un-

developed polity', as many contemporary political scientists

seem to think. And though it is difficult to say that there are

not 'varieties of goodness' or even 'more or less of goodness',

Socrates was perhaps not wrong in the Platonic dialogues when

he denied both. Perhaps 'the body politic' is really like 'the

body' which has a thousand ways of being ill, but only one way

of being healthy. Analogies may deceive, but they may illumine

as well. And 1 see no reason why the analogy with individual

health need be regarded as'more misleading than illuminating.

In fact, in a recent discussion Fred Riggs has taken recourse to

the same analogy, though he has chosen to draw different

conclusions from it. He observes that 'if,we compare health

with development, then we can see that a balance of height

and weight is a consideration-even an important considera-

tion in determining health'.33 He, of course, explicitly warns..

'my thinking about the prismatic model and the relation of

differentiation to integration, is, not derived from the body

metaphor just used, but perhaps the metaphor can appro-

priately be employed to show that we are dealing with different

gm

@A

Oi@

1

202 Political Development

variables, and none of them imply unilinearity or irreversibi-

lity.'34 True, but there is a deeper dissimilarity with the

metaphor in that the concept of development does not seem

applicable to health except in the indirect sense of reducing

illness, creating institutional mechanisms for its prevention and

cure, and increasing longevity.

In this article, Riggs has tried to meet the objections 1 had

raised in the course of the debate and attempted to clarify

further h is own notion of 'political development'. It may,

therefore, not be entirely irrelevant to discuss his final position

as stated in this paper. He suggests that the word 'development'

in the political context be confined to connote 'an increasing

ability to make and carry out collective decisions affecting the

environment (not the context)'.35 The crucial concepts i@ the

definition are those of 'collective decision', 'environment', and

'context'. As the distinction between 'environment' and 'con-

text' is crucial to this new move in the definition of 'political

development', we may devote some time to its clari cation.

The ecological dimension which the term 'environment' intro-

duces in considerations of political decision-making requires

that 'both the cultural and the human environment need to

be added to the physical environment in order to form an

adequate picture of the ecology of politicalladministrative

action.'313 But while it is necessary to include 'cultural and

human environment in the concept of "environment", it is

equall necessary to exclude from its definition all other social

,Y

systems with which it interacts,' for they are what is meant by

the term 'context'.37 Clarifying the notion of 'context' further

by providing specific examples, Riggs observes, 'thus the

context of nation-states is the international system. Within

India, the context of Rajasthan is other Indian States, and

the context ofjaipur is-other Indian cities.'38

But, if taken scriousl' the examples would make nonsense

yy

of the distinction between 'context' and 'environment' on

which Riggs' whole argument rests. If every 'social system'

with which one interacts is to be included in the 'context', it

is difficult to see how anything except the hare physical en-

vironmen't can be excluded from it, for surely it is not the

contention of Riggs that there could 'be 'cultural or human

environment' which was not anchored in a social system. One

The Concept of Development 203

could also argue@ conversely, that there can hardly be a social

system without human or cultural components. But this would

be, to accept the contention. that the distinction between 'con-

text', and 'environment' on which Riggs' whole argument is

built@ is untenable at its very foundations. It could perhaps be

saved by treating it as an analytic distinction which applies to

all institutions having on one side thefunction of power which

they have to exercise vis-b.-vis all other institutions for pur-

poses of survival and growth, along with the other aspect which

Riggs has called the capacity of 'self-determination'. In his

own words,.'My view of development, accordingly, is that it

involves a growing understanding of both constraints and

resources of the environment. Moreover, and this is often the

critical element in development, a society may choose to do

things that change its environment so as to reduce the c ement

of constraint and increase the element of resources, thereby

expanding its own capacity to make decisions that will enlarge

the scope of its own sej-determination.'311 And he makes it clear

that 'the relation between a system and its context is governed

by '.'power", not by levels of development'. 40

It is not, howc.ver, quit6 clear what will be gained by treating

the distinction as analytic rather than substantive in character.

Power relations are involved everywhere, and they themselves

are determined by that capacity of decision-making and self-

determination which are considered by Riggs as the distinctive

characteristics of the development of a,polity. Riggs seems to

have an unstated metaphysical belief that any real increase in

the capacity of 'self-determination' or 'effective decision-

making' on the part of a polity would not result in its domina-

tion over, or aggrandizement and exploitation of other polities.

He is, of course, vaguely aware that it may not be so. He almost

concedes as much when he writes that 'this is not to say that

development and aggrandizement are unrelated to each other.

A, developing country may, certainly, choose to enhance its

military capabilities and use them to subject and exploit others.'

But he salves his conscience by calling such a possibility. a

negative' development,." little realizing that it completely

undermines the, unbridgeable divide between 'context' and

'environment'pn which he built the whole edifice of his argu-

rnent in reply to my criticism. To introduce the .-notions of

1

-1

1

~

g@

204 Political Development

'positive' and 'negative' development and to correlate them

with 'environment' and 'context', is to go counter not only to

the radical distinction between the latter on which the hard

core, of his argument rested, but also to that neutral definition

of development with which he started his clarification, when

lie wrote: 'I think it is helpful to use the word "development"

for a kind of change that can be clearly identified, but which

one may approve or disapprove of for vari.ous-reasons-it may

combine beneficial with harmful consequences; and it may

affect some more favourably than others.'42 And, 'to use the

word "development" for a decision-making capability is there-

fore to recognize differences in values and goals-it is not to

accord any particular output of decision-makii@g (such as economic

growth) the honor of serving as a criterion for development'. 43

But if no particular output can be given such honour, why

should we call one type of development 'positive' and the

other 'negative', or one 'responsible' and the other 'irrespon-

sible'? Riggs has made both the distinctions and thus succumbed

to the same temptation which he accuses others of succumbing

to, that is, to make the concept of 'development' value-loaded

rather than value-neutral

We have already alluded to the former distinction while

discussing his attempt at distinguishing between 'context' and

'environment'. The latter distinction he makes in the,context

of whether the collective decisions taken by a society take into

account their long-run consequences on the environment or

not. As he says, 'not to consider the long-run consequences of

the impact on one's environment of the decisions taken by a

society is to manifest irresponsible development; to adapt one's

policies affecting environmental transformations to the long-

term requirements of survival is to engage in responsible devel-

opment.'44 One wonders how Riggs would characterize collec-

tive decisions taken by a polity Which ignore the consequences

on its 'context', whether short-term or long-term, and how he

would distinguish between those that ignore only the long-term

consequences and take into account only those that are short-

term. It would perhaps be still more inconvenient to ask how

short is the short-term and how long the long-term for decisions

to be characterized as 'responsible' or 'irresponsible'. To raise

these questions is not only to reveal the irresponsibly casual

The Concept of Development 205

way in which Riggs has made distinctions, but also to show

the utter untenability of his attempt to provide a formal notion

of 'political development' which would steer clear of all the

pitfalls pointed out in my critique of his earlier formulations. 45

It appears then that the concept of development has not

only to be positively value-laden for it to be interesting to

thinkers for application to social phenomena, but also that it

has to be buttressed by 'premises of immanence, continuity,

directionality, necessity, and uniformitarianism',46 which most

thinkers find extremely questionable. Besides these, what is

perhaps even more important for the application of the concept

is the requirement that the specific field of its application be

defined by a value which is of such a nature that it can possibly

be realized through a process of infinite, additive accretion

which can be computed through some common measure in

terms of which the concerned value may find its quantitative

correlate for measurement. The realm of the political, along

with many others, does not seem defined by any such value and

hence, as we have shown in detail in all these pages, the concept

of 'Political development'. is not a viable concept for the study

of political phenomena. The criteria that have been offered

uptil now have been shown to be untenable, and there can be

little hope of finding any unless it be first established that the

value or values sought to be realized in the field of politics are

of such a nature as to permit not only asymptotic growth but

the devising of a common measure in terms of which that growth

may be measured. Till such time as this is established, the

search for criteria is bound to be fruitless; and there are reasons

to think that, if the arguments advanced in the course of this

book have any validity, the situation is irremediable not only

as a matter of fact, but in principle. This, hoWdVet. need be no

cause for despondency for, as we have shown in this last

chapter, the same situation prevails in many other areas which

are not only dear to the human heart, but which may even be

said to make man more distinctively human.

~

A

~

1, l@

4A

206

1. Charles Tilly (ed.), The Formation of National States in Western Europe (Princeton:

Prinecton University Press, 1975), pp. 619-20.

2. Ibid., p. 618.

3. Ibid., p. 615.

4. An interesting critique of the repeated attempts to find a common spirit

between different works of art is found in Ren@ Wellek's, 'The Parallelism

between Literature and the Arts', a'lccture delivered at The English Institute,

and printed in W. K. Wimsatt (ed.), Literap Criticis;n-idea and Act (Berkeley..

University of California Press, 1974).

5. Daya Krishna, Considerations Towards a Theory of Social Change (Bombay:

Manaktalas, 1965). See specially chapters V & VI, pp.. 103-57.

6. Tilly, p. 15.

7. Ibid.,, p. 618.

8. Ibid., p. 630.

9. Robert A. Nisbet, Social Change and History (London: Oxford University Press,

1969), p. V-U-.

10. Ibid., p. 241. Italics author's.

11. Ibid., p. 267.

12. Ibid.> pp. 251, 267.

13. Ibid., p. 245. Italics author's.'

14. Ibid., p. 249.

15. Robert Nisbet, Twilight of Authority (New York: Oxford University Press,

1975), p. 8.

16. Ibid., p. 9.

17. Ibid., p. 1 1.

18. Nisbet, Social Change and History, pp. 253-6.

19. Ibid., pp. 256-9.

20. Ibid., pp. 259-62.

21. Ibid., pp. 262-6.

22. Ibid., p. 270. Italics author's.

23. Ibid., p. 270.

24. Ibid., p. 27f.

25. Ibid., pp. 271-2. Italics author's.

26. Ibid., pp. 281-2.

27. Ibid., p. 280. Italics mine.

28. Ibid., p. 203.

29. Ibid., p. 288. Italics author's.

30. Ibid., p. 241.

31. Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific &volutions (Chicago: University of

Chicago Press, 1962).

32. Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge

(Cambridge.. Cambridge University Press, 1970). See also, Brian Easlec,

Liberation and the Air@u of Science (London. Chatto & Windus, 1973).

33. Fred W. Riggs, 'Further considerations on "Development"-A Comment. on

Daya Krishna's comment', A .dministrative Change, vol. 4, no. 1 (July-Dec. 76),

p. 8. Also, see the whole. controversy in Adrninistratim Change, vol. 1, no. 2

Political Development

NOTES

n

Tize ConPept of Development

207

(Dec. 1973); vol. 11, no. 1 (June 1974); vol. 11, no. 2 and vol. Ill, no. 2.

34. Ibid., p. 8.

35. Ibid., p. 2.

36. Ibid., p. 4.

37. Ibid., p. 6.

38. Ibid.

39. Ibid., p. 5. Italics mine.

40@. Ibid., p. 6.

41. Riggs, 'But when it uses its growing capacity in this way, it manifests "nega-

tive", not "positive", development', p. 6.

42. Ibid., p. 2.

@3. Ibid., p. 3. Italics mine.

44. Ibid., p. 5.. Italics author's.

45. Daya Krishna, 'Shall we be diffracted?@A critical comment. on Fred Rigg@'s

"Prismatic Societies and Public Administratior@"', Administrative Change, vol. 11,

no. 1 and 'Towards a saner view of "Development" ', vol. 3, no. 2.

46. Robert Nisbet, Social Change and History, p. 303.

cl

1

g@

~

1@@7@G

~

End of Book

................
................

In order to avoid copyright disputes, this page is only a partial summary.

Google Online Preview   Download