PDF Max Weber'S Conception of Covenant in Ancient Judaism, With ...
[Pages:17]MAX WEBER'S CONCEPTION OF COVENANT INANCIENT JUDAISM, WITH REFERENCE TO THE BOOK OF
JUDGES
Alan Mittleman
Max Weber provided an importantmethodological toolfor the modernstudyoftheJewishpolitical tradition:a predominantlysocio
political analysis of Israelite covenants. Yet in emphasizing a func tional analysis of covenanting, Weber problematized covenant as a
theologicalconcept.Arriving at an appropriatebalance ofpolitical
and theological elements in the analysis and interpretation of cov
enant is crucial to any adequate account of the Jewishpolitical
tradition. This essay offers an explication ofWeber's views, a contem
porarycritiqueof thembyJuliusGuttmann,whowas sensitiveto the methodologicalproblem,and a challenge tofuturewriting on the Jewishpolitical tradition.
JewishPolitical StudiesReview 6:1-2 (Spring 1994) 9
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.216 on Tue, 27 Nov 2012 03:30:02 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
10
Alan Mittleman
Weber's Contribution toOur Understanding of Jewish Political Traditions
Max Weber (1864-1920) may seem at first an unlikely con
tributor toward our modern understanding of the political tra
ditions of the Jewish people. A product of the nineteenth century
German university, Weber partook of its many prejudices to
ward and preconceptions about the Jews.While not an antisemite,
neither was Weber a pluralist. He believed that Jewish identity
in the modern world was a traditionalistic anomaly which had
no real place in the German nation-state. The problem of the
Jewish "pariah people," a term he did much to popularize, was
to be solved through radical assimilation. In views such as this,
Weber was of a piece with the entirety of the liberal movement
inWilhelmian Germany.1
In addition to his negative judgment on the viability of
Jewish identity in his own time, Weber drew, in his scholarly
study of ancient Judaism, from the German tradition of "higher
criticism," principally from the work of Julius Wellhausen
and
Eduard Meyer. In our time, the methods and theses of higher
criticism are much in doubt. Weber's indebtedness to this schol
arship circumscribes his contemporary relevance. In its own
epoch, higher criticism was founded on several assumptions
that may properly be labelled anti-Judaic
(though not
antisemitic). Influenced by both classical Christian theology and
its recent secular incarnation, Hegelian immanentist-evolution
ary thought, Wellhausen,
for example, saw in the history of
ancient Israel a proto-evangelium.
Israelite history moved to
ward an anticipation
(by the literary prophets) of an inner
freedom and a moral universalism
fully realized only by Chris
tianity. Israel itself foundered on the narrow shoals of priestly
ritualism and nationalistic
self-centeredness.
The immanent
dynamic of the Israelite spirit, badly misunderstood by Israel
itself, lay dormant until the rise of Christianity. InWellhausen's
source-critical view, the priestly corpus represented by Leviticus
is the last stage in the evolution/devolution
of Israelite religion.
Rabbinic Judaism, denominated
"late Judaism," is a fossilized
extension of the sterile priestly religion into which Judaism had
degenerated.2
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.216 on Tue, 27 Nov 2012 03:30:02 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Max Weber's Conception ofCovenant inAncient Judaism
11
Weber inherits these views from the scholars on whom he
relied, yet it cannot be said that he followed them blindly.
Insofar as Weber was explicitly devoted to putting the sociology
of religion on a sound scientific basis, he was alert to the
infiltration of theological or metaphysical
elements.3 To a cer
tain extent, therefore, he succeeded
in freeing himself from
standard theology-driven methodological
assumptions.4 On the
other hand, Weber remains solidly committed towhat we today
denominate as a "hermeneutics of suspicion/' He assumes that
the actual course of Israelite history differs radically from the
narrative presentation of that history in the Bible. He is con
vinced of the basic soundness of source criticism and is confi
dent that P, for example, is the latest stage in the redactional
process. Weber buttresses this assumption by his own formi
dable theory of rationalization. While this assumption
is not
necessarily anti-Judaic, it does imply a notion of increasing
rigidity and decline. Weber does not free himself from such
views.
What then can Weber contribute to an understanding
of
Jewish political tradition? His contribution is three-fold: sub
stantive, methodological,
and cautionary. Both his theses, his
sociological approach, and his limits are instructive.
Substantively, Weber was the first modern scholar to work
out the implications of a concept of covenant rooted in socio
political rather than strictly theological categories. Weber's
posthumous classic, Das antike Judentum (1921), had a profound
impact on the development of subsequent German Bible schol
arship. Influenced by Weber, the works of Albrecht Alt and
Martin Noth came to shape the research of American scholars
such as William Foxwell Albright and George Mendenhall.
Our
modern understanding of covenant as the form of the Israelite
polity is directly indebted toWeber's interpretation.5 This inter
pretation, with references to Judges, is explored in greater detail
below.
Weber's substantive appreciation of covenant follows from
hismethodology. Methodologically, all subsequent sociologists
of religion are, more or less, inWeber's debt. Here we briefly
review some of the methodological
aspects of his sociology of
religion, his thesis on covenant, and some points of Julius
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.216 on Tue, 27 Nov 2012 03:30:02 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
12
AlanMittleman
Guttmann's critique ofWeber which illustrate the problems and
the limitsof a highly political reading of biblical texts.
An "Understanding" (Verstehende) Sociology
Weber was a practitioner of what has been called
ogy of knowledge. He learned from Marx to implicate of ideas in a network ofmaterial factors.6 Unlike Marx,
the sociol the world however,
Weber did not believe that material factors caused constellations
of ideas and values in a straightforward manner. The ideational
sphere is not, inWeber's thought, simply an expression of the
play of material interests. Neither is it ever the case that reli
gious ideas alone determine the historical process, as a typical
misunderstanding
of Weber's thesis on Puritanism and the rise
of capitalism would have it. The interrelation of ideas and
material factors ismore problematic.
To start, Weber rejects Marx's monocausal
emphasis on the
determinative
force of economic factors. He faults Marx for
failing to distinguish between an idea being caused by economic
forces and economic forces being relevant to the progress of an
idea. InWeber's celebrated thesis on the Puritan ethic, capital
ism is not caused by Puritanism. Puritanism is, rather, relevant
as a factor among factors in the development
of the type of
mentality which was able to rationalize the organization
of
production.
Weber ismore concerned to study the interrelatedness of all
spheres of social life: economic, political, religious, technologi
cal, aesthetic, military, legal and ideational, than he is to privi
lege any of them.All of these orders are linked in relations of
causation, expression, and affinity. Unlike Marx, Weber rejects
historical necessity as an illicit philosophical
concept which
ought to have no role in science. Weber sees a great deal of
accident, arbitrariness, and, of course, uniqueness
in social
reality. Social arrangements do not cause ideas. Rather, arrange
ments and ideas coexist. Ideas and values are often produced by
extraordinary, charismatic individuals for idiosyncratic, unpre
dictable reasons. Once an idea becomes available, social groups,
driven by particular interests,may findan affinitywith itand
institutionalize
it. The chosen idea then becomes an ideology
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.216 on Tue, 27 Nov 2012 03:30:02 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Max Weber'sConceptionofCovenantinAncientJudaism 13
which endures to the extent that it enables its bearers to survive
and succeed. As we shall see, covenant Weber.
is just such an idea for
Verstehende sociology has as its purpose to understand the
ideas and values of historical groups as they themselves under
stand them. This emphasis on empathy was a legacy of the
German historicist tradition. By affirming Verstehen, Weber
rejects Marxism's
claim to objective knowledge of the meaning
of historical events. Objective meaning construed against an
essentially metaphysical
construction of the process of history is
an illicit notion forWeber. What can be understood objectively,
indeed what must be understood objectively (for science re
quires objectivity) is how historical agents themselves under
stood or defined their situation. What did the values of a group
mean to the group? Why did they choose these values and not
others?How did these values effectempirical reality?Did the
subjects who chose them act rationally, i.e., consistently, ac
cording to them? At a higher level of abstraction, Weber asks,
what would
like?
ideal, rational behavior according
to x values be
Using an abstract standard of ideal rational congruence with some set of values, Weber derives the heuristic concept of an
"ideal type." Ideal types (e.g., capitalism, Christianity, asceti cism, salvation, charisma) are generalizing concepts which en able us to talk comparatively and abstractly about the brute,
infinite particularity of empirical reality. Unlike the historicists,
Weber, while respecting the unique irreplacability of human events, does not believe that empathy alone suffices to grasp their meaning. Sociology is not an imaginative hermeneutics by which we reexperience (Dilthey's Nachdenken) the Erlebnis of others. Sociology, rather, discerns amid the flux of human events an underlying lawful structure. This structure is de
scribed by postulating ideal types.
Ideal types may be compared to the grammar of a language. No one ever speaks a language entirely in accordance with the norms of grammar. Yet grammar, in all its abstractness, de
sslcatrrrliuybce,tsurideaessal?wetlylcpleasrai?sfypwrethshceenrifboeraspmpsliheodofwrattaioonhlaualnmitgayunageirmelpafltiuiconitncstioinnasan.7dculstSouimcrieai.l Weber believed that human beings in society often acted ratio
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.216 on Tue, 27 Nov 2012 03:30:02 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
14
Alan Mittleman
nally, i.e., consistently within a given framework of ideas and
values. Insofar as the researcher can rationally explore the
rational action of his subjects, verstehende sociology is a strictly
scientific inquiry.
There are, however, two great irrationalities at the margins
of scientific praxis. One is the researcher's choice of data. That,
Weber granted, is governed by subjective preference.8 But after
that choice is made, science is "value-free." The other field of
irrationality has more radical consequences. Weber believed
that all values are essentially ungrounded, human construc
tions. The universe itself is meaningless.
Religion arises in
response tomeaningless
suffering. Humans do not wrest mean
ing from the universe, they ascribe sense and intelligibility (Sinn
und Bedeutung) to the meaningless
infinity of events.9 Neutral
with respect to such axiological
commitments,
the scientist
looks upon this irrational process of sense-making and traces its
rational consequences.
The view that theworld is in semeaningless, Weber terms the
"disenchantment of theworld." Disenchantment
is the correlate
of rationalization, by which Weber implies an increasing coher
ence and consistency of ideas, associated with an increasing
systematization of institutions. Rationalization
is promoted by
the intellectual strata of cultures such as Confucian mandarins
or biblical prophets. Opposing rationalization
is charisma, the
characteristic of extraordinary personal authority associated
with uniquely powerful individuals. Charisma often introduces
discontinuity into rational procedures. Just as often, eruptions
of charisma are institutionalized and hence rationalized. Where
rationalization
progresses, belief in the adventitious,
spirit
animated character of the world and confidence in magical
means to manipulate
it diminishes. When an ethical, righteous
God replaces a world of competing spirits or nature divinities,
rational action, i.e., ethics, replaces magic. Only in the West,
under the impact of Israelite monotheism,
did a consistently
anti-magical worldview prevail. InWeber's view, such an ontol
ogy was a necessary (but not a sufficient) condition for the
emergence of capitalism.
Weber's studies of world religions were generated by the
problem of charting the growth of rationalization
in relevant
cultures of the East and West.10 Given the historical prevalence
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.216 on Tue, 27 Nov 2012 03:30:02 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Max Weber's Conception ofCovenant inAncient Judaism
15
of rationalization/disenchantment,
why did capitalism only
arise to an advanced degree in theWest? What factors in China
and India inhibited the growth of economic rationality? These economic concerns stimulated/ but did not exhaust, Weber's
interest inworld religions.
Thus Weber's specific interest in Judaism stems from his
conviction that only Judaism intuited the complete disenchant
ment and hence the complete rationalization of the world:
The world was conceived [by ancient Judaism] as neither eternal nor unchangeable, but rather as having been created. Its present structures were a product of man's activities,
above all those of the Jews and of God's reactions to them.
Hence the world was an historical product designed to give
way again to the truly God-ordained
order....There existed
in addition a highly rational religious ethic of social conduct;
it was free of magic and all forms of irrational quest for
salvation; itwas inwardly worlds apart from the paths of
salvation offered by Asian religions. To a large extent this
ethic still underlies contemporary Mid Eastern and Euro
pean ethic. World-historical
interest in Jewry rests upon this
fact.11
Unlike the great ancient cultures of the East, the Jews did not
produce: contemplative mystics, but "inner worldly ascetics."
(Contemplative mysticism and inner-worldly asceticism are
ideal types which permit comparative analysis of religious
groups.) The Jews conceived of man as an instrument for purpo
sive action, not as a vessel for salvific, unitive experience. Doing
the divine will through a rationally elaborated system of com
mandments,
rather than ruminating on the meaning of the
universe as a whole, marked Jewish religiosity. "The only prob
lems which could arise were those which were concrete and
topical and concerned action in the world; any other problem
was excluded."12 By "inner-worldly asceticism," Weber implies
a religious type of historically-conscious,
sober, activist piety
centered on fulfillment inhistory and society of divine will. This
formof religiosity, fullyarticulated by theprophets, originates
in thecovenantal thoughtof early Israel at thetimeof thejudges.
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.216 on Tue, 27 Nov 2012 03:30:02 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
16
Alan Mittleman
The Concept of Covenant
The importance and insight ofWeber's concept of covenant
can best be gained by contrasting itwith Wellhausen's.
In the
latter's view, covenant is a theologically charged metaphor for
Israel's relationship with God.13 A product of prophetic religion,
it is not earlier than the eighth century. Prior to prophecy, God's
relationship with Israel was conceived as a natural bond be
tween father and son. God provides immediate help with things
such as rain, war or oppression, not future salvation or deliver
ance. The prophets shatter this "naturalistic" understanding
of
God, replacing it by a contingent, ethical one. God becomes a
transcendent god of righteousness, rather than a tribal numen.
The relationship of God and Israel is one of divine demand and
human performance. Its conditionality is expressed metaphori
cally in the form of a contract or covenant.
Wellhausen
rejects the historicity of Mosaic/Sinaitic
tradi
tions. Moses, ifhe existed, was probably a leader and judge, on
the model of the shoftim, who promulgated
individual laws in
the form of God's oracular guidance. The presentation of this
guidance as a great corpus of law, deriving once and for all from
Sinai, was a prophetic innovation designed to illustrate the
absolute otherness and transcendence of a righteous god. The
ethical relation this god required awakened, as it were, an
antithesis within the thesis of "naturalistic," tribalistic Israel.
Not until Christianity was a synthesis, inwhich ethical univer
salism triumphs, achieved.
Weber decisively rejects this strictly theological concept of
covenant. For him, by contrast, Israel has its origins in covenant
(brith). Israel both develops and acquires its peculiar character
as an "oath-bound confederation"
through negotiated agree
ments between sub-groups and through an overall agreement
with YHVH. The "inner political history of Israel developed
through ever-repeated
ritualistic confederate resolutions."14
Weber believed that individual tribes such as Judah formed
through agreements between various ethnic and status groups,15 that kings were accepted through covenanting, that Deuteronomy was accepted as a Yahwistic constitution by the polity through
covenant, and that the procedure of covenanting carried Israel
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.216 on Tue, 27 Nov 2012 03:30:02 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
................
................
In order to avoid copyright disputes, this page is only a partial summary.
To fulfill the demand for quickly locating and searching documents.
It is intelligent file search solution for home and business.
Related download
- pdf max weber s conception of covenant in ancient judaism with
- pdf culture and education edu
- pdf chapter 7 religion the protestant ethic and moral values
- pdf introduction to sociology university of florida
- pdf weber made a number of contributions to sociology some of
- pdf max weber charisma and the disenchantment of the world
- pdf comparing marx and weber nyu
- pdf bureaucracy and formal organizations iitk
- pdf bureaucracy administrative structure and set of regulations
- pdf max weber modernity and the role of ideas andrew j perrin
Related searches
- weber s theory of bureaucracy summary
- max weber bureaucratic theory of management
- pdf max weber s contribution to sociology
- weber s principles of bureaucratic structure
- max weber s six characteristics of bureaucracy
- weber s theory of bureaucracy
- max weber s bureaucratic theory pdf
- max weber s model bureaucracy
- max weber s theory
- max weber s principles of organization
- max weber s concept of bureaucracy
- max weber s bureaucratic theory