Moral Development: Theories and Evidence



Moral Development: Changing Theories and Evidence

Darcia Narvaez, University of Notre Dame

Moral development has been traditionally viewed as the inculcation of cultural values and moral practices as if the child is largely a passive recipient (hence lectures and rote memorization). Piaget (1932/1965) revolutionized development theory by documenting how individuals construct their understanding of the world through shifting understandings that are modified by experience in interaction with maturation (e.g., working memory increases through childhood). Countless studies have shown how individuals are active learners, not passive tabula rasa, applying what they know to incoming information and often getting it wrong if the information is too advanced for or culturally different from their current knowledge (e.g., Bartlett, 1932). In short, individuals learn by actively constructing knowledge about the world from experience. Understanding develops initially as tacit knowledge which sometimes can be accessed explicitly (Keil & Wilson, 1999).

But this does not say enough. Vygotsky (1935) emphasized the relational aspects of learning, how learning is scaffolded by those with more experience. Parents do this with their children, for example, when teaching them to dance they hold them first, then have them stand on their feet to learn the steps or the feel of the music, giving the child more and more independent control of the action. Knowledge is built as the learner internalizes the actions and voice of the mentor for particular situations until she can perform on her own (Rogoff, 1990). Thus knowledge, especially explicit understanding, develops within a guided context.

In a way these two perspectives align with contemporary cognitive science’s understanding of learning (see Hogarth, 2001, for an extensive review). Learning involves both the deliberate conscious system (explicit knowledge) and unconscious implicit systems (tacit knowledge). The deliberative or conscious mind can learn and access theory and apply rules and procedures (“top down”). But most of learning in life takes place without consciousness from multiple systems keeping records of events and associations in implicit systems. The implicit mind (adaptive unconscious or intuitive mind) learns effortlessly from everyday experience about what works to help meet one’s goals (“bottom up”; Reber, 1993). It appears that most of human behavior is governed by implicit rather than deliberative systems (Bargh & Chartrand, 1999), although one must distinguish seat-of-the-pants intuition from well-education intuition (Narvaez, 2009).

The Focus on Moral Reasoning. Moral reasoning research, the primary focus of moral psychology for over 50 years, has often emphasized the deliberate mind, asking people to articulate reasons for making judgments (Kohlberg, 1981; 1984). However, only those with extensive reasoning practice, like moral philosophers, are able to articulate what they know in this manner, making it more appropriate to use measures of tacit knowledge (Rest, 1979; 1986). Indeed, documented with tens of thousands of subjects, moral judgment develops tacitly from an emphasis on prioritizing personal interest, to an appreciation of the rules and order of society and, with higher education, to an ability to think postconventionally in terms of procedural justice and fair practice (Rest et al., 1999). Those with greater preferences for postconventional thinking are more supportive of human rights, more democratic as teachers, cheat less and are more cooperative (Rest, 1979; 1986). We also know that moral judgment best develops in a context of engaging cognitive conflict, discussion of relevant moral dilemmas whether in the classroom with peers or at home with responsive parents (for a review, see Lapsley, 1996). Moreover, individuals who select enriched social environments maintain higher levels of moral reasoning during and after college (Rest, 1986). My research has measured moral information processing with tasks like reaction time, comprehension (e.g., recall, theme comprehension) of stories that have embedded moral content (e.g., Narvaez & Gleason, 2007), finding that moral judgment development influences how one perceives moral events.

Expanding the Components of Moral Functioning. Despite its importance, moral reasoning is only one of several psychological processes related to ethics that is individually constructed with social mediation. Other components or processes that have been identified are moral sensitivity (e.g., moral perception, empathic response, taking the perspective of others), moral focus/motivation (e.g., ethical identity, integrity), ethical action skills (e.g., perseverance, resolving conflicts nonviolently) (Rest, 1983; Narvaez & Rest, 1995). Many of these capacities involve the implicit mind more than the deliberative mind and influence moral perception and moral action (Narvaez & Lapsley, 2009). Moral exemplars exhibit actionable sets of procedural, declarative and conditional knowledge in these components. For example, experts in ethical sensitivity are better at accurately discerning moral situations and seeing action possibilities (Varela, 1999). They are able to take on the perspective of the other in an effort to be morally responsive to others (Monroe, 1994). Experts in ethical judgment are able to hold multiple perspectives as they reason about duty and consequences to solve complex problems (Kohlberg, 1984). Experts in ethical focus prioritize and deepen commitment to ethical goals (Walker & Frimer, 2009). Experts in ethical action know how to implement the task step by step, persevering over years of commitment (Colby & Damon, 1991). Virtue overall has to do with embodied understanding. Embodied cognition can be described as ‘mesh,’ the particular way that situational affordances (action possibilities), knowledge (effectivity), and goals combine to foster action (Glenberg, 1997).

The Nature of Ethical Know-How. The virtuous person has more and better organized knowledge about their area of excellence; they have highly tuned perceptual sensibilities for it and a deep moral desire for it; they exhibit highly automatized, effortless responses in combination with deliberative self-guidance. Ethical know-how or mature moral functioning (see Narvaez, 2009, for a review) is evident in action that balances intuition and deliberation with individual capacities for habituated empathic concern (Stout, 2009), moral imagination (Dewey, 1934), and moral metacognition (e.g., moral self-regulation, moral self-reflection). Mature moral functioning also involves collective capacities for moral dialogue and moral institutions. These capacities are related to moral innovation (Tough, 2008). Many of these abilities develop with experience and can be fostered through educational intervention.

Moral functioning can be fostered like any expertise. Experts-in-training actively build capacities through extended, focused, deliberate practice under the guidance of a mentor (Ericsson & Charness, 1994; Ericsson et al., 1993), training both deliberative and intuitive understanding (Feltovich, Prietula, & Ericsson, 2006). The implicit mind develops understanding through immersed experience which fosters perceptions, sensibilities and trains up emotions and intuitions based on what works in the particular environment. At the same time, the deliberative mind learns such things as theory, logical procedures, explicit self understanding and goal setting. Novice to expert pedagogy involves coached guidance, the guide on the side whispering into the ear about what is known to work and what to watch for, and extensive opportunities to practice in environments that give good feedback about what is effective. Environments matter for developing intuitions and fostering mindsets but the deliberate mind can select the environments (Hogarth, 2001).

Ethical skills can be fostered in all domains of study—in school settings, at home, and in communities. Adaptive ethical education (Narvaez, in press) fosters expertise in the four components (judgment, sensitivity, focus/motivation, action), taking both minds into account (deliberative and implicit). But in terms of ethical education, more is required. Integrative Ethical Education (IEE; Narvaez, 2006; 2007; 2008) synthesizes the research literature across psychology and education into five basic suggestions for ethical education: (1) Establish a caring relationship with the child or mentee. As emotion-based creatures, humans need trust and social connection to be engaged in learning (Baumeister & Leary, 1995). (2) Design a climate supportive of ethics and excellence. Climates or cultures encourage some behaviors and not others. Climates that support autonomy, competence and belonging foster motivation (Deci & Ryan, 1985) and prosocial behavior (Solomon et al., 1988). Socially toxic environments discourage moral development (Garbarino, 1995). (3) Cultivate ethical skill development with a novice-to-expert pedagogy. This can be done in every area of academic instruction (Narvaez, 2006). (4) Help mentees develop self-regulation for ethics and excellence, a requirement for success in any domain (Zimmerman, Bonner & Kovach, 2000). (5) Restore the village of support for the student and all community members (Bronfenbrenner, 1979). Individuals flourish in communities where they are known and supported (Lerner, Dowling & Anderson, 2003). IEE provides a basic framework for ethical education. Mature functioning comes with much practice and maturation (plus brain myelinzation occurring in middle age speeds neuronal communication, facilitating the synthesizing of knowledge; Giedd et al., 1999).

Importance of Early Life Experience. But moral development begins from birth, if not before. Neurobiological research studies are demonstrating the epigenetic effects of early experience. Many children are not receiving the care mammals require. For example, even in the womb, the brain of the child is influenced by the depression or stress experienced by the mother, shaping the brain for hyperactive stress response after birth, which is linked to “unsociable and inconsiderate behaviours” in childhood (p. 435, Lupien et al., 2009). Human mammalian needs are reflected in the “environment of evolutionary adaptedness” or EEA (as named by Bowlby, 1951) and are increasingly corroborated by neurobiological studies (see Narvaez & Panksepp, 2009, for a review). Some EEA characteristics have been identified by anthropologists for infants and young children (Hewlett & Lamb, 2005), for example: breastfeeding for 2-5 years (the immune system develops to adult level by age 5; breastmilk is 80% probiotic); constant touch in first two years of life (linked to multiple system development); prompt response to cries and distress (linked to emotion regulation and personality); multiple adult caregivers beyond parents; and multi-age play groups. Modern childrearing practices have upended most of these principles with negative consequences that appear to be snowballing (e.g., epidemics of depression and anxiety; NICHD, 2004).

These findings have been integrated into a moral development theory (Triune Ethics theory; TET; Narvaez, 2008), examining the effects of early life experience on moral functioning. According to TET, moral capabilities, which are always based in neurological and physical systems, are compromised by modern childrearing practices. For example, vagal nerve function is related to immune, emotion, cardiac, digestive system function. With inconsistent or neglectful parenting the vagal nerve is compromised. Vagal nerve response not only is related to multiple health effects, it accompanies expressions of compassion and prosocial behavior (Eisenberg & Eggum, 2008).

When physiological and psychological system needs are compromised by poor care, the systems resort to a default primitive survival orientation, resulting in a self-focused orientation to the moral life (the Security ethic or “bunker” morality). In this case, the “panic/distress” and/or “fear/anxiety” emotional systems are easily evoked, compromising the ability to have open-hearted relationships with others, making “negative morality” more morally salient (i.e., harming others for justice reasons). The more advanced ethics (emotional Engagement with others in the moment—“harmony” morality, and Imaginative concern for those not present—“mindful” morality) require EEA caregiving and are compromised without it. The Engagement ethic, rooted in the proper functioning of the “care” and “play” emotional circuits, underlies prosocial behavior. The Imagination ethic requires proper functioning of the prefrontal cortex (executive functions) for the cognitive aspects of prosocial behavior and is also affected by early experience. In sum, early experience sets the trajectory for life in most every way, including moral capabilities. Although the brain is malleable, it is much more difficult to repair poor emotional system setup after it is established, and such repair may never reach optimality.

Centrality of moral identity. Some time ago, Blasi (1984) emphasized the importance of moral identity as key to moral action. One has a moral identity when moral constructs—moral desires, integrity and willpower—are fundamental to self identity. An areas of increasing interest among researchers (e.g., Lapsley & Narvaez, 2004; Narvaez & Lapsley, 2009), moral identity has been especially noted as a factor driving moral action (Colby & Damon, 1991), social information processing and moral evaluation (Narvaez, Lapsley, Hagele & Lasky, 2006).

In summary, moral development research has moved from an emphasis on deliberative reasoning to a broader view of embodied processes that include perception/sensitivity, focus/motivation and action/implementation. Best practice for cultivating moral capacities involves a novice-to-expert pedagogy but also caring relationships, supportive climate, fostering moral self-actualization, and a village of support. Moral maturity combines deliberative and intuitive processes in capacities for moral self regulation, and practices such as habituated empathic concern, moral dialogue and moral institutions. Moral development research is also looking at early life and its impact on moral functioning, finding that neglectful caregiving from the view of mammalian needs underdevelops brain systems required for optimal moral functioning.

REFERENCES

Aquino, Karl and Dan Freeman. 2009. Moral Identity in Business Situations: A Social-Cognitive Framework for Understanding Moral Functioning. Pp. 375-395 in Personality, Identity, and Character: Explorations in Moral Psychology edited by D. Narvaez and D. K. Lapsley. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Bargh, John A., & Tanya L. Chartrand. 1999. The unbearable automaticity of being. American Psychologist, 54: 462-479.

Bartlett, Frederic C. 1932. Remembering: A study in experimental and social psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Baumeister, Roy and Mark Leary. 1995. The need to belong: Desire for interpersonal attachments as a fundamental human motivation. Psychological Bulletin, 117: 497-529.

Bowlby, John. 1951. Maternal care and mental health. New York: Schocken.

Bronfenbrenner, Urie. 1979. The ecology of human development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Colby, Anne and William Damon. 1991. Some do care. New York: Free Press.

Cervone, Daniel and Ritu Tripathi. 2009.The Moral Functioning of the Person as a Whole: On Moral Psychology and Personality Science. pp. 30-51 in Personality, Identity, and Character: Explorations in Moral Psychology edited by D. Narvaez and D. K. Lapsley. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Deci, Edward L. and Richard M. Ryan. 1985. Intrinsic motivation and self-determination in human behavior. New York: Academic Press.

Dewey, John. 1934. The Later Works, 1925-1953: Volume 10: Art as Experience. Edited by J. A. Boydston. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.

Eisenberg, Nancy and Natalie D. Eggum. 2008. Empathic Responding: Sympathy and Personal Distress. Pp. xx In Cooperation: The political psychology of effective human interaction edited by B. Sullivan, M. Snyder, & J. Sullivan. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

Eisenberg, Nancy, Richard A. Fabes, and Tracy L. Spinrad. 2006. Prosocial development. Pp.646-718 in Handbook of child psychology, 6th. ed. edited by W. Damon Series Ed. &. N. Eisenberg Vol. Ed.,. New York: John Wiley & Sons.

Ericsson, K. Anders and Neil Charness. 1994. Expert performance: Its structure and acquisition. American Psychologist, 49, 725-747.

Ericsson, K. Anders., Ralf T. Krampe, and Clemens Tesch-Roemer. 1993. The role of deliberate practice in the acquisition of expert performance. Psychological Review, 100 3: 363-406.

Feltovich, Paul J., Michael J. Prietula, and K. Anders Ericsson. 2006. Studies of expertise from psychological perspectives. Pp. 41-68 in K.A. Ericsson, N. Charness, P.J. Feltovich, R.R. Hoffman Eds., The Cambridge handbook of expertise and expert performance. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Garbarino, James. 1995. Raising children in a socially toxic environment. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.

Giedd, Jay N., Jonathan Blumenthal, and Neal O. Jeffries et al. 1999. Brain development during childhood and adolescence: A longitudinal MRI study. Nature Neuroscience, 210: 861-3.

Hewlett, Barry. S. and Michael E. Lamb. 2005. Hunter-gatherer childhoods: Evolutionary, developmental and cultural perspectives. New Brunswick, NJ: Aldine.

Hogarth, Robin. M. 2001. Educating Intuition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Keil, Frank C. and Robert A. Wilson. 2000. Explaining explanations. In F.C. Keil & R.A. Wilson Eds., Explanation and Cognition pp. 1-18. Cambridge MA: Bradford MIT Press.

Kohlberg, Lawrence. 1984. The psychology of moral development: Essays on moral development, Vol. II. New York: Harper & Row.

Lapsley, Daniel K. 1996. Moral Psychology. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

Narvaez, Darcia and Daniel K. Lapsley. Eds. 2009. Personality, Identity, and Character: Explorations in Moral Psychology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Lerner , Richard M., Elizabeth M. Dowling, and Pamela M. Anderson. 2003. Positive youth development: Thriving as a basis of personhood and civil society. Applied Developmental Science, 7, 172-180.

Lupien, Sonia J., Bruce S. McEwen, Megan R. Gunnar, and Christine Heim. 2009. Effects of stress throughout the lifespan on the brain, behaviour and cognition. Nature, 10: 434-445.

Monin, Benoit and Alex Jordan. 2009. The Dynamic Moral Self: A Social Psychological Perspective. In D. Narvaez & D. K. Lapsley, Eds. Personality, Identity, and Character: Explorations in Moral Psychology pp. 341-354. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Monroe, Kenwick R., & Constance Epperson. 1994. But what else could I do? Choice, identity and a cognitive- perceptual theory of ethical political behavior. Political Psychology, 15, 201-226.

Narvaez, Darcia. 2006. Integrative Ethical Education. In M. Killen & J. Smetana Eds., Handbook of Moral Development pp. 703-733. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

Narvaez, Darcia. 2008. Triune ethics: The neurobiological roots of our multiple moralities. New Ideas in Psychology, 26, 95-119.

Narvaez, Darcia. In press. Moral complexity: The fatal attraction of truthiness and the importance of mature moral functioning. Perspectives on Psychological Science.

Narvaez, Darcia. in press. Guiding the brain and mind for high moral intelligence. In B. Latzko & T. Malti Eds.. Children’s Moral Emotions and Moral Cognition: Developmental and Educational Perspectives, New Directions for Child and Adolescent Development.

Narvaez, Darcia and Tracy Gleason. 2007. The Influence of moral judgment development and moral experience on comprehension of moral narratives and expository texts. The Journal of Genetic Psychology, 1683, 251–276.

Narvaez, Darcia and Jaak Panksepp. 2009. Restoring human nature: Mammalian needs and the [missing] environment of evolutionary adaptedness. Manuscript submitted for publication.

Narvaez, Darcia and James Rest. 1995. The four components of acting morally. In W. Kurtines & J. Gewirtz Eds., Moral behavior and moral development: An introduction pp. 385-400. New York: McGraw-Hill.

National Institute of Child Health and Human Development, Early Child Care Research Network. 2004. Affect dysregulation in the mother-child relationship in the toddler years: Antecedents and consequences. Developmental Psychopathology, 16, 43–68.

Panksepp, Jaak. 1998. Affective neuroscience: The foundations of human and animal emotions. New York: Oxford University Press.

Piaget, Jean. 1932/1965. The moral judgment of the child M. Gabain, Trans.. New York: Free Press.

Reber, Arthur S. 1993. Implicit learning and tacit knowledge: An essay on the cognitive unconscious. New York: Oxford University Press.

Rest, James, R. 1983. Morality. Pp. 556-629 in Cognitive development, edited by J. Flavell & E. Markham (volume eds.) and Vol. 3. Manual of child psychology, edited by P. Mussen (Series Ed.) New York: Wiley.

Rest, James R. 1986. Moral development: Advances in research and theory. New York: Praeger.

Rest, James, Darcia Narvaez, Muriel Bebeau, and Stephen J. Thoma. 1999. Postconventional moral thinking: A neo-Kohlbergian approach. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Rogoff, Barbara. 1990. Apprenticeship in thinking: Cognitive development in social context. New York: Oxford University Press.

Skitka, Linda J. and G. Scott Morgan. 2009. The Double-edged Sword of a Moral State of Mind. Pp. 355-375 in Personality, Identity, and Character: Explorations in Moral Psychology edited by D. Narvaez and D. K. Lapsley. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Solomon, Daniel, Marilyn Watson, Kevin Delucchi, Eric Schaps, and Victor Battistich. 1988. Enhancing children’s prosocial behavior in the classroom. American Educational Research Journal, 25: 527–554.

Stout, J.D. 2009. The empathy gap. New York: Viking.

Tough, Paul. 2008. Whatever it takes: Geoffrey Canada’s quest to change Harlem and America.

Varela, Francisco. 1999. Ethical Know-How: Action, Wisdom, and Cognition. Stanford CA: Stanford University Press.

Vygotsky, Lev. S. 1935. The mental development of children in the process of learning. Oxford, England: Uchpedgiz.

Walker, Lawrence J. and James Frimer. 2009. Moral Personality Exemplified. pp. 232-255 in Personality, Identity, and Character: Explorations in Moral Psychology edited by D. Narvaez and D. K. Lapsley. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Zimmerman, Barry J., Sebastian Bonner, and Robert Kovach. 2002. Developing self-regulated learners. Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association.

................
................

In order to avoid copyright disputes, this page is only a partial summary.

Google Online Preview   Download