Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Philosophy of Language
Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Philosophy of Language
Table of Contents
1
Adverbs
6
2
Ambiguity
11
3
Analyticity
15
4
Anaphora
20
5
Animal language and thought
26
6
Communication and intention
31
7
Communicative rationality
35
8
Compositionality
39
9
Counterfactual conditionals
41
10 Criteria
46
11 Deconstruction
50
12 Demonstratives and indexicals
55
13 Descriptions
60
14 Discourse semantics
66
15 Emotive meaning
76
16 Fiction, semantics of
78
17 Holism: mental and semantic
83
18 Implicature
89
19 Indicative conditionals
94
20 Indirect discourse
97
21 Intensionality
100
22 Interpretation, Indian theories of
102
23 Language and gender
107
24 Language of Thought
114
25 Language, ancient philosophy of
118
26 Language, conventionality of
124
27 Language, early modern philosophy of
128
28 Language, Indian theories of
137
29 Language, innateness of
143
30 Language, medieval theories of
148
31 Language, philosophy of
165
32 Language, Renaissance philosophy of
169
33 Language, social nature of
174
34 Linguistic discrimination
179
35 Logical atomism
184
36 Mass terms
188
37 Meaning and communication
191
38 Meaning and rule-following
193
39 Meaning and truth
199
40 Meaning and understanding
206
41 Meaning and verification
211
42 Meaning in Islamic philosophy
218
43 Meaning, Indian theories of
221
44 Metaphor
226
45 Moscow-Tartu School
229
46 Performatives
235
47 Post-structuralism
237
48 Pragmatics
242
49 Predication
257
50 Presupposition
259
51 Private language argument
263
52 Private states and language
269
53 Proper names
273
54 Propositional attitude statements
279
55 Propositional attitudes
289
56 Propositions, sentences and statements
298
57 Questions
300
58 Radical translation and radical interpretation
303
59 Reference
315
60 Religious language
328
61 Rhetoric
333
62 Sapir-Whorf hypothesis
338
63 Scope
341
64 Semantics
343
65 Semantics, conceptual role
347
66 Semantics, game-theoretic
352
67 Semantics, informational
354
68 Semantics, possible worlds
358
69 Semantics, situation
367
70 Semantics, teleological
372
71 Semiotics
375
72 Sense and reference
380
73 Speech acts
385
74 Structuralism in linguistics
391
75 Syntax
395
76 Type/token distinction
406
77 Universal language
408
78 Use/mention distinction and quotation
411
Adverbs
Adverbs
Adverbs are so named from their role in modifying verbs and other non-nominal expressions. For example, in `John ran slowly', the adverb `slowly' modifies `ran' by characterizing the manner of John's running. The debate on the semantic contribution of adverbs centres on two approaches. On the first approach, adverbs are understood as predicate operators: for example, in `John ran slowly', `ran' would be taken to be a predicate and `slowly' an operator affecting its meaning. Working this out in detail requires the resources of higher-order logic. On the second approach, adverbs are understood as predicates of `objects' such as events and states, reference to which is revealed in logical form. For example, `John ran slowly' would be construed along the lines of `there was a running by John and it was slow', in which the adverb `slowly' has become a predicate `slow' applied to the event that was John's running.
Since adverbs are exclusively modifiers, they are classed among the syncategorematic words of terminist logic, the investigation of which carried the subject forward from Aristotle in the thirteenth century. (The contrasting `categoremata' - grammatical subjects and predicates - are those words which have meaning independently.) They are of contemporary interest for philosophical logic and semantic theory, because particular accounts of them carry implications for the nature of combinatorial semantics and language understanding, and for ontology.
1 Syntactic types and semantic combination
There are several types of adverbial constructions, of which we distinguish the following classes: (a) `manner' adverbs, which intuitively function as simple modifiers of verbs; (b) `thematic' adverbs, of which some and possibly all function as (at least) two-place predicates in their own right; (c) adverbs of quantification, which express generality applying to whole sentences; and (d) discourse particles, whose meaning evidently derives from their role in linking clauses or independent sentences. (These categories are not exhaustive.) `Adverbs', especially manner `adverbs', are not in fact confined to single words. The general category is therefore not that of adverbs, but of adverbial phrases or adverbials (for example, `more quickly than Mary', `very frequently').
Typical manner adverbials are as in (1) below, thematic adverbs as in (2) and adverbs of quantification as in (3):
(1) John walked slowly/quietly/more quickly than Mary. (2) Mary apparently/reluctantly went to New York. (3) Mary occasionally/always walks to work.
Discourse particles, considered briefly below, include `but', `anyway' and several others. We discuss these cases in turn.
The essential logical problem of manner adverbials is already apparent in the simplest examples. A verb combines with a manner adverb to form a complex verbal construction of the same type. Thus `walk' and `walk slowly' are both predicates, and the syntax of the combination may be depicted as follows: [V [V walk][Adv slowly]]
If (disregarding tense) we take `walk' as a one-place predicate, then the semantics of this combination might be given by positing that `slowly' is interpreted as a predicate operator; that is, as a function that maps one-place predicate interpretations onto other one-place predicate interpretations. Alternatively, it may be suggested that `slowly' and the other manner adverbials are, logically speaking, predicates in their own right, specifically predicates of actions. The adjectives to which they are related do seem to play this role. Corresponding to (1), for instance, we have the adjectival predications
(4) John's walk was slow/quiet/quicker than Mary's.
If we take the further step of supposing that the verb `walk' is in fact a two-place predicate, with a position for actions, then the combination `walk slowly' can be interpreted as
walk(x, e) & slow(e),
Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Version 1.0, London and New York: Routledge (1998)
6
................
................
In order to avoid copyright disputes, this page is only a partial summary.
To fulfill the demand for quickly locating and searching documents.
It is intelligent file search solution for home and business.
Related download
- introduction to philosophy stephen hicks
- dictionary of islamic philosophical terms
- the oxford handbook of philosophy of religion
- history of philosophy i ancient philosophy
- dictionary of non philosophy monoskop
- the hegel dictionary meetup
- glossary of philosophical terms oxford university press
- introduction to philosophy a general outline of
- routledge encyclopedia of philosophy philosophy of language
- the philosophy of humanism
Related searches
- stanford encyclopedia of philosophy plato
- encyclopedia of philosophy online
- stanford encyclopedia of philosophy app
- internet encyclopedia of philosophy articles
- internet encyclopedia of philosophy ethics
- internet encyclopedia of philosophy iep
- stanford encyclopedia of philosophy love
- stanford encyclopedia of philosophy ethics
- encyclopedia of philosophy stanford university
- stanford encyclopedia of philosophy law
- stanford encyclopedia of philosophy archive
- philosophy of language pdf