A priori intuition and demonstration
The problem of evilThe argumentGod is traditionally understood to be perfectly good, omnipotent and omniscient. The existence of evil causes problems for this definition. If God is good, then he has the desire to eliminate evil. If God is omnipotent, then God is able to eliminate evil. If God is omniscient, then God knows that evil exists and knows how to eliminate it. But if God wants to eliminate evil and can eliminate evil, then why does evil exist? We can conclude that since evil exists, God – at least an omnipotent, good God – does not exist.We can express this in terms of love. If you love someone, you don’t want them to suffer, and you will do what you can to prevent them from suffering. If God is all-loving, then he would prevent us from suffering if he could. Evil causes us to suffer, so if God is all-loving and all-powerful, he would prevent evil. Since evil exists, either God does not exist or God is not all-loving and all-powerful.The logical problemThere are two interpretations of this argument. One version, called the logical problem of evil, claims that the mere existence of evil is logically incompatible with the existence of an omnipotent, good God. It understands the argument deductively.For the existence of evil to be logically incompatible with the existence of God, we have to suppose that being good, God has the desire to eliminate all evil. But this isn’t true if some evil is necessary for a greater good. For example, unless we felt pain, we could never learn endurance; or again, what would love be like without sadness when we lose someone we love? But, as the poet Tennyson says, ‘’Tis better to have loved and lost, than never to have loved at all’. So some evil is actually necessary to make the world as good a place as it is. A variation of this argument is that we could not appreciate what is good, and so would not desire it as we do, unless we experienced evil to contrast it with. So being good, God does not desire to eliminate all evil. So the mere existence of evil is not logically incompatible with the existence of God.The evidential problemThe evidential problem of evil claims that the amount and distribution of evil that exists is good evidence that an omnipotent, good God does not exist. It understands the argument inductively: the way evil actually exists is good evidence for thinking that God does not exist. For example, children can die of terrible diseases or they can be brutally treated. Animals can suffer in natural disasters such as drought. This seems exactly the kind of thing an omnipotent, good God would want to eradicate. Evil is unfairly distributed, and even if it is necessary for certain goods, is so much evil necessary? It is this version of the problem we will discuss.Moral and natural evilTo understand the argument, we need to be clear on what ‘evil’ means in this context. ‘Evil’ usually refers to morally wrong actions or motives of human beings. So we say that Hitler was evil in trying to eradicate the Jews or that ethnic cleansing is an evil policy. This is ‘moral evil’.But this isn’t the only kind of evil the problem of evil is talking about. There is also ‘natural evil’, which refers to suffering caused by natural events and processes, e.g. the suffering caused by earthquakes, illness, the predation of animals on each other, and so on.The two types of evil are distinct. What people choose to do to each other is not usually the result of natural events. Sometimes it is: famine may drive people to stealing and killing; but this is the exception. And natural events are not usually the result of what people choose to do. Again, sometimes they are – the results of global warming could be an example. But nothing people did caused the tsunami in the Indian Ocean on 26 December 2004 (which killed hundreds of thousands of people).We need to keep both types of evil in mind when we look at responses to the problem of evil. In particular, some responses may solve the problem of moral evil, but don’t answer the problem of natural evil.free willA theodicy is an argument which tries to make evil compatible with the existence of an omnipotent, good God. Perhaps the most famous theodicy appeals to free will. It argues that evil is the result of our free will. God gave us free will, as something that is very good. It is better to have a universe with free will than without. Being morally imperfect, however, we do not always use our free will for good, but sometimes bring about evil. But God cannot make people with free will act for good. Given how good free will is, it is still better than we have free will and sometimes use it to bring about evil than that we don’t have free will at all.We can object that the argument only deals with moral evil, evil that we bring about, through our choices. It doesn’t account for natural evil at all. There are two replies to this. First, we could argue that natural evil is the result of an evil supernatural being, such as the Devil. The traditional story goes that the Devil was an angel, created by God, endowed with free will. But he rebelled against God, and since then has sought to bring evil into the world. Natural evil is the effects of his actions, so it is moral evil. The second reply comes from St Augustine.Augustine’s argumentAugustine argues that natural evil is a result of the moral evil of human beings. He claims that the choice of Adam and Eve to disobey God led to ‘The Fall’. The Fall was a metaphysical change, altering nature, human beings, and the relationship between them: there is enmity between human beings and animals, giving birth causes pain, we must work hard to survive (Genesis 3:15-19). Nature and human nature are ‘out of sorts’. So all evil, natural evil as well as moral evil, was caused by human free choice.A first objection is that the Fall was not an actual event in human history. If it didn’t happen, and if, for instance, animals were suffering long before human beings even existed, then free will can’t be the cause of natural evil. Many Christians now understand the Fall as an important myth about the relationship between human beings, nature and God. But this means that we cannot claim the Fall is literally responsible for all natural evil.A second objection is that, if it were true, it seems grossly unfair. Why should animals and children suffer as a result of a choice made by two people a very long time ago? It is not just to punish children for what their parents do; if your dad steals something, it isn’t right that you get sent to prison! So how could a good God make the evil chosen by two people lead to such terrible consequences for so many other people? Surely it didn’t have to be this way, and a good God wouldn’t allow it.How good is free will?It is central to the free will defence that free will is a great good. It is better for God to have created a world in which beings with free will (us) cause evil than a world in which there is no free will and no evil. However, we can object that even if free will is a great good, that doesn’t mean we should never interfere with it. If we see someone about to commit murder and do nothing about it, it is no defence to appeal to how wonderful it is that the murderer has free will. The existence and goodness of free will is compatible with interfering with it. So why doesn’t God prevent evil actions?We can reply that God would have to interfere very often to prevent all the evil we cause, and this would undermine our sense of free will. But perhaps that depends on how God interferes. Couldn’t God arrange it that we would be tempted to harm one another, and believe that we were capable of doing so, but when it actually came to acting on such motives, a strong sense of conscience prevented us?Second, God could have given us free will without giving us the power to commit terrible evil. Is free will, as it is now, such a good thing that its existence outweighs all the evil in the world? Wouldn’t a limited kind of free will have been better? Richard Swinburne replies that the value of free will depends on what one can do with it. A world in which we couldn’t harm each other would also be one in which we would have very little responsibility for each other’s well-being. It would be a ‘toy world’. But does this follow? We could still have a world in which we could choose to greatly benefit each other or not. Or again, we could harm each other in more minor ways, but because of a strong conscience, feel terrible about it, so be less inclined to commit harm. (These points are all the more powerful when we consider the free will of the Devil. We referred to the Devil to extend the free will defence to natural evil. But surely a world without the Devil, and so a world without natural evil, would be better than a world with the Devil and his free will. If this is right, then the free will defence cannot answer the problem of natural evil.)appeal to ignoranceThe evidential problem of evil appeals to an intuition, that there is no good reason that could justify the amount and distribution of evil in the world. However, a religious believer may simply reply that we don’t know this. It may be that all evil serves some higher purpose, but we simply don’t, and perhaps can’t, know what that purpose is or how evil serves it.Yes, it may be, but then it may not be. This isn’t enough to undermine the evidential problem of evil, because the argument isn’t meant to be a proof that God doesn’t exist. It only intends to show that it is very unlikely that God exists. So we should say this: There is no good that we know of that could justify the evil that we see. Any higher good we can think of (such as free will or spiritual growth) could be obtained without God having to allow the evil that exists. Whatever higher good evil is supposed to be necessary for, if it’s anything we can think of already, it won’t justify evil.Therefore, evil can only be justified by a higher good that we are simply not familiar with.It is probable that we know most goods.So it is probable that there is no such higher good.We often infer from what we know to what we don’t know. For example, we constantly form beliefs about the future: the sun will rise tomorrow, chairs won’t suddenly sprout wings, and so on. We do this because we think the future will be like the past. Inferring from ‘nothing we know of will justify evil’ to ‘nothing will justify evil’ is just the same.When reasoning about what is probable, we don’t usually allow the appeal to ignorance on its own. Instead, we need a good reason for thinking that there is some higher good that we don’t know about. Suppose we have a revelation from God that everything is for the best. This won’t really count, because if it is unlikely that God exists, it is unlikely that the revelation is genuine. But we don’t know whether it is unlikely that God exists or not until we have solved the problem of evil.The best of all possible worldsOne way of phrasing the problem of evil is to say that if God is all-loving and all-powerful, then he would make the best of all possible worlds for us to live in. This is clearly not the best of all possible worlds – the removal of many evils would make the world better. Therefore, an all-loving and all-powerful God does not exist.One response is to argue that this is the best of all possible worlds. We have already seen indications of this: that the world is better with free will and evil than without either free will or evil, and we cannot have a world which has free will but not evil; or again, that the world is better with souls that develop morally and spiritually, but for this, evil is necessary. We can also give a more general argument. It is easy to pick out some event or some feature of the world that we think the world would be better off without. If someone we know hadn’t got cancer; if a particular type of parasite hadn’t evolved; if Hitler had never got into power – the world would be a better place. However, we don’t know what the consequences would be of removing these events or features from the world. We don’t know the connections between these events and others. Removing these features or preventing these events may require all sorts of changes, which in the end would produce a worse world. Because we can’t know this, we can’t know that this isn’t the best of all possible worlds. The laws of natureFor example, the most obvious we can imagine some one event changing is for God to intervene in what caused the event. For example, he could prevent Hitler’s parents from meeting, or he could kill Hitler off by a freak lightning strike. This would be a miracle – an intervention with events that are in accordance with the laws of nature. But the laws of nature are themselves a great good. For example, for free will to exist, for us to do anything at all, things need to happen in a regular way (chairs don’t sprout wings, water quenches thirst, etc.). If events are going to happen in a regular way, then the world needs to be governed by natural laws. These laws will give rise to natural evil or to people who will commit moral evil. But this evil is justified because the alternative is a much worse world in which nothing takes place in a regular way.We can object that there would still be laws of nature if God intervened sometimes, to prevent the very worst evils from occurring. But once again, we can appeal to our ignorance of the effects if God miraculously prevented some event from happening or some feature of the world from existing. Suppose it is true, as the soul-making argument claims, that a certain amount of evil is necessary in the world for good souls to grow. Then while God could have prevented this evil or that evil, he would then have had to allow some other evil to occur, or there would not be enough total evil in the world for us to grow spiritually. Second, how can this be the best of all possible worlds given the amount of suffering of animals, which does neither them nor us any good? One response is that for us to exist, given the laws of nature, many other sentient animals needed to exist as well. We have evolved from them, and we cannot know that if God had created a world without animals or a world in which animals didn’t suffer (but we did – how??), that this would be a better world.Finally, for this to justify evil, we must suppose that no alternative set of natural laws could lead to less natural evil. But this seems hard to believe. Is it impossible that there are no droughts? Is it impossible that animals all eat plants rather than each other? Is it impossible that cancer didn’t exist? Surely there could be natural laws that meant these things never happened; and a good God would choose those laws that didn’t lead to natural evil. The standard for ‘best possible world’The problem of evil takes the happiness of creatures on Earth as the standard for judging whether the world could be better. But we can’t take the happiness of human beings (and other animals we know about) as the standard for whether the universe is the best possible world. Suppose, for example, we expanded it just to ‘the happiness of all beings capable of happiness and suffering’. We don’t know what other beings exist in the universe, we don’t know what supernatural beings, such as angels, exist as well. It might be that our unhappiness on Earth is very small in comparison with their happiness, and that to try to remove our unhappiness would lead to greater unhappiness overall.Perhaps we can’t know that this isn’t the best of all possible worlds. We could still object that we have no good reason to think that it is the best of all possible worlds, and we have very good reason to think that it isn’t. The afterlifeAnother theodicy takes a completely different approach. It doesn’t try to justify the evil that exists in this life by other aspects of this life (free will, spiritual growth, etc.). Instead, it appeals to an ‘afterlife’. The idea is that if you suffer unjustly in this life, God will make it up to you in the next life. On balance, everyone will get what they deserve in the end.This argument has not been popular with philosophers. The difficulty is that it does not offer a moral justification for evil. For example, if I hit you and then give you ?20, was it alright for me to hit you? Would it be alright if I gave you ?1000? No, there is just something wrong with this way of thinking. At best, the money is compensation for something I did wrong, it does not justify what I did. The same applies to thinking about evil. If God rewards those who deserve it by eternal life in heaven, this is at best a compensation for the unjust suffering they experienced in life. It does not make it morally good or justifiable that they suffered. A loving God would not act this way. Furthermore, if we want to bring about something good, but know that it will harm someone innocent as a result, we should at least ask their permission. If they consent, then perhaps the act and the compensation we offer is morally justified. They have agreed with our plan, and accept the consequences. But to go ahead without informing or asking them is to use them as a means to our end. If God has brought about a world in which evil is unfairly distributed, but this is necessary for some greater good, God has used people as a means to that end – even if they receive compensation in the afterlife.At best, the afterlife might make us care less about the evil we suffer. But it cannot seem to offer a moral justification for how an all-good God could allow such evil in the first place. ................
................
In order to avoid copyright disputes, this page is only a partial summary.
To fulfill the demand for quickly locating and searching documents.
It is intelligent file search solution for home and business.
Related download
- the problem of evil and suffering a worldview analysis
- a priori intuition and demonstration
- the problem of evil kansas state university
- a priori intuition and demonstration a level philosophy
- the problem of evil and its solution
- a level philosophy religious studies
- the problem of evil and theodicy philosophy 1
- com
Related searches
- reading a z username and password 2019
- get a loan quick and easy
- after a heart attack and stent
- a person strengths and weaknesses
- qualities of a good husband and father
- what is a unit rate and examples
- what is a red moon and deer
- a z diseases and conditions
- fp a interview questions and answers
- a person weakness and strengths
- make a certificate online and print free
- write a letter online and print it